Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-sxzjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T04:02:41.772Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Hasty Retreat From Evidence: The Recalcitrance of Relativism in Feminist Epistemology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 March 2020

Abstract

While feminist epistemologists have made important contributions to the deconstruction of the traditional representationalist model, some elements of the Cartesian legacy remain. For example, relativism continues to play a role in the underdetermination thesis used by Longino and Keller. Both argue that because scientific theories are underdetermined by evidence, theory choice must be relative to interpretive frameworks. Utilizing Davidson's philosophy of language, I offer a nonrepresentationalist alternative to suggest how relativism can be more fully avoided.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1998 by Hypatia, Inc.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alcoff, Linda Martín. 1996. Real knowing: New versions of the coherence theory. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Barad, Karen 1997. Meeting the universe halfway: Realism and social constructivism without contradiction. In Feminism, science and the philosophy of science, ed. Hankinson Nelson, Lynn and Nelson, Jack. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Bergstrom, Lars 1993. Quine, underdetermination, and skepticism. The Journal of Philosophy 90 (7): 331–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Code, Lorraine 1991. What can she know? Feminist theory and the construction of knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1984. On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. In Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1989a. The myth of the subjective. In Relativism: Interpretations and confrontations, ed. Krausz, Michael. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1989b. The conditions of thought. In The mind of Donald Davidson, ed. Brands, Johannes and Gombocz, Wolfgang. Grazer Philosophische Studien, no. 36. Amsterdam: Editions Rodopoi.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1990. The structure and content of truth. The Journal of Philosophy 87 (6): 279328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald [1986] 1991a. A coherence theory of truth and knowledge. Reprinted in Reading Rorty: Critical responses to philosophy and the mirror of nature (and beyond), ed. Alan Malachowski. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1991b. Epistemology externalized. Diaelctica 45 (2‐3): 191202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nietzsche, Friedrich 1991c. Three varieties of knowledge. In A.J. Ayer memorial essays, ed. Phillips Griffiths, A.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Doell, Ruth, and Longino, Helen 1988. Sex hormones and human behavior: A critique of the linear model. Journal of Homosexuality 15 (3/4): 5579.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harding, Sandra 1991. Whose science? Whose knowledge? Thinking from women's lives. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Harding, Sandra 1993. Rethinking standpoint epistemology: What is “strong objectivity?” In Feminist epistemologies, ed. Alcoff, Linda and Potter, Elizabeth. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. 1965. Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Keller, Evelyn Fox 1992a. Introduction to Secrets of life, secrets of death: Essays on language, gender and science. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, Friedrich 1992b. Gender and science: An update. In Secrets of life, secrets of death: Essays on language, gender and science. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, Friedrich 1992c. Critical silences in scientific discourse. In Secrets of life, secrets of death: Essays on language, gender and science. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas 1972. The structure of scientific revolutions, 2d ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, C.I. [1929] 1956. Mind and the world order, republication of 1st ed. with corrections. New York: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
Lloyd, Elisabeth. 1997. Science and anti‐science: Objectivity and its real enemies. In Feminism, science and the philosophy of science, ed. Hankinson Nelson, Lynn and Nelson, Jack. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen 1987. Can there be a feminist science? Hypatia 2 (3): 5164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen 1990. Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Malpas, , Jeffrey, E. 1992. Donald Davidson and the mirror of meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nelson, Lynn Hankinson 1990. Who knows: From Quine to a feminist empiricism. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Nelson, Lynn Hankinson 1993. A question of evidence. Hypatia 2 (8): 172189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niiniluoto, Ilkka 1997. The relativism question in feminist epistemology. In Feminism, science and the philosophy of science, ed. Hankinson Nelson, Lynn and Nelson, Jack. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Willard Van Orman, Quine 1960. Word and object. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, Friedrich 1969. “Ontalogical relativity” and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, Friedrich 1981. Empirical content. In Theories and things. Cambridge: The Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Ramberg, Bjørn. 1989. Donald Davidson's philosophy of language: An introduction. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard 1991. Philosophical papers. Vol. 1, Objectivity, relativism, and truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Van Fraassen, Bas. 1980. The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar