Skip to main content
Log in

Enactive Affectivity, Extended

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I advance an enactive view of affectivity that does not imply that affectivity must stop at the boundaries of the organism. I first review the enactive notion of “sense-making”, and argue that it entails that cognition is inherently affective. Then I review the proposal, advanced by Di Paolo (Topoi 28:9–21, 2009), that the enactive approach allows living systems to “extend”. Drawing out the implications of this proposal, I argue that, if enactivism allows living systems to extend, then it must also allow sense-making, and thus cognition as well as affectivity, to extend—in the specific sense of allowing the physical processes (vehicles) underpinning these phenomena to include, as constitutive parts, non-organic environmental processes. Finally I suggest that enactivism might also allow specific human affective states, such as moods, to extend.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are different versions of both internalism and externalism (see Hurley 2010). In this paper I am concerned only with “vehicle” internalism/externalism (as opposed to “content” internalism/externalism), which is about the location of the material vehicles taken to underpin mental states. I also adopt a relatively broad characterization of internalism, according to which vehicles outside the brain but within the organism still count as internal (whereas sometimes internalism is limited to the view that the vehicles of mental states are “brainbound”, i.e., remain within the brain).

  2. In recent years, the term “enactivism” has come to refer to a variety of related but different approaches—such as Noë’s (2004) “dynamic sensorimotor approach”, and Hutto and Myin’s (2013) “radical enactivism”. For the purposes of this paper I focus on the canonical version of enactivism, and in particular on its account of the relationship between life and mind.

  3. For different ways of challenging this view, see Stephan, Walter and Wilutzky (2014) and Colombetti and Roberts (2015) on how HEC can be applied to the affective domain.

  4. In what follows I summarize my own viewpoint (see Colombetti 2010, 2014). Other relevant discussions can be found in Varela and Depraz (2005) and Thompson (2007, chapter 12). Not much otherwise has been written about affectivity from an enactive perspective.

  5. Thompson and Stapleton (2009) and Di Paolo and Thompson (2014) also provide useful succinct introductions. For the full treatment, see Thompson (2007).

  6. It is thus not exact to call this strand of enactivism “autopoietic”, as Hutto and Myin (2013) do. Note also that the theory of autopoiesis does not feature in Varela et al. (1991).

  7. The term “Umwelt” as is used here comes from Jacob von Uexküll (1934/2010), where it refers to the world from the perspective of living organisms that inhabit it, or their “lived environment”. Uexküll distinguished between Umwelt and Umgebung, where the latter refers to the physical surroundings of the organism. Varela (1991) draws a parallel distinction between the “world” that is enacted or brought forth by the organism in sense-making, and the physiochemical “environment” in which the organism is situated. In this and other earlier works, Varela used the term “world-making” (rather than “sense-making”) to refer to the process of enacting a world of meaning.

  8. The qualification “basic” (Thompson 2011: 211; Di Paolo and Thompson 2014: 73) is meant to allow for the appearance of more complex forms of cognition in more complex organisms, including forms of human cognition dependent on organisms being situated in cultural symbolic contexts.

  9. Jonas (1966: 99) talked of the irritability of life to refer to its “sensitiveness to the stimulus”, and wrote that “irritability is the germ, as it were the atom, of having a world”.

  10. Radical enactivists (Hutto and Myin 2013) do reject the notion of “vehicles” of cognition, together with the one of “content”, because they see both notions as going hand-in-hand with computational-representationalist accounts of cognition. However, it is not clear that canonical enactivism needs to reject all talk of vehicles and contents. This is a point that promoters of canonical enactivism will need to clarify in the future. Here I only note that Thompson (2007: 59) seems willing to talk of “vehicles” in the sense of “the structures or processes that embody meaning”, provided we keep in mind that these are “temporally extended patterns of activity that can crisscross the brain-body-world boundaries, and the meanings or contents they embody are brought forth or enacted in the context of the system’s structural coupling with its environment”.

  11. There are several species of aquatic insects, commonly called “water boatmen”, that use this or other similar underwater respiration methods. Di Paolo refers to Thorpe’s (1950) study, which described amongst others the genus Aphelocheirus, which apparently has perfected this system of respiration.

  12. Equivalent notions can be found in Tolman (1932), Uexküll (1934/2010) and Koffka (1935).

  13. Gibson (1979) mentions Lewin’s notion of demand character as a precursor of his notion of affordances, but also emphasizes a main difference between the two: unlike Lewin’s demand characters, Gibson’s affordances do not depend on the organism’s needs (op. cit., 129–131). Relatedly, Gibson also claims that affordances should be characterized in terms of behaviour and biology, rather than experience or phenomenology. I think this claim is problematic, although I shall not develop this point here. See also Dreyfus and Kelly (2007) for a phenomenological take on affordances.

  14. Some readers will find this constitutive claim counterintuitive. One referee queried why I did not settle for the “more intuitive” view that the air bubbles causally support, or scaffold, both living and affective processes (but are not themselves part of the living system). The answer is that it is not the goal of this paper to settle the causal-constitution debate. This paper is structured so as to draw out logically (what I think are) the implications of the enactive approach for the material underpinnings of affectivity. As explained in the previous section, I think that enactivism’s characterization of life entails that living systems can extend, i.e., that appropriately integrated mediating structures can be part of living systems. My further point in this and the next section is that, if enactivism entails that life extends, then it also entails that affectivity extends. Personally, I do not find these claims counterintuitive, but in any case intuitions should not matter here, because in this paper the constitutive claims are derived logically as implications of enactivism’s characterization of life and sense-making. In other words, the arguments of this paper should be construed as a conditional: given enactivism’s account of life and cognition, it follows that affectivity can extend.

  15. For related discussions of this example, see Colombetti and Roberts (2015) and Roberts (2015).

  16. See also Zahavi (2011) for related questions about the role of phenomenology in enactivism, and its relation to natural science.

References

  • Clark A (2003) Natural-born cyborgs: minds, technologies and the future of human intelligence. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2008) Supersizing the mind: embodiment, action and cognitive extension. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A, Chalmers D (1998) The extended mind. Analysis 58:7–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cochrane T (2008) Expression and extended cognition. J Aesthet Art Crit 66(4):329–340

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti G (2005) Appraising valence. J Conscious Stud 12(8–10):103–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti G (2014) The feeling body: affective science meets the enactive mind. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti G, Roberts T (2015) Extending the extended mind: the case for extended affectivity. Philos Stud 172(5):1243–1263

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio AR (1999) The feeling of what happens: body, emotion and the making of consciousness. Vintage, London

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher H, Di Paolo EA (2007) Participatory sense-making: an enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenol Cognit Sci 6:485–507

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Preester H, Tsakiris M (2009) Body-extension versus body-incorporation: is there a need for a body-model? Phenomenol Cognit Sci 8(3):307–319

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo EA (2005) Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenol Cognit Sci 4:429–452

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo EA (2009) Extended life. Topoi 28(1):9–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo EA, Thompson E (2014) The enactive approach. In: Shapiro LA (ed) The routledge handbook of embodied cognition. Routledge, Oxon, pp 69–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus H, Kelly SD (2007) Heterophenomenology: heavy-handed sleight-of-hand. Phenomenol Cognit Sci 6(1–2):45–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J, O’Malley MA (2009) Varieties of living things: life at the intersection of lineage and metabolism. Philos Theory Biol 1:e003

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson JJ (1979) The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton, Mifflin and Company, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley S (2010) The varieties of externalism. In: Menary R (ed) The extended mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 101–153

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto DD, Myin E (2013) Radicalizing enactivism: basic minds without content. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1884) What is an emotion? Mind 9:188–205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas H (1966) The phenomenon of life: toward a philosophical biology. Northwestern University Press, Evanston

    Google Scholar 

  • Koffka K (1935) Principles of gestalt psychology. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger J (2013) Merleau-Ponty on shared emotions and the joint ownership thesis. Cont Philos Rev 46:509–531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewin K (1935) A dynamic theory of personality: selected papers. (Trans: Adams DK, Zener KE). McGraw-Hill, New York

  • Lewis MD (2000) Emotional organization at three time scales. In: Lewis MD, Granic I (eds) Emotion, development, and self-organization: dynamic systems approaches to emotional development. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 37–69

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1980) Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. D. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Menary R (ed) (2010) The extended mind. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1945/2012) Phenomenology of perception. (Trans Landes DA). New York: Routledge

  • Noë A (2004) Action in perception. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum MC (2004) Emotions as judgments of value and importance. In: Solomon RC (ed) Thinking about feeling: contemporary philosophers on emotions. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 183–199

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz JJ (2004) Gut feelings: a perceptual theory of emotion. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe M (2010) The phenomenology of mood and the meaning of life. In: Goldie P (ed) The Oxford handbook of philosophy of emotion. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 349–371

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts T (2015) Extending emotional consciousness. J Conscious Stud 22(3–4):108–128

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon RC (1993) The passions: emotions and the meaning of life (2nd revised), edition edn. Hackett, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephan A, Walter S, Wilutzky W (2014) Emotions beyond brain and body. Philos Psychol 27(1):98–111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson E (2007) Mind in life: biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson E (2011) Reply to commentaries. J Conscious Stud 18(5–6):176–223

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson E, Stapleton M (2009) Making sense of sense-making: reflections on enactive and extended mind theories. Topoi 28(1):23–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson E, Zahavi D (2007) Philosophical issues: continental phenomenology. In: Zelazo PD, Moscovitch M, Thompson E (eds) The cambridge handbook of consciousness. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 67–88

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thorpe WH (1950) Plastron respiration in aquatic insects. Biol Rev 25:344–390

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tolman EC (1932) Purposive behavior in animals and men. Appleton-Century, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Uexküll von J (1934) A foray into the worlds of animals and humans. with a theory of meaning. (Trans: O’Neil JD). University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis and London

  • Varela FJ (1979) Principles of Biological autonomy. Elsevier, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela FJ (1991) Organism: a meshwork of selfless selves. In Tauber AI (ed) Organism and the origin of the self. Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp 79–107

  • Varela FJ, Depraz N (2005) At the source of time—valence and the constitutional dynamics of affect. J Conscious Stud 12:61–81

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela FJ, Thompson E, Rosch E (1991) The embodied mind: cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber A, Varela FJ (2002) Life after Kant: natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenol Cognit Sci 1(2):97–125

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler M (2010) Minds, things and materiality. In: Malafouris L, Renfrew C (eds) The cognitive life of things: recasting the boundaries of the mind. McDonald Institute for Archaeological Research, Cambridge, pp 29–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Withagen R, de Poel HJ, Araújo D, Pepping G-J (2012) Affordances can invite behavior: reconsidering the relationship between affordances and agency. New Ideas Psychol 30(2):250–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2011) Mutual enlightenment and transcendental thought. J Conscious Stud 18(5–6):169–175

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to participants of the AISB 2014 symposium on enactivism, and to Ezequiel Di Paolo, Tom Roberts, and two anonymous referees for their comments on early versions of this paper. Any remaining misunderstanding is entirely my responsibility. This work was partially supported by the European Research Council under the European Community’s Seventh Framework Programme (FP7/2007–2013), project title “Emoting the Embodied Mind” (EMOTER), ERC Grant agreement 240891.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Giovanna Colombetti.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Colombetti, G. Enactive Affectivity, Extended. Topoi 36, 445–455 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-015-9335-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-015-9335-2

Keywords

Navigation