Skip to main content
Log in

Transmuted Expertise: How Technical Non-Experts Can Assess Experts and Expertise

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

To become an expert in a technical domain means acquiring the tacit knowledge pertaining to the relevant domain of expertise, at least, according to the programme known as “Studies of Expertise and Experience” (SEE). We know only one way to acquire tacit knowledge and that is through some form of sustained social contact with the group that has it. Those who do not have such contact cannot acquire the expertise needed to make technical judgments. They can, however, use social expertise to judge between experts or expert claims. Where social expertise is used to make technical judgments we refer to it as “transmuted expertise”. The various kinds of transmuted expertise are described and analysed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Walton’s (1997) excellent historical overview reminds us that philosophers have tried to deal with the problem as to how non-experts can make sense of expert arguments and accounts for more than two millennia.

  2. We are grateful to the Gabor Kutrovátz and Gabor Zemplen for pointing out to us that our Table 2 bears strong resemblance to Douglas Walton’s “6 critical questions” (Walton 1997: 223, see also Gelfert and Wagemans in this issue). As Goodwin (in this issue) observes, there is a great deal of overlap between SEE and work in argumentation studies though, as pointed out above, there are also differences.

  3. See Collins (1999) for a similar argument in respect of the rejection of claims about the existence of gravitational waves.

  4. See Selinger et al. (2011) for a debate about this point.

  5. While we rely mainly on detailed research by Boyce (2007), the case is discussed in detail in Tindale’s paper in this issue.

  6. This reflection on the relationship between sociology of scientific knowledge and transmuted expertise was initiated by Martin Weinel as part of his PhD project at Cardiff (Weinel 2011).

  7. The empirical proof of this point within science studies actually goes back to 1975 if not further.

  8. To know whether some phenomenon, “thargs”, exist one has to build a competent tharg detector. But to know whether a tharg detector is competent one has to examine its performance in the detection thargs. But to know whether its performance is competent one has to know whether or not it should find thargs when it is working properly. To know this one has to know whether or not thargs exist. But to know this one has to build a competent tharg detector. And so on.

  9. The idea is that those with expertise in science studies ought to have a well established “understanding how science works” or some a well-developed “intelligence regarding science” (Kutrovátz 2010). It is not only professional sociologists who exercise such skills. For example, Lee Smolin’s (2006) critique of the current state of string theory is based on observation of its social development.

  10. For example, there are continuing disputes in physics over the foundations of special relativity and the foundations of quantum theory but nearly all physicists simply ignore them; were they not to do so they would not be able to get on with their scientific lives.

  11. The events are reported at greater length in Collins (2004: 366–367).

  12. Shwed and Bearman’s (2010) approach to recognising and temporarily tracing genuine scientific controversies shows that a purely quantitative approach might work. It also demonstrates that quantitative analysts do not need to have specialist expertises in the fields under consideration. A less complicated, but equally effective approach has been employed by Collins and Pinch (1998[1993]) in their analysis of the “cold-fusion controversy”.

  13. The existence of outlets for fringe scientific opinions is not bad in itself as some scientists involved in disputes with so-called “AIDS sceptics” correctly argue (see for example Nattrass 2010); such journals are important for a lively and open science. The existence of fringe journals only becomes a problem when outsiders involved in policy decisions fail to understand what they are. Mbeki, for example, described Current Medical Research and Opinion as “very senior” (Robertson et al. 2000).

References

  • Boyce, T. 2007. Health, risk and news: The MMR vaccine and the media. New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cherry, M. 2009. The president’s panel. In The virus, vitamins & vegetables: The South African HIV/AIDS mystery, ed. K. Cullinan and A. Thom, 16–35. Johannesburg: Jacana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H.M. 1988. Public experiments and displays of virtuosity: The core-set revisited. Social Studies of Science 18(4): 725–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins H.M. 1992[1985]. Changing order: Replication and induction in scientific practice. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Collins, H.M. 1999. Tantalus and the aliens: Publications, audiences and the search for gravitational waves. Social Studies of Science 29(2): 163–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H.M. 2004. Gravity’s shadow: The search for gravitational waves. Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H.M. 2010. Tacit and explicit knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H.M., and R.J. Evans. 2007. Rethinking expertise. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H.M., and T.J. Pinch. 1998[1993]. The golem: What everyone should know about science. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Collins, H.M., M. Weinel, and R.J. Evans. 2010. The politics and policy of the third wave: New technologies and society. Critical Policy Studies 4(2): 185–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldacre, B. 2008. Bad science. London: Fourth Estate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. 2001. Experts: Which ones should you trust? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63(1): 85–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalichman, S. 2009. How to spot an AIDS denialist? New Humanist 124(6). http://newhumanist.org.uk/2165/how-to-spot-an-aids-denialist. Accessed 7 June 2011.

  • Krimsky, S. 1984. Epistemic considerations on the value of folk wisdom in science and technology. Policy Studies Review 3(2): 246–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kutrovátz, G. 2010. Trust in experts: Contextual patterns of warranted epistemic dependence. Balkan Journal of Philosophy 2(1): 57–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mbeki, T. 1999. Address of President Mbeki, at the National Council of Provinces. http://www.info.gov.za/speeches/1999/991028409p1004.htm. Accessed 6 June 2011.

  • Nattrass, N. 2007. Mortal combat: AIDS Denialism and the struggle for antiretrovirals in South Africa. Scottsville: University of KwaZulu Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nattrass, N. 2010. Still crazy after all those years: The challenge of AIDS denialism for science. AIDS and Behavior 14(2): 248–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, H., R. Hartley, and C. Paton. 2000. Face to face with the President: Sunday times interview with President Mbeki. Sunday Times February 6.

  • Scott, D., and A. Leonov. 2004. Two sides of the moon: Our story of the cold war space race. London: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selinger, E., P. Thompson, and H.M. Collins. 2011. Catastrophe ethics and activist speech: Reflections on moral norms, advocacy, and technical judgment. Metaphilosophy 42(1/2): 118–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shwed, U., and P.S. Bearman. 2010. The temporal structure of scientific consensus formation. American Sociological Review 75(6): 817–840.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smolin, L. 2006. The trouble with physics: The rise of string theory, the fall of a science, and what comes next. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. 1997. Appeal to expert opinion: Arguments from authority. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinel, M. 2008. Counterfeit scientific controversies in science policy contexts. Cardiff School of Social Sciences Working Paper, no. 120. Cardiff: Cardiff school of social sciences.

  • Weinel, M. 2009. Thabo Mbeki, HIV/AIDS and bogus scientific controversies. Politicsweb 19 March. http://www.politicsweb.co.za/politicsweb/view/politicsweb/en/page71619?oid=121968&sn=Detail. (Accessed 6 June 2011).

  • Weinel, M. 2011. Technological decision-making under scientific uncertainty: Preventing mother-to-child transmission of HIV in South Africa. PhD Thesis. Cardiff: Cardiff School of Social Sciences.

  • Wynne, B. 1989. Sheepfarming after Chernobyl: A case study in communicating scientific information. Environment 31(2): 10–15, 33–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynne, B. 1992. Misunderstood misunderstanding: Social identities and public uptake of science. Public Understanding of Science 1(3): 281–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to Rob Evans as well as the reviewers for exceptionally useful comments on this text.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Martin Weinel.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Collins, H., Weinel, M. Transmuted Expertise: How Technical Non-Experts Can Assess Experts and Expertise. Argumentation 25, 401–413 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-011-9217-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-011-9217-8

Keywords

Navigation