Skip to main content
Log in

Description-Names

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is argued that, contrary to appearances, description-names (e.g.: “The Roman Empire”, “The Beatles”, “The Holy Virgin”,...) do conform to Millianism, i.e. the view that proper names are directly referential expressions, referring regardless of whether the relevant individual satisfies some associated description or not. However, description-names name and describe. Some arguments supporting this peculiarity and a logic to handle description-names are proposed. It will be shown that the best framework with which to accommodate description-names is a multiple-proposition theory, according to which a given utterance may express several propositions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

REFERENCES

  • Bach, K.: 1999, The myth of conventional implicature, Linguistics and Philosophy 22, 327-366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barcan Marcus, R.: 1975, Does the principle of substitutivity rest on a mistake, in A. R. Anderson, R. M. Martin and R. B. Marcus (eds.), The Logical Enterprise, Yale University Press, New Haven, pp. 31-38. Reprinted in R. B. Marcus (ed.), Modalities, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 101-109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dever, J.: 2001, Complex demonstratives, Linguistics and Philosophy 24(3), 271-330.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K.: 1966, Reference and definite descriptions, The Philosophical Review 75, 281-304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M.: 1973, Frege: Philosophy of Language, 2nd edn 1981, Duckworth, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G.: 1977, Pronouns, quantifiers, and relative clauses (I), Canad. J. Philos. 7(3), 467-536. Reprint in G. Evans (ed.), Collected Papers, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1985, pp. 76-152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G.: 1982, The Varieties of Reference, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiengo, R. and May, R.: 1994, Indices and Identity, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P.: 1962, Reference and Generality, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P.: 1989, Studies in the Way of Words, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D.: 1978, Dthat, in P. Yourgrau (ed.), Demonstratives, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1990, pp. 11-33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D.: 1989, Afterthoughts, in, J. Almog, J. Perry and H. Wettstein (eds.), Themes from Kaplan, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 565-614.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S.: 1980, Naming and Necessity, B. Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larson, R. and Segal, G.: 1995, Knowledge of Meaning, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neale, S.: 1999, Coloring and composition, in K. Murasugi and R. Stainton (eds.), Philosophy and Linguistics, Westview Press, Boulder, CO, pp. 35-82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J.: 1988, Cognitive significance and new theories of reference, Noûs 22, 1-18, reprinted in J. Perry (ed.), The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays, CSLI Publications, Stanford, CA, 2000, pp. 189-206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J.: 2001, Reference and Reflexivity, CSLI Publications, Stanford, CA.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Corazza, E. Description-Names. Journal of Philosophical Logic 31, 313–325 (2002). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1019950905478

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1019950905478

Navigation