Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

European Health Systems and the Internal Market: Reshaping Ideology?

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Health Care Analysis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Departing from theories of distributive justice and their relation with the distribution of health care within society, especially egalitarianism and libertarianism, this paper aims at demonstrating that the approach taken by the European Court of Justice regarding the application of the Internal Market principles (or the market freedoms) to the field of health care services has introduced new values which are more concerned with a libertarian view of health care. Moreover, the paper also addresses the question of how these new values introduced by the Court may affect common principles of European health systems, such as equity and accessibility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Barak-Erez and Gross [5].

  2. International Conference on Primary Health Care, Alma-Ata, USSR, 6–12 September 1978.

  3. Ruger [47].

  4. Williams [55, p. 292].

  5. The most common typology used to distinguish the different models of welfare state is the one proposed by Esping–Andersen. He laid out three main types of welfare states, in which modern developed capitalist nations cluster: the liberal, the conservative and the social democratic. The differences between these models are centered in the relation between the private and public sectors in the provision of social services, in the level of decommodification of social services goods and in the social structure. Although, in practice, welfare states are not designed according to his typology, the traditional examples of the three types of welfare states he proposes are the United States (liberal), Germany (conservative) and Sweden (social democratic) [20].

  6. Lamping [39, p. 20].

  7. De Búrca [16, p. 11].

  8. Most studies of equity in the delivery of health care start from the premise that health care ought to be distributed according to need rather than ability to pay [54, p. 9].

  9. See for example, Case C-120/95 Decker; Case C-158/96 Kohll; Case C-368/98 Vanbraekel; Case C-157/99 Smits and Peerbooms; Case C-385/99 Müller-Fauré; and Case C-372/04 Watts.

  10. Commission of the European Communities [12].

  11. See for example, Dougan and Spaventa [18].

  12. Council of the European Union [14].

  13. World Health Organization [57, p. 4]. Date accessed 12 February 2010, http://www.who.int/whr/2000/en/whr00_en.pdf.

  14. In effect, other social determinants of health, such as sanitation, income and education are more effective in improving health indicators [6].

  15. Rawls [46].

  16. Sen [51].

  17. Anand et al. [1, p. 17].

  18. Hurley [29, p. 308].

  19. “Justice concerned with the relation between persons and especially with the fairness in the exchange of goods and the fulfilment of contractual obligations” [7, p. 942].

  20. Ibid.

  21. See for example, Stanton-Ife [52, p. 17].

  22. Utilitarianism is also important as a theory of distributive justice. Classical utilitarianism is based on the work of Jeremy Benthan and John Stuart Mill who believed that pleasure promotion and pain avoidance could be measured cardinally. Therefore, this theory supports that individual action is adequate when it maximises pleasure and well-being and minimises pain. Although utilitarianism is used in the field of health care, it is usually associated with some special feature of the health system, as for example applied in specific areas of the system, such as health care planning and priority setting, and not as a general ideology to justify the moral basis of the health system. This is the reason why it will not be considered separately in this work.

  23. Olsen [45].

  24. Arneson [3]. Date accessed 12 February 2010, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/egalitarianism/.

  25. See for example, Arneson [2] and Cohen [11].

  26. Daniels [15, p. 57].

  27. Gulliford et al. [26].

  28. Supra n. 21, p. 9.

  29. The communitarian movement gained expression during the 1980s as a critical philosophical movement against libertarianism. By defending the idea that communitarianism is the politics of the common good as opposed to the politics of rights diffused by liberalism, communitarian philosophers have sought to move ethics away from individual rights and universal rules toward theories which give moral importance to the community and the social good.

  30. Mooney and Houston [41].

  31. Wiseman [56].

  32. For matters of ideology and ethics, public health systems which provide universal access to health care tend to use the egalitarian ideology as the basis for their policies. However, even countries that do not use this ideology as a general policy supporting the whole system, have egalitarian concerns to develop some specific policies. This is the case, for example, of the Medicaid and Medicare in the United States, which are health care programmes specially designed for the poor and the elderly, respectively.

  33. “The overarching values of universality, access to good quality care, equity, and solidarity have been widely accepted in the work of the different EU institutions. Together they constitute a set of values that are shared across Europe. Universality means that no-one is barred access to health care; solidarity is closely linked to the financial arrangement of our national health systems and the need to ensure accessibility to all; equity relates to equal access according to need, regardless of ethnicity, gender, age, social status or ability to pay. EU health systems also aim to reduce the gap in health inequalities, which is a concern of EU Member States;[…]” Supra n. 12, p. 3.

  34. Jepsen and Pascual [30].

  35. Supra n. 14, p. 190.

  36. Sandel [49, p. 13].

  37. Nozick [44, pp. 138–139].

  38. According to this model, health care cannot be considered the chief among all goods (the ‘insulation’ model of health care) because in this case it would require society to spend all its resources on health care. He also refuses the idea of need, arguing that it is a philosophically controversial idea. By imagining a society where there is fair equality in the distribution of resources, where people in general know about the costs and value of medical procedures, and health care is not provided by the government, he proposes, then, that whatever this society spends as its total health-care budget and however it distributes health care would be a just distribution of health care for that society [19].

  39. Although the American system underwent some changes due to the health reform recently approved, which aims, inter alia, to increase the number of people with health insurance coverage by creating a new insurance marketplace that allows people without insurance and small businesses to compare plans and buy insurance at competitive prices, and by offering a public health insurance option to provide the uninsured who cannot find affordable coverage with a real choice, the reform is not intended to change the market-oriented logic of the system. For detailed information, see the reports on the Obama Plan. Date accessed 14 February 2010, http://www.healthreform.gov/reports/index.html.

  40. Freeman and Moran [24, p. 36].

  41. Santos [50, p. 21].

  42. Callahan and Wasunna [9, p. 9].

  43. Ibid. p. 112.

  44. Toth [53].

  45. As Freeman and Moran explain “By 1975, in France, Germany and Sweden, public spending on health absorbed more than twice the proportion of GDP it had in 1960: in Italy, health spending had grown by more than two-thirds and in the UK by more than half.” Supra n. 40, p. 37.

  46. Supra n. 40.

  47. See for example [21].

  48. Saltman [48]. Available at http://www.euro.who.int/observatory/Studies/20021223_2, Date accessed 22 March 2010.

  49. For example, Article 20 paragraph 1 of the German Basic Law characterises Germany as a ‘social federal state’. In economic terms, this idea is associated with a ‘social market economy’, an expression invented by the German Professor of Economics Alfred Müller Armak, which presented in an article of 1948 the ‘social market economy’ as a third way between ‘laissez-faire liberalism and ‘planned economy’ with the threat of socialisation [32, p. 139].

  50. Brown and Amelung [8].

  51. The use of private insurance combined with private (often for-profit) providers. According to this model, insurance can be mandatory, as in Switzerland, or voluntary, as in the United States, and in the case of the latter, affordable insurance may not be available to some individuals [17, p. 10].

  52. Esping–Andersen refers to this term as the “process by which both human needs and labor power became commodities and, hence, our well-being came to depend on our relation to the cash nexus.” Supra n 5, p. 35.

  53. Jost et al. [33].

  54. Joerges [31].

  55. Koivusalo [36].

  56. Ferrera [22, p. 11].

  57. Cornelissen [13].

  58. Mossialos et al. [42, p. 83].

  59. See Regulation 859/2003.

  60. Hervey and McHale [28, p. 113].

  61. This includes: pensioners entitled to a pension and their families; nationals of a Member State and their families not currently employed and looking for a job in another Member State; employed or self-employed persons exercising their professional activity in another Member State; frontier workers; students and those undertaking professional training and their families.

  62. This mechanism is put in practice through the use of the European health insurance card, which ensures that the person will get the same access to public sector health care (e.g., a doctor, a pharmacy, a hospital or a health care centre) as nationals of the country he/she is visiting.

  63. Although Regulation 1408/71 provides for mechanisms which allow the free movement of people, including planned health care abroad, the control over these mechanisms still confers wide discretion to Member States. This discretion is, indeed, found in the wording of Article 168(7) of the TFEU) which, in theory, provides for the application of the principle of subsidiarity, explicitly preserving Member States’ competence in the organisation and delivery of health services and medical care.

  64. At the present moment, with the enter into force of the Lisbon Treaty, European citizenship is mentioned in Articles 9, 18 and 20 of the TFEU.

  65. Ibid. p. 168.

  66. In this regard, Majone proposes a distinction in relation to the social policies developed at European level, distinguishing them in policies of regulatory nature and those of non-regulatory nature The social policies of regulatory nature are those developed by the European Union based on the freedom of movement and aiming at implementing the Internal Market. They do not have a redistributive nature and are motivated by an efficiency criterion, having only indirect redistributive consequences. The second category of social policies is represented by those policies which really have redistributive objectives. These policies aim at reducing inequalities between the different countries and regions, and foment social cohesion within the Union, and they are promoted through the different Structural and Cohesion Funds of the European Union. Rights promoted through these funds are much vaguer and, although redistributive in nature, they are minimum in comparison to national social policies [40].

  67. Kandil [35, p. 160].

  68. Supra n 66.

  69. Clarke et al. [10].

  70. Kostakopoulou [38]. It must be noted, however, that this author, although describing different models for the European citizenship, including the market model, does not support the idea that the market citizenship is the one pursued by the EU.

  71. Flear [23].

  72. Kaczorowska [34].

  73. In this regard, in Watts (Paragraph 86) the Court pointed out that “It should be noted in that regard that, according to settled case-law, medical services provided for consideration fall within the scope of the provisions on the freedom to provide services (see inter alia, Case C-159/90 Society for the Protection of Unborn Children Ireland [1991] ECR I-4685, paragraph 18, and Kohll, paragraph 29), there being no need to distinguish between care provided in a hospital environment and care provided outside such an environment (Vanbraekel, paragraph 41; Smits and Peerbooms, paragraph 53; Müller-Fauré and van Riet, paragraph 38; and Inizan, paragraph 16)”.

  74. Even if the Court recognises the special nature of health services as a social security benefit, according to its view this assumption does not place these services beyond the scope of the Union rules on free movement. See for example, Kohll, paragraph 20 and Smits and Peerbooms, paragraph 54.

  75. Koivusalo [36].

  76. Non-economic services are those which are prerogatives of the State, such as national education and compulsory basic social security schemes. See the Green paper on services of general interest. Commission of the European Communities. 2003. COM (2003) 270, p. 15.

  77. One of the main critics concerning the inclusion of health services in the services directive was that the underling concept of the proposal was a simply relationship between a consumer and a provider and health services, however, form part of complex systems, involving also a third party, which pays the major part of the bill. See R. Baeten, “The potential impact of the services directive on health services”, in: P. Nihoul and A.C. Simon (eds.) L'Europe et les soins de santé: marché intérieur, sécurité sociale, concurrence (Bruxelles: Larcier, 2005).

  78. In its meeting on 2 December 2009, the Council failed to reach an agreement on the Patients’s Rights Directive, therefore it has not been approved yet. Date accessed 25 April 2010, http://register.consilium.europa.eu/pdf/en/09/st16/st16005.en09.pdf.

  79. For comments on the proposal, see [4].

  80. As Baeten argues, “a general ‘clean-up’, had been carried out in order to eliminate any notion of ‘health services from the text. Instead, the provisions were presented under the heading of ‘patients’ rights’. This general tyding up did however not concern the legal basis of the proposal, which remained Art. 95 of the EC Treaty, concerning the internal market.” Ibid., p. 157.

  81. At this point, it is worth noting that through the mechanism established by Regulation 1408/71 patients can receive treatment abroad as benefits-in-kind.

  82. Flear [23].

  83. This was, in effect, argued by Advocate General Colomer in his opinion in Case C-385/99 Müller-Fauré, paras 51 and 52, in which he states that “there is another reason why I believe there would be a relatively high number of patients who, if they could be certain of being reimbursed, would choose to travel to another Member State in order to see a specialist. They would be those who, having the means to afford it, would not wish to wait a relatively long time before being seen by a doctor. The patient seeks, with legitimate eagerness, to do everything in his power to look after himself”.

  84. As Newdick claims, “health rights in systems based on social welfare cannot be enforced without regard to their impact on others. They are relative rights which can be determined only by reference to the needs of other patients and mediated through the discretion of a third party public authority” [43, p. 1651].

  85. As Greer states, “Some would integrate health into the internal market; some would integrate it with other areas of EU social policy; and some would enhance its distinctiveness” [25, p. 225].

  86. Hervey [27].

References

  1. Anand, S., Peter, F., & Sen, A. K. (2004). Public health ethics, and equity. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Arneson, R. (1989). Equality and equal opportunity for welfare. Philosophical Studies, 56(1), 77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Arneson, R. (2002). Egalitarianism. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford, CA: Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Baeten, R. (2009). The proposal for a directive on patients’ rights in cross-border healthcare. In C. Degryse (Ed.), Social developments in the European Union 2008. Brussels: Trade Union Institute (ETUI), Observatoire social européen (OSE).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Barak-Erez, D., & Gross, A. M. (2007). Exploring social rights: Between theory and practice. Oxford/Portland, OR: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Beauchamp, T. L., & Childress, J. F. (1983). Principles of biomedical ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Black, H. C., & Garner, B. A. (2009). Black’s law dictionary. St. Paul, MN: Thomson Reuters.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Brown, L. D., & Amelung, V. E. (1999). ‘Manacled competition’: Market reforms in German health care. Health Affairs, 18, 76–91.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  9. Callahan, D., & Wasunna, A. A. (2006). Medicine and the market: Equity v choice. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Clarke, J., Newman, J., Smith, N., Vidler, E., & Westmarland, L. (2007). Creating citizen-consumers: Changing publics and changing public services. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cohen, G. A. (1989). On the currency of egalitarian justice. Ethics, 99(4), 906–944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Commission of the European Communities. (2008). Proposal for a directive of the European parliament and of the Council on the application of patients’ rights in cross-boarder healthcare. 2008/0142 (COD).

  13. Cornelissen, R. (1996). The principle of territory and the community regulations on social security (regulations 1408/71 and 574/72). Common Market Law Review, 33, 439–471.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Council of the European Union. (2006/C 146/01). Council conclusions on common values and principles in European Union Health Systems, Brussels.

  15. Daniels, N. (2008). Just health: Meeting health needs fairly. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. De Búrca, G. (2005). EU law and the welfare state: In search of solidarity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Docteur, E., & Oxley, H. (2003). Health-care systems: Lessons from the reform experience. OECD Health Working Papers. Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development.

  18. Dougan, M., & Spaventa, E. (2005). Social welfare and EU law. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Dworkin, R. (1993). Justice in the distribution of health care. McGill Law Journal, 38(4), 883–898.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  20. Esping-Andersen, G. (1990). The three worlds of welfare capitalism. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Esping-Andersen, G. (1999). Social foundations of postindustrial economies. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ferrera, M. (2005). The boundaries of welfare: European integration and the new spatial politics of social protection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Flear, M. (2007). Developing Euro-biocitizens through migration for healthcare services. Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law (MJ), 14(3), 239–262.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Freeman, R., & Moran, M. (2000). Reforming health care in Europe. West European Politics, 23, 35–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Greer, S. L. (2008). Choosing paths in European Union health services policy: A political analysis of a critical juncture. Journal of European Social Policy, 18, 219–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Gulliford, M., Figueroa-Munoz, J., Morgan, M., et al. (2002). What does ‘access to health care’ mean? Journal of Health Services Research & Policy, 7(3), 186–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Hervey, T. K. (2002). Mapping the contours of European Union health law and policy. European Public Law, 8(1), 69–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Hervey, T. K., & McHale, J. V. (2004). Health law and the European Union. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  29. Hurley, S. (2007). The ‘what’ and the ‘how’ of distributive justice and health. In N. Holtug & K. Lippert-Rasmussen (Eds.), Egalitarianism: New essays on the nature and value of equality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Jepsen, M., & Pascual, A. S. (2005). The European social model: An exercise in deconstruction. Journal of European Social Policy, 15(3), 231–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Joerges, C. (2009). A renaissance of the European constitution? In U. B. Neergaard, R. Nielsen, & L. M. Roseberry (Eds.), Integrating welfare functions into EU law: From Rome to Lisbon. Copenhagen: DJØF Pub.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Joerges, C., & Rödl, F. (2004). “Social market economy” as Europe’s social model? In L. Magnusson & B. Stråth (Eds.), A European social citizenship?: Preconditions for future policies from a historical perspective. Bruxelles/New York: P.I.E.-Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Jost, T. S., Dawson, D., & Exter, A. D. (2006). The role of competition in health care: A western European perspective. Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law, 31(3), 687–703.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  34. Kaczorowska, A. (2006). A review of the creation by the European Court of Justice of the right to effective and speedy medical treatment and its outcomes. European Law Journal, 12, 345–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Kandil, F. (2004). European social citizenship and the requirement of European solidarity. In L. Magnusson & B. Stråth (Eds.), A European social citizenship?: Preconditions for future policies from a historical perspective. Bruxelles/New York: P.I.E.-Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Koivusalo, M. T. (2005). The future of European health policies. Journal of Health Services, 35(2), 325–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Kolb, A.-K. (1999). European social rights towards national welfare states: Additional, substitute, illusory? In J. Bussemaker (Ed.), Citizenship and welfare state reform in Europe. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Kostakopoulou, D. (2005). Ideas, norms and European citizenship: Explaining institutional change. The Modern Law Review, 68, 233–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Lamping, W. (2005). European integration and health policy. In M. Steffen (Ed.), Health governance in Europe: Issues, challenges, and theories. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Majone, G. (1996). Regulating Europe. London/New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  41. Mooney, G., & Houston, S. (2008). Equity in health care and institutional trust. Cadernos de Saúde Pública, 24(5), 1162–1167.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  42. Mossialos, E., McKee, M., Palm, W. J., Karl, B., & Marhold, F. (2002). EU law and the social character of health care. Bern/Oxford: P. Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Newdick, C. (2006). Citizenship, free movement and health care: Cementing individual rights by coordinating social solidarity. Common Market Law Review, 43, 1645–1668.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Nozick, R. (1974). Distributive justice. In S. Avineri & A. De-Shalit (Eds.), Communitarianism and individualism. Oxford, UK/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Olsen, J. A. (1997). Theories of justice and their implications for priority setting in health care. Journal of Health Economics, 16(6), 625–639.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  46. Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Ruger, J. P. (2004). Health and social justice. The Lancet, 364, 1075–1080.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Saltman, R. B. (2002). The western European experience with health care reform. Copenhagen: European Observatory on Health Systems and Policies.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Sandel, M. (1984). The procedural republic and the unencumbered self. In S. Avineri & A. De-Shalit (Eds.), Communitarianism and individualism. Oxford, UK/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Santos, I. S. (2009). O Mix Público-Privado no Sistema de Saúde Brasileiro: elementos para a regulação da cobertura duplicada. Rio de Janeiro: Escola Nacional de Saúde Pública Sergio Arouca-ENSP/FIOCRUZ.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Sen, A. (1985). Well-being, agency and freedom: The Dewey lectures 1984. The Journal of Philosophy, 82, 169–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Stanton-Ife, J. (1999). Health care allocation in ethics and law: a defence of the need principle. Florence: Law Department, European University Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Toth, F. (2010). Healthcare policies over the last 20 years: Reforms and counter-reforms. Health Policy, 95, 82–89.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  54. Wagstaff, A., & Doorslaer, E. K. A. V. (1993). Equity in the finance and delivery of health care: Concepts and definitions. In A. Wagstaff, F. Rutten, & E. K. A. V. Doorslaer (Eds.), Equity in the finance and delivery of health care: An international perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Williams, A. (1993). Equity in health care: The role of ideology. In A. Wagstaff, F. Rutten, & E. K. A. V. Doorslaer (Eds.), Equity in the finance and delivery of health care: An international perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Wiseman, V. (1998). From selfish individualism to citizenship: Avoiding health economics’ reputed ‘dead end’. Health Care Analysis, 6, 113–122.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  57. World Health Organization. (2000). The world health report 2000—Health systems: Improving performance. Geneva: World Health Organization.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank professor Christopher Newdick for his helpful comments on a previous draft of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Danielle da Costa Leite Borges.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

da Costa Leite Borges, D. European Health Systems and the Internal Market: Reshaping Ideology?. Health Care Anal 19, 365–387 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-010-0158-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-010-0158-4

Keywords

Navigation