Skip to main content
Log in

Meaning in Nature: Organic Manufacture?

  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper examines Marcello Barbieri’s (2007) Introduction to Biosemiotics. Highlighting debate within the biosemiotic community, it focuses on what the volume offers to those who explain human intellect in relation to what Turing called our ‘physical powers.’ In scrutinising the basis of world-modelling, parallels and contrasts are drawn with other work on embodied-embedded cognition. Models dominate biology. Is this a qualitative fact or does it point to biomechanisms? In evaluating the 18 contributions, it is suggested that the answers will shape the field. First, they will decide if biochemistry and explanatory reduction can be synergised by biosemantics. Second, they will show if our intellectual powers arise from biology. Does thinking use—not a language faculty—but what Markoš and colleagues call semiosis by the living? Resolution of such issues, it is suggested, can change how we view cognition. Above all, if the biomechanists win the day, cultural models can be regarded as extending natural meaning. On such a view, biomechanisms prompt us to act and perceive as we model our own natural models. This fits Craik’s vision: intellect gives us the alphanumerical ‘symbols’ that allow thoughts to have objective validity. For the biomechanist, this is explained—not by brains alone—but, rather, by acting under the constraints of historically extended sensoria.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. After Turing abandoned the goal of developing O-machines (ones returning the value of functions that are not Turing computable), he decided that “mental processes, conceptualized as distinct from matter, could be understood in machine-based terms” (Boden 2006: 168).

  2. On this view ‘conceptual structure arises from sensorimotor experience and the neural structures that give rise to it’ (Lakoff and Johnson 1999: 77).

  3. This contrasts with viewing language as based on ‘non-natural meaning’ or using the human intellect as a basis for signaling and construing intentions.

  4. Clark’s (2006) ‘cognitive niche’ is said to exploit ‘material symbols’. If these are independent of agents, they are inert objects. As Clowes (2007) notes, it is hard to imagine how living beings could learn from such entities. By contrast, if we posit semiotics by the living, such objections fall away.

  5. Instead of seeking foundational propositions, a coherentist approach to science adopts explanatory reduction or what Rescher (1974) called a network model. As Bechtel (2002) puts it, one decomposes behaviour into subtasks and, later, seeks explanations in lower level mechanisms and properties. Where successful, this permits progressive integration of predictions and applications into an established knowledge system.

  6. On this issue the biosemiotician does not take experience to show ‘purposeful inwardness’ (Jonas 2001); unlike Di Paolo (2005), this is taken to be no more than semiotic expression.

  7. Elsewhere, I argue that learning to talk draws heavily on a caregiver’s over-ascriptions. By the end of the first year a child produces abstraction amenable behaviour; by the ‘word-combinations’ of the second, this is analysis amenable (Spurrett and Cowley 2004; Cowley 2004).

References

  • Barbieri, M. (2007). Introduction to biosemiotics: The new biological synthesis. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2002). Decomposing the mind-brain: A long-term pursuit. Brain and Mind, 3(2), 229–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. (2007). Language as an interaction system. New Ideas in Psychology, 25/2, 171–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boden, M. (2006). Mind as machine: A history of cognitive science (vol. 1). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cangelosi, A., Greco, A., & Harnad, S. (2002). Symbol grounding and the symbolic theft hypothesis. In A. Cangelosi and D. Parisi (Eds.), Simulating the evolution of language191–210. London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2006). Language, embodiment and the cognitive niche. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10/8, 370–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clowes, R. (2007). A self regulation model of inner speech and its role in the self-regulation of conscious experience. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14/7, 59–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowley, S. J. (2004). Contextualizing bodies: How human responsiveness constrains distributed cognition. Language Sciences, 26/6, 565–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowley, S. J. (2007). The codes of language: Turtles all the way up? In M. Barbieri (Ed.), The codes of life (pp. 319–345). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craik, K. (1943). The nature of explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason and the human brain. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1881). The formation of vegetable mould through the actions of worms with observations on their habits. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. (2007). Participatory sense-making: An enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 485–507.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo E. A. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elman, J. L., Bates, E. A., Johnson, M. H., Karmiloff-Smith, A., Parisi, D., & Plunkett, P. (1996). Rethinking innateness: A connectionist perspective on development. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Favareau, D. (2007). Animal sensing, acting and knowing: Bridging the relations between brains, bodies and world. In G. Witzany (Ed.), Biosemiotics in transdisciplinary contexts (pp. 61–69). Helsinki: Umweb Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (1995). How a cockpit remembers its speeds. Cognitive Science, 19, 265–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. (2002). Foundations of language: Brain, meaning, grammar, evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Järvilehto, T. (1998). The theory of the organism-environment system 1. Description of the theory. Integrative Behavioural and Physiological Science, 33/4, 321–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (2001). The phenomenon of life: Toward a philosophical biology. Everston, IL: Northwestern University Press, (first published, 1965).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and its challenge to western thought. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K., & Brown, G. (2006). Niche construction, human behavior, and the adaptive-lag hypothesis in humans. Evolutionary Anthropology, 15/3, 95–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J., & Bogin, B. (2006). Language and life history: A new perspective on the development and evolution of human language. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 29/3, 259–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, N. (2007). Language and the digital code. Language Sciences, 29/5, 690–709.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R. (1978). Biology of language: The epistemology of reality. In G. A. Miller, & L. Elizabeth (Eds.), Psychology and biology of language and thought: Essays in honor of Eric Lenneberg, (pp. 27–63). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1992). The tree of knowledge: The biological roots of human understanding. Boston MA: Shambhala.

    Google Scholar 

  • Port, S. (1994). The language instinct. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Port, R. (2007). How are words stored in memory: Beyond phones and phonemes.New Ideas in Psychology, 25/2, 143–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raczaszek-Leonardi, J., & Scott Kelso, J. A. (2008). Reconciling symbolic and dynamic aspects of language: Toward a dynamic psycholinguistics. New Ideas in Psychology (in press) DOI 10.1016/j.newideapsych.2007.07.003.

  • Rescher, N. (1974). Foundationalism, coherentism, and the idea of cognitive systematization. The Journal of Philosophy, 71(19), 695–708.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, D. (2007). H sapiens as ecologically special: What does language contribute?. Language Sciences, 16/1, 710–731.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, D., Spurrett, D., Kincaid, H., & Stephens, D. L. (2007). Distributed cognition and the will. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sebeok, T. A. (1991). A sign is just a sign. Bloomington IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1957). Verbal behavior. Acton, MA: Copley Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spurrett, D., & Cowley, S. J. (2004). How to do things without words. Language Sciences, 26/5, 443–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, T. J. (2000). Language constructing language: The implications of reflexivity for linguistic theory. Language Sciences, 22/4, 483–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thibault, P. (2004). Agency and consciousness in discourse. Continuum: London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind and life: Biology, phenomenology and the sciences of mind. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2003). Constructing a language: A usage-based theory of language acquisition. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 59, 433–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1991). Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves. In A. I. Tauber (Ed.), Organism and the origin of self (pp. 79–107). Amsterdam: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walmsley, J. (2008). Methodological situatedness; or, DEEDS worth doing and pursuing. Cognitive Systems Research (in press) DOI 10.1016/j.cogsys.2007.07.006.

  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world: The next step. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Willems, R., Hagoort, P. (2007). Neural evidence and the interplay between language, gesture and action: A review. Brain and Language, 101, 278–289.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. (2005). Collective memory, group minds, and the extended mind thesis. Cognitive Processes, 6, 227–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stephen J. Cowley.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Cowley, S.J. Meaning in Nature: Organic Manufacture?. Biosemiotics 1, 85–98 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-008-9003-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-008-9003-7

Keywords

Navigation