Skip to main content
Log in

The Psychological Origins of the Doctrine of Double Effect

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The doctrine of double effect (DDE) is a moral principle that distinguishes between harm we cause as a means to an end and harm that we cause as a side-effect. As a purely descriptive matter, the DDE is well established that it describes a consistent feature of human moral judgment. There are, however, several rival theories of its psychological cause. I review these theories and consider their advantages and disadvantages. Critically, most extant psychological theories of the DDE regard it as an accidental byproduct of cognitive architecture. This may provide philosophers with some reason to question its normative significance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Aquinas, T. (1988/1274). Summa Theologiae IIa IIae, Question 64, Article 7. In P. Sigmund (Ed.), St. Thomas Aquinas on Politics and Ethics. Norton, New York.

  • Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crockett, M. J. (2013). Models of morality. Trends in Cognitive Science, 17 (8): 363–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F. A., Young, L., & Hauser, M. D. (2006). The role of conscious reasoning and intuition in moral judgment: Testing three principles of harm. Psychological Science, 17 (12): 1082–1089.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F. A. (2008). Crime and punishment: Distinguishing the roles of causal and intentional analyses in moral judgment. Cognition, 108 (2): 353–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F. A., & Young, L. (2011). Patterns of moral judgment derive from nonmoral psychological representations. Cognitive Science, 35 (6): 1052–1075.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F. A. (2013). Action, outcome and value: A dual-system framework for morality. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 17 (3): 273–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dayan, P. (2012). How to set the switches on this thing. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 22 (6): 1068–1074.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeScioli, P., Asao, K., & Kurzban, R. (2012). Omissions and byproducts across moral domains. PLOS One, 7 (10): e46963.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickinson, A., Balleine, B., Watt, A., Gonzalez, F., & Boakes, R. A. (1995). Motivational control after extended instrumental training. Learning & Behavior, 23 (2): 197–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickinson, A., & Shanks, D. (1995). Instrumental action and causal representation. In D. Sperber, D. Premack & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal Cognition (pp. 5–25). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1967). The problem of abortion and the doctrine of double effect. Oxford Review, 5: 5–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, M. J., & Badre, D. (2012). Mechanisms of hierarchical reinforcement learning in cortiostriatal circuits 1: computational analysis. Cerebral Cortex, 22 (3): 509–526.

  • Goldman, A. (1971). The individuation of action. Journal of Philosophy, 68: 761–774.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science, 293: 2105–2108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D. (2008). The Secret Joke of Kant’s Soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral Psychology (Vol. 3). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D., Cushman, F. A., Stewart, L. E., Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J. D. (2009). Pushing moral buttons: The interaction between personal force and intention in moral judgment. Cognition, 111 (3): 364–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, M. D., Cushman, F. A., Young, L., Jin, R., & Mikhail, J. (2007). A dissociation between moral judgment and justification. Mind and Language, 22 (1): 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lashley, K. S. (1951). The problem of serial order in behavior. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lotto, L., Manfrinati, A., & Sarlo, M. (2013). A New Set of Moral Dilemmas: Norms for Moral Acceptability, Decision Times, and Emotional Salience. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 27 (1): 57–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mikhail, J. (2000). Rawls’ Linguistic Analogy: A study of the ‘generative grammar’ model of moral theory described by John Rawls in ‘A theory of justice’. (Doctoral Dissertation), Cornell University, Ithaca.

  • Mikhail, J. (2007). Universal moral grammar: Theory, evidence, and the future. Trends in Cognitive Science, 11 (4): 143–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mikhail, J. (2011). Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls’ Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, G. A. (1956). The magical number seven, plus or minus two: some limits on our capacity for processing information. Psychological Review, 63 (2): 81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, R., & Cushman, F. (2013). Aversive for me, wrong for you: first-person behavioral aversions underlie the moral condemnation of harm. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 7 (10): 707–718.

  • O’Reilly, R. C., & Frank, M. J. (2006). Making working memory work: a computational model of learning in the prefrontal cortex and basal ganglia. Neural Computation, 18 (2): 283–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ribas-Fernandes, J. Ú. J. F., Solway, A., Diuk, C., McGuire, J. T., Barto, A. G., Niv, Y., & Botvinick, M. M. (2011). A neural signature of hierarchical reinforcement learning. Neuron, 71 (2): 370–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Royzman, E., & Baron, J. (2002). The Preference for Indirect Harm. Social Justice Research, 15 (2): 165–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. A. (2012). Expertise in moral reasoning? Order effects on moral judgment in professional philosophers and non-philosophers. Mind and Language, 27 (2): 135–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Mallon, R., McCoy, T., & Hull, J. G. (2008). Intention, temporal order, and moral judgments. Mind & Language, 23 (1): 90–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldmann, M. R., & Dieterich, J. H. (2007). Throwing a bomb on a person versus throwing a person on a bomb: intervention myopia in moral intuitions. Psychological Science, 18 (3): 247–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, L., Cushman, F. A., Hauser, M. D., & Saxe, R. (2007). The neural basis of the interaction between theory of mind and moral judgment. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 104 (20): 8235–8240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This research was supported by Grant N00014-13-1-0281 from the Office of Naval Research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fiery Cushman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cushman, F. The Psychological Origins of the Doctrine of Double Effect. Criminal Law, Philosophy 10, 763–776 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-014-9334-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-014-9334-1

Keywords

Navigation