Skip to main content

Becoming Virtuous: Character Education and the Problem of Free Will

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Springer International Handbooks of Education ((SIHE))

Abstract

How can we reconcile the fact that in order to act virtuously we appear to need to refer to the concept of a free will, while, at the same time, there are convincing philosophical arguments (aligned with a contemporary scientific understanding of natural causation) discrediting any viable notion of an unconstrained or uncaused will? Taking its cue from this important question, this chapter will proceed along the following lines. First, I aim to substantiate the link between contemporary character education and the concept of the free will so as to illustrate the interdependency between the two. Next, I will scrutinize the concept of a free will, raising some philosophical concerns about its validity in a contemporary educational context. This involves looking at the philosophical stakes involved in proposing a unique capacity to intervene with the causal order of nature. At this point, I will suggest that there is a way out of this conundrum, and I will continue by proposing a radically different understanding of the will, offered by the seventeenth-century rationalist Spinoza. The chapter will close by looking at some of the practical consequences of grounding contemporary character education in a Spinozistic conception of the will.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   669.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   849.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   849.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Correspondingly, to be able to make choices is generally taken to be what constitutes being free. For a choice to be genuinely autonomous, in turn, it is generally required that one is the cause of one’s choice. Accordingly, in the context of educational theory, Kenneth A. Strike offers the following three conditions of freedom:

    1. 1.

      “A person must be able to do what he chooses. This includes possessing relevant abilities and skills of execution as well as not being prohibited or physically prevented from taking a chosen course of action.

    2. 2.

      A person must possess those reasoning skills which enable him to evaluate various courses of action. This is a matter of having learned to apply those criteria relevant to making various sorts of judgments.

    3. 3.

      A person must be psychologically constituted such that it is possible for the exercise of such reasoning skills to become the actual determinates of choice and action” (1972, p. 274).

  2. 2.

    Stefaan E. Cuypers, for example, contends that “[t]he complementary issues of manipulation and autonomy in the metaphysics of free will cover, to a large extent, the same domain as that of indoctrination and authenticity in the philosophy of education” (2009, p. 124).

  3. 3.

    For a helpful discussion on how the four cardinal western virtues of prudence, justice, fortitude, and temperance correspond to Buddhist virtues (identifying both similarities and differences), see Keown (2007, pp. 101–104).

  4. 4.

    For an informed discussion on the relation between (and, to a degree, convergence of) Socratic and Confucian senses of self-cultivation, self-knowledge, and ethics of learning, see Kwak (2016). For a brief comparison of the Confucian ethics of virtues and Aristotelian ethics, see Chen (2002).

  5. 5.

    For a brief overview of the shifting historical role and the recent revival of Confucianism in Chinese public education, see Wu and Wenning (2016, pp. 559–565).

  6. 6.

    Accordingly Carr writes: “The Christian idea of the will as something which operates as an independent source of motivation and choice and which is open to the influence of good or evil is quite different in these crucial respects from Plato’s thumos and probably makes its first entrance into western thought with St Augustine” (1991, p. 37).

  7. 7.

    Cf. Aristotle (1984), NE, Book III, 5.

  8. 8.

    Similarly, Allen W. Wood offers the following helpful explanation of transcendental freedom: “When we think of ourselves as appearances, we are determined, but when we think of ourselves as moral agents, we transport ourselves into the intelligible world, where we are transcendentally free” (2008, p. 135).

  9. 9.

    Authentic education, on Cuypers’ view, is conceived as “opposed to indoctrinative education” insofar as it “consists of necessary educational interferences that are conducive to the attainment of the primary educational aim of transforming children into morally responsible agents” (2009, p. 135).

  10. 10.

    Cf. Kant 1999, A532–58/B560–86.

  11. 11.

    Similarly, Young Pai concludes that “[t]he feeling of being able to act contrary to his [the agent’s] character may be nothing but an illusion, but it is a psychological fact” (1966, p. 143).

  12. 12.

    Passages in Spinoza’s Ethics will be referred to using the following abbreviations: D(-efinition), p(-roposition), s(-cholium), and pref(-ace). Hence, E3p9s refers to the scholium of the 9th proposition of Part 3 of the Ethics. All references to the Ethics are to Curley’s (1985a) translation.

  13. 13.

    References to Spinoza’s correspondence are to Shirley’s translation in Spinoza: Complete Works (2002).

  14. 14.

    For an in-depth discussion of Spinoza and moral education, see Dahlbeck (2016, 2017).

  15. 15.

    References to Spinoza’s Metaphysical Thoughts (CM) are to Curley’s (1985b) translation.

References

  • Aristotle. (1984). Nicomachean ethics. In J. Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle: The revised Oxford translation (Vol. 2, pp. 1729–1867). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (1991). Educating the virtues: An essay on the philosophical psychology of moral development and education. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (2003). Character and moral choice in the cultivation of virtue. Philosophy, 78(304), 219–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, C.-Y. (2002). Editor’s introduction: On the comparative origins of classical Chinese ethics and Greek ethics. Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 29(3), 307–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cuypers, S. E. (2009). Educating for authenticity: The paradox of moral education revisited. In H. Siegel (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of education (pp. 122–144). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahlbeck, J. (2016). Spinoza and education: Freedom, understanding and empowerment. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahlbeck, J. (2017). A Spinozistic model of moral education. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 36(5), 533–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eshleman, A. (2014). Moral responsibility, The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2014 Edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/moral-responsibility/

  • Gavin, E. A. (1992). Moral choice: A psychological perspective. In R. T. Knowles & G. F. McLean (Eds.), Psychological foundations of moral education and character development: An integrated theory of moral development (2nd ed., rev.) (pp. 125–139). Washington, DC: Council for Research in Values and Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giesinger, J. (2010). Free will and education. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 44(4), 515–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giesinger, J. (2012). Kant’s account of moral education. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 44(7), 775–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, D. (1975). Free-will and the undesirability of moral education. Educational Theory, 25(4), 407–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haji, I., & Cuypers, S. E. (2004). Moral responsibility and the problem of manipulation reconsidered. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 12(4), 439–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Y. (2011). Can virtue be taught and how? Confucius on the paradox of moral education. Journal of Moral Education, 40(2), 141–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1999). In P. Guyer & A. W. Woods (Eds.), Critique of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kent, B. (1995). Virtues of the will: The transformation of ethics in the late thirteenth century. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keown, D. (2007). Buddhism and ecology: A virtue ethics approach. Contemporary Buddhism, 8(2), 97–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, R. (2014). Aristotle’s ethics. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2014 Edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/aristotle-ethics/

  • Kristjánsson, K. (2007). Aristotle, emotions, and education. Ashgate: Aldershot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson, K. (2015). Aristotelian character education. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kwak, D.-J. (2016). Ethics of learning and self-knowledge: Two cases in the Socratic and Confucian teachings. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 48(1), 7–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melamed, Y. Y. (2011). Spinoza’s anti-humanism: An outline. In C. Fraenkel, D. Perinetti, & J. E. H. Smith (Eds.), The rationalists: Between tradition and innovation (pp. 147–166). Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pai, Y. (1966). The free will problem and moral education. Educational Theory, 16(2), 135–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, R. S. (2015a). Moral development and moral education (Routledge revivals). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, R. S. (2015b). Authority, responsibility and education (Routledge revivals). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ravven, H. M. (2013). The self beyond itself: An alternative history of ethics, the new brain sciences, and the myth of free will. New York: The New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanderse, W. (2015). An Aristotelian model of moral development. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 49(3), 382–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (1985a). Ethics. In E. Curley (Ed. & Trans.), The collected works of Spinoza (Vol. 1, pp. 408–617). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (1985b). Metaphysical thoughts (Cogita Metaphysica). Appendix to principles of Cartesian philosophy. In E. Curley (Ed. & Trans.), The collected works of Spinoza (Vol. 1, pp. 299–346). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (2002). The letters. In M.L. Morgan (Ed.) & S. Shirley (Trans.), Spinoza: Complete works (pp. 755–959). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (1994). The impossibility of moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 75(1/2), 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strike, K. A. (1972). Freedom, autonomy and teaching. Educational Theory, 22(3), 262–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1986). An essay on free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vokey, D. (1999). MacIntyre, moral value, and Mahayana Buddhism: Embracing the unthinkable in moral education. Educational Theory, 49(1), 91–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. W. (2008). Kantian ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu, J., & Wenning, M. (2016). The postsecular turn in education: Lessons from the mindfulness movement and the revival of Confucian academies. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 35(6), 551–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Johan Dahlbeck .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Dahlbeck, J. (2018). Becoming Virtuous: Character Education and the Problem of Free Will. In: Smeyers, P. (eds) International Handbook of Philosophy of Education. Springer International Handbooks of Education. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-72761-5_65

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-72761-5_65

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-72759-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-72761-5

  • eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics