Skip to main content
Log in

In defence of error theory

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many contemporary philosophers rate error theories poorly. We identify the arguments these philosophers invoke, and expose their deficiencies. We thereby show that the prospects for error theory have been systematically underestimated. By undermining general arguments against all error theories, we leave it open whether any more particular arguments against particular error theories are more successful. The merits of error theories need to be settled on a case-by-case basis: there is no good general argument against error theories.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Let us give two examples from recent textbooks of metaphysics. According to Jubien (1997, p. 25), nominalists all agree that sentences like ‘Seven is less than nine’ are true: they undertake to explain how they can be true if there are no numbers. Loux (2002, pp. 15–16) assumes that all philosophers debating the existence of somersaults will agree that sentences like ‘George performed five somersaults between 3 p.m. and 4 p.m. on Thursday’ are true: he says that their disagreement concerns what makes these sentences true. This example is meant to illustrate ‘the nature of metaphysical disputes’ (p. 15).

  2. Our definition of ‘error theory’ does not exclude expressivist theories from counting as error theories. We are happy to contribute to the defence of any such expressivist theories. (Expressivists might truly deny that they are error theorists on some other definition of ‘error theory’.)

  3. Miller (2002) has shown that, in the case of ethics at least, Wright’s response to error theory suffers from a further weakness.

  4. Colour discourse is a case in point. The error theory about colour advanced by Hardin (1988) is philosophically controversial, but all parties appear to agree that the scientific basis that it draws upon is impressively rich and detailed.

  5. We are very grateful to Tom Smith and an anonymous referee for this journal for extremely helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. (2006). The scope and limits of human knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84, 159–166. doi:10.1080/00048400600758896.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. (1973). Mathematical truth. The Journal of Philosophy, 70, 661–679. doi:10.2307/2025075.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P., & David Velleman, J. (1989). Colour as a secondary quality. Mind, 98, 81–103. doi:10.1093/mind/XCVIII.389.81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brock, S., & Mares, E. (2007). Realism and anti-realism. Stocksfield: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgess, J., & Rosen, G. (2005). Nominalism reconsidered. In S. Shapiro (Ed.), Oxford handbook of the philosophy of mathematics and logic (pp. 515–535). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (1994). Conservatism in epistemology. Nous, 28, 69–89. doi:10.2307/2215920.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1973–1974). On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association, 47, 5–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • DePaul, M. R. (1998). Why bother with reflective equilibrium? In M. R. DeMichael & W. Ramsey (Eds.), Rethinking intuition: The psychology of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry (pp. 293–309). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devlin, J. (2003). An argument for an error theory of truth. Philosophical Perspectives: Language and Philosophical Perspectives, 17, 51–82. doi:10.1111/j.1520-8583.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1978). Wittgenstein’s philosophy of mathematics. In Truth and other enigmas (pp. 166–185). London: Duckworth Press.

  • Eklund, M. (2007). Fictionalism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.seop.leeds.ac.uk/entries/fictionalism/.

  • Evans, G. (1982). Can there be vague objects? Analysis, 38, 208. doi:10.2307/3327996.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Everett, A. (2005). Against fictional realism. The Journal of Philosophy, 102, 624–649.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, H. (1950). De Principiis Non Disputandum…? On the meaning and the limits of justification. In M. Black (Ed.), Philosophical analysis (pp. 119–156). Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1980). Science without numbers: A defence of nominalism. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1989). Realism, mathematics and modality. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grandy, R. E. (1973). Reference, meaning and belief. The Journal of Philosophy, 70, 439–452. doi:10.2307/2025108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, C. L. (1988). Color for philosophers. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1986). Change of view. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (1998). Truth (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (2006a). A world without isms: Life after realism, fictionalism, non-cognitivism, relativism, reductionism, revisionism, and so on. In P. Greenough & M. P. Lynch (Eds.), Truth and realism (pp. 188–202). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (2006b). The quest for REALITY. Dialectica, 61, 5–16. doi:10.1111/j.1746-8361.2006.01082.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. L. (1989). Natural reasons: Personality and polity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1994). Realism, truth and truth aptness. Philosophical Books, 35, 162–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1992a). Reasons and reductionism. The Philosophical Review, 101, 589–618. doi:10.2307/2186058.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1992b). How to speak of the colors. Philosophical Studies, 68, 221–263. doi:10.1007/BF00694847.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1993). Objectivity reconfigured: Pragmatism without verificationism. In J. Haldane & C. Wright (Eds.), Realism and reason (pp. 85–130). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jubien, M. (1997). Contemporary metaphysics: An introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, E., & Ludwig, K. (2005). Donald Davidson: Meaning, truth, language and reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983a). Introduction. In Philosophical papers (Vol. 1, pp. ix–xii). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1983b). ‘Radical interpretation’ (with Postscripts). In Philosophical papers (Vol. 1, pp. 108–121). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1983c). ‘Truth in fiction’ (with Postscripts). In Philosophical papers (Vol. 1, pp. 261–280). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liggins, D. (2006). Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? Analysis, 66, 135–141. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8284.2006.00601.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liggins, D. (2007). Anti-nominalism reconsidered. The Philosophical Quarterly, 57, 104–111. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.472.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loux, M. (2002). Metaphysics: A contemporary introduction (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Harmondsworth Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1977). Charity, interpretation, and belief. The Journal of Philosophy, 74, 521–535. doi:10.2307/2025795.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2001). Objects and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, A. (2002). Wright’s argument against error-theories. Analysis, 62, 98–103. doi:10.1111/1467-8284.00338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1959). Philosophical papers. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pryor, J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Nous, 34, 517–549. doi:10.1111/0029-4624.00277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1983). Convention: A theme in philosophy. In Realism and reason: Philosophical papers (Vol. 3, pp. 170–183). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Russell, B. (1912). On the notion of cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 13, 1–26; reprinted in his 1918, Mysticism and logic. London: Penguin.

  • Russell, B. (1914). The relation of sense-data to physics. Scientia, 16, 1–27; reprinted in his 1918 Mysticism and logic. London: Penguin.

  • Stanley, J. (2001). Hermeneutic fictionalism. In P. A. French & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy: Figurative language (Vol. XXV, pp. 36–71). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tait, W. W. (1986). Truth and proof: The Platonism of mathematics. Synthese, 69, 341–370. doi:10.1007/BF00413978.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P., & Nisbett, R. E. (1983). Rationality and charity. Philosophy of Science, 50, 250–267. doi:10.1086/289108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vahid, H. (2001). Charity, supervenience, and skepticism. Metaphilosophy, 32, 308–325. doi:10.1111/1467-9973.00190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vahid, H. (2004). Varieties of epistemic conservatism. Synthese, 141, 97–122. doi:10.1023/B:SYNT.0000035849.62840.e8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1990). Material beings. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (1980). What would be a substantial theory of truth? In Z. van Straaten (Ed.), Philosophical subjects: Essays in Honour of P.F. Strawson. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1992). Truth and objectivity. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1994). Response to Jackson. Philosophical Books, 35, 169–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chris Daly.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Daly, C., Liggins, D. In defence of error theory. Philos Stud 149, 209–230 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9346-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9346-1

Keywords

Navigation