Skip to main content
Log in

In Defence of the Hivemind Society

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The idea that humans should abandon their individuality and use technology to bind themselves together into hivemind societies seems both farfetched and frightening – something that is redolent of the worst dystopias from science fiction. In this article, we argue that these common reactions to the ideal of a hivemind society are mistaken. The idea that humans could form hiveminds is sufficiently plausible for its axiological consequences to be taken seriously. Furthermore, far from being a dystopian nightmare, the hivemind society could be desirable and could enable a form of sentient flourishing. Consequently, we should not be so quick to deny it. We provide two arguments in support of this claim – the axiological openness argument and the desirability argument – and then defend it against three major objections.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For discussions of Star Trek’s utopian pretensions, see Segal, H Utopias (Wiley-Blackwell 2012), pp. 199 ff [1]; and Saadia, M. Trekonomics (San Francisco, SF: Pipertext 2016) [2].

  2. Almost: Star Trek is a fictional product of Hollywood and was never ideally progressive when it came to its celebration of human differences and diversities. Homosexual characters, for example, were absent until the series Star Trek Discovery.

  3. On this distinction, see the Orwell-Huxley exchange on dystopianism. Available at: http://www.lettersofnote.com/2012/03/1984-v-brave-new-world.html

  4. In this sense, the article takes onboard the lesson of Owen Flanagan’s book The Geography of Morals (Oxford: OUP 2017), which is to appreciate how large the space of ‘moral possibility’ for humanity actually is.

  5. Many philosophers will be reminded of Ned Block’s [3] “Chinese Nation” thought experiment. In that case, though, the mental state of the whole is independent of the mental states of the citizens. Here we consider cases where the mental state of the whole is in some way composed of the mental states of the (former?) individuals.

  6. [5] argues that true largescale hiveminds (he doesn’t use this term) are quite rare in practice, but then tempers this by arguing that ‘minds’ come in degrees and that many group entities approximate or approach hivemind status.

  7. For an entertaining summary of the NeuraLink project and its motivations, see the Wait But Why? post at https://waitbutwhy.com/2017/04/neuralink.html.

  8. This is the Virtual Embodiment and Robotic Re-Embodiment Project, which produced well over 100 publications over the course of its duration. A full list can be found at http://www.vereproject.eu/. A readable summary of some key results is available in Rothman ‘Are we already living in virtual reality?’, New Yorker 3rd February 2018.

  9. An interesting edge case is that of conjoined twins. Some historically documented cases of conjoined twins suggest that they can have high degrees of rational unity, and, due to some shared bodily limbs and functions, some degree of phenomenological unity. That said, some of the best documented cases of conjoined twins—such as the infamous Chang and Eng Bunker twins of the nineteenth century—suggest that they can have very different personalities. For a longer discussion see [14]. In addition to this, and as a general point, there are more metaphysical arguments in favour of the possibility of phenomenological unity that are worth considering. Eric Schwitzgebel [15] argues that, as his title goes, “if materialism is true, the United States is probably conscious”. If he is right—and if materialism is right—then just about all of us are already part of phenomenologically unified hiveminds.

  10. Already, for example, there are (ungainly) devices that can read subvocalizations fairly reliably; see https://www.cnbc.com/2018/04/10/mit-alterego-communicates-with-a-computer-through-subvocalization.html. The internal audio receiver might work something like the cochlear implants of today.

  11. We pick these as examples of goals that might be deemed “good” and thus add value to life. Some people might disagree with this and think that other goals are good. This doesn’t really affect the point we are making which is simply that some level of goal achievement is part of the good life and many goals require collective action to achieve.

  12. It is possible that both forms of unity are required on some accounts of meaning but that only one is required on others. For example, on a purely consequentialist theory of meaning—that meaning depends on producing good consequences for the world—rational unity may be all that it is required. On subjectivist or hybridist accounts, phenomenological unity may also be necessary.

  13. To use more Parfittian language, the claim is that the only thing that determines personal survival is the relation between mental states — something that Parfit calls ‘Relation R’. This relation comes in degrees and it is possible for you to have relation R with a different physical body.

  14. Plausibly the Borg are bad guys because they do not seek consent. At least, this would make them bad guys from our current individualistic perspective!

  15. They are not perfectly identical of course. In the case of suicide, if you don’t believe in an everlasting soul, then the self, and every sub-component or part of the self (including its sentience) ceases to exist. In the hivemind case, some sub-components of the individual will continue to exist, including some aspects of its sentience—they will just be subsumed into the hivemind. If anything, however, this might speak in favour of the permissibility of joining a hivemind since it allows for the persistence of valuable sub-components of the self, and not their everlasting destruction.

References

  1. Segal, Howard. 2012. Utopias. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  2. Saadia, Manu. 2016. Trekonomics. San Francisco: Pipertext.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Block, Ned. 1978. Troubles with Functionalism. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9: 261–325.

    Google Scholar 

  4. List, Christian, and Phillip Pettit. 2011. Group Agency, 2011. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  5. Huebner, Bryce. 2014. Macrocognition: A Theory of Distributed Minds and Collective Intentionality. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Harari, Yuval Noah. 2016. Homo Deus. London: Harvill Secker.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Clark, Arthur C. (1962). Profiles of the Future. Harper & Row.

  8. Warwick, K. 2013. Cyborgs- the neuro-tech version. In Implantable bioelectronics — devices, materials and applications, ed. E. Katz. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Warwick, K. 2014. The Cyborg Revolution. Nanoethics 8: 263–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Nicolelis, Miguel. 2011. Beyond Boundaries: The New Neuroscience of Connecting Brains with Machines and How it Will Change Our Lives. New York: St Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Metzinger, Thomas. 2009. The Ego Tunnel: The Science of the Mind and the Myth of the Self. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Sotala, Kaj, and Harri Valpola. 2012. Coalescing Minds: Brain Uploading-Related Group Mind Scenarios. International Journal of Machine Consciousness 4 (1): 293–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Churchland, Paul. 1981. Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes. Journal of Philosophy 78 (2): 67–90.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Savulescu, Julian, and Ingmar Persson. 2016. Conjoined Twins: Philosophical Problems and Ethical Challenges. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 41: 41–54.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Schwitzgebel, Eric. 2015. If materialism is true, the United States is probably conscious. Philosophical Studies 172 (7): 1697–1721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Flanagan, Owen. 2017. The Geography of Morals: On the Varieties of Moral Possibility. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Christie, Tim. 2009. Natural Separateness: Why Parfit's Reductionist Account of Persons Fails to Support Consequentialism. Journal of Moral Philosophy 6 (2): 178–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Schneewind, J.B. 1998. The Invention of Autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Siedentop, Larry. 2011. Inventing the Individual. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Chadha, Monima. 2017. No Self and the Phenomenology of Agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. 16: 187–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Chadha, Moniam. 2018. No Self and the Phenomenology of Ownership. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 96 (1): 14–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Becker, Ernest. 1971. The Birth and Death of Meaning. 2nd ed. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Bradford, Gwen. 2016. Achievement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Maslen, H., J. Savulescu, and C. Hunt. 2019. Praiseworthiness and Motivational Enhancement: ‘No Pain, No Praise’? Australasian Journal of Philosophy: 1–15. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2019.1618883.

  25. Luper, S. 2014. Life’s Meaning. In The Cambridge Companion to Life and Death, ed. S. Luper. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  26. Morris, Ian. 2015. Foragers, Farmers and Fossil Fuels. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Tainter, Joseph. 1988. The Collapse of Complex Societies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Henrich, Joseph. 2015. The Secret of Our Success. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  29. Collison, Patrick and Nielsen, Michael (2018). Science is Getting Less Bang for its Buck. The Atlantic 16th November 2018.

  30. Bloom, Nicholas, Jones, Charles, Van Reenen, John and Webb, Michael, ‘Are ideas getting harder to find?’ (2018), NBER Working Paper 5 March 2018, Version 2.0 – available at https://web.stanford.edu/~chadj/IdeaPF.pdf

  31. Dennett, Daniel C. (2017). From Bacteria to Bach and Back. W. W. Norton & Company.

  32. Beyleveld, Deryck. 1991. The Dialectical Necessity of Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Smith, Michael. 1994. The Moral Problem. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Enoch, David. 2011. Taking Morality Seriously: A Defence of Robust Realism. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  35. Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Le Bihan, Baptiste (2018). The No Self View and the Meaning of Life. Philosophy East and West 69(2).

  37. Campbell, Steven, and Sven Nyholm. 2015. Anti-Meaning and Why it Matters. Journal of the American Philosophical Association. 1 (4): 694–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Danaher, John. 2014. Hyperagency and the Good Life - Does Extreme Enhancement Threaten Meaning? Neuroethics 7 (2): 227–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Danaher, John. 2017. Will Life Be Worth Living in a World Without Work? Technological Unemployment and the Meaning of Life. Science and Engineering Ethics 23: 41–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Metz, T. 2013. Meaning in Life: an analytic study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  41. Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Nozick, Robert. 1989. The Examined Life. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Landau, Iddo. 2018. Finding Meaning in an Imperfect World. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Minerva, Francesca. 2018. The Ethics of Cryonics. London: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  45. O’Connell, Mark. 2017. To Be A Machine. London: Granta.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Korsgaard, Christine M. 1989. Personal Identity and the Unity of Agency: a Kantian Perspective on Parfit. Philosophy and Public Affairs 18: 101–132.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Strawson, Galen. 2018. Things That Bother Me: Death, Freedom, the Self, Etc. New York: New York Review of Books.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Rovane, Carole. 1997. The Bounds of Agency: An Essay in Revisionary Metaphysics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  49. Rovane, Carole. 2004. What is an agent? Synthese 140 (1–2): 181–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Rovane, Carole. 2006. Why do individuals matter? Daedelus 135 (4): 49–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Rovane, Carole. 2014. Group Agency and Individualism. Erkenntis 79 (S9): 1663–1684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Danaher.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Danaher, J., Petersen, S. In Defence of the Hivemind Society. Neuroethics 14, 253–267 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-020-09451-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-020-09451-7

Keywords

Navigation