Skip to main content
Log in

On nonindexical contextualism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

MacFarlane distinguishes “context sensitivity” from “indexicality,” and argues that “nonindexical contextualism” has significant advantages over the standard indexical form. MacFarlane’s substantive thesis is that the extension of an expression may depend on an epistemic standard variable even though its content does not. Focusing on ‘knows,’ I will argue against the possibility of extension dependence without content dependence when factors such as meaning, time, and world are held constant, and show that MacFarlane’s nonindexical contextualism provides no advantages over indexical contextualism. The discussion will shed light on the definition of indexicals as well as the meaning of ‘knows,’ and highlight important constraints on the way meaning can be represented in semantics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Bar-Hillel (1954, p. 359), Gale (1967, p. 151), Montague (1968, p. 103), Lewis (1970, p. 184ff), Stalnaker (1976, p. 229), Kaplan (1977, pp. 490, 506), Lyons (1977, pp. 106, 637, 646), Levinson (1994, 2003), Leezenberg (1994, p. 1648), Perry (1997, p. 586), Forbes (2003, p. 87), Corazza (2003, p. 593ff), Cappelen and Lepore (2005, p. 89) Gonzáles-Romero (2005, p. 261). Related definitions characterize indexicals as expressions whose reference varies with the token, occurrence, or utterance; see Burks (1949, pp. 685–7), Reichenbach (1947, p. 284), Gale (1964, p. 227), Searle (1983, p. 221), Perry (2003, p. 378); contrast Kaplan (1977, p. 522).

  2. MacFarlane cites Kompa (2002) and Ludlow (2005, p. 27) as possible antecedents.

  3. This formulation is adapted from MacFarlane (2009, p. 236). For it to be plausible, we also need to assume that S’s epistemic position with respect to p meets e(C) only if S believes p, and is not in a Gettier situation.

  4. MacFarlane credits Hawthorne (2004) and Cappelen and Lepore (2005) for this argument.

  5. MacFarlane (2009, p. §2) uses “temporalism” as a motivating example. Inferring from that example, MacFarlane might take temporalism to maintain that ‘knows’ expresses the same two-place relation in every context, the relation S stands in to p iff S knows p. Given MacFarlane’s truth-conditions, and the independence of t as well as e of S and p, there is no such two-place relation.

  6. ‘S knows’ can be used elliptically. If Sam says, “Does Alice know her husband is having an affair?” Barry can reply “She knows.” When so used, ‘S knows’ expresses different propositions on different occasions.

  7. MacFarlane could fill this out by using the theory of thoughts and propositions I developed in Davis (2003).

  8. As MacFarlane (2009, p. 240) observes in connection with a slightly different example (one of DeRose’s “abominable conjunctions”), nothing in contextualism prevents the epistemic standard from shifting from one conjunct to another since they occur in different contexts (as demonstrative pronouns show). So it allows an explicit contradiction like ‘Alice knows her car is in the driveway but does not know it is’ to come out true. MacFarlane claims that nonindexical contextualism explains why it always seems contradictory: “the context of use determines a single epistemic standard that is relevant to the evaluation of both occurrences of ‘know.’” This is an independent postulate, however, not something entailed by nonindexical contextualism. The indexical contextualist could postulate the same thing.

  9. As is customary, we are using ‘utter’ in a generic sense that includes writing and signing. If it is restricted to spoken utterance, then to utter an expression is to make it occur by speaking.

  10. Things are less obvious if a sentence occurs more than once in a context, which is why I changed MacFarlane’s ‘an’ to ‘the.’

  11. See Cappelen and Lepore (2005, p. 105ff), MacFarlane (2005, p. 202ff), Hawthorne (2004, pp. 107, fn. 125), Davis (2005, p. 39, 2007, pp. 400–01), Bach (2005, p. 60), Stanley (2005, pp. 54ff, 115, 119ff), Fantl and McGrath (2009, p. 180ff). Contrast DeRose (1992, pp. 925–6, 2009, pp. 207–12), Cohen (2005, pp. 205–206), Blome-Tillmann (2008, pp. 34, 37).

  12. MacFarlane thought that Kompa 2002 lapsed into inconsistency when she claimed that her theory had the “unpleasant” consequence of counting Ascriber C says something true in uttering ‘A knows that p’ but A doesn’t know that p, his (30), as true in certain cases. According to MacFarlane (2009, p. 248), ‘if “says something true” means “expresses a proposition that is true,” which I think is the most natural reading, then nonindexical contextualism does not predict that (30) is true.’ But ‘says something true’ also means “speaks truly,” which on nonindexical contextualism means uttering a sentence that is true in the context of utterance, and requires only that the proposition expressed be true relative to that context.

  13. I critique MacFarlane’s relativism in “Knowledge Claims and the Context of Assessment,” which was presented at the “Contexts, Perspectives, and Relative Truth” conference held at the University of Bonn, June 9–11, 2011.

References

  • Bach, K. (2005). The emperor’s new ‘knows’. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy: Knowledge, meaning, and truth (pp. 51–90). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Hillel, Y. (1954). Indexical expressions. Mind, 63, 359–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blome-Tillmann, M. (2008). The indexicality of ‘knowledge’. Philosophical Studies, 138, 29–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braun, D. (2007). Indexicals. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (pp. 1–33). Stanford, CA: http://www.plato.stanford.edu/entries/indexicals/.

  • Burks, A. W. (1949). Icon, index, and symbol. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 9, 673–689.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Hawthorne, J. (2009). Relativism and monadic truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (2005). Insensitive semantics: A defense of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1986). Knowledge and context. Journal of Philosophy, 83, 574–583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1988). How to be a fallibilist. Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 91–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2005). Knowledge, speaker and subject. Philosophical Quarterly, 55, 199–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corazza, E. (2003). Indexicality: Philosophical aspects. In W. J. Frawley (Ed.), International encyclopedia of linguistics (2nd ed., pp. 593–596). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2003). Meaning, expression, and thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2005). Contextualist theories of knowledge. Acta Analytica, 20, 29–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2007). Knowledge claims and context: Loose use. Philosophical Studies, 132(3), 395–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1992). Contextualism and knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, 913–929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2009). The case for contextualism: Knowledge, skepticism, and context (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2009). Critical study of John Hawthorne’s Knowledge and lotteries and Jason Stanley’s Knowledge and practical interests. Noûs, 43, 178–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, G. (2003). Indexicals. In D. M. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic, vol. 10 (2nd ed., pp. 87–120). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gale, R. M. (1964). The egocentric particular and token-reflexive analysis of tense. Philosophical Review, 43, 213–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gale, R. M. (1967). Indexical signs, egocentric particulars, and token-reflexive words. In P. Edwards (Ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy (Vol. 4, pp. 151–154). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonzáles-Romero, L. (2005). Deixis. In P. Strazny (Ed.), Encyclopedia of linguistics (pp. 260–262). New York: Fitzroy Dearborn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1977). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press (1989).

  • Kompa, N. (2002). The context sensitivity of knowledge ascriptions. Grazier Philosophische Studien, 64, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leezenberg, M. (1994). Indexicals. In R. Asher (Ed.), Encyclopedia of language and linguistics (pp. 1648–1651). Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (1994). Deixis. In R. E. Asher (Ed.), The encyclopedia of language and linguistics (Vol. 2, pp. 853–857). Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (2003). Deixis. In W. J. Frawley (Ed.), International encyclopedia of linguistics (Vol. 2, pp. 423–424). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1970). Anselm and actuality. Nous, 4, 175–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow, P. (2005). Contextualism and the new linguistic turn in epistemology. In G. Preyer & G. Peters (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy (pp. 11–50). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, J. (1977). Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2005). The assessment sensitivity of knowledge attributions. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 1, pp. 197–233). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2007). Semantic minimalism and nonindexical contextualism. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Context-sensitivity and semantic minimalism (pp. 240–250). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2009). Nonindexical contextualism. Synthese, 166, 231–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1968). Pragmatics. In R. Klibansky (Ed.), Contemporary philosophy (pp. 102–122). Florence: La Nuova Italie Editrice.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1997). Indexicals and demonstratives. In B. Hale & C. Wright (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of language (pp. 586–612). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (2003). Predelli’s threatening note: Contexts, utterances, and tokens in the philosophy of language. Journal of Pragmatics, 35, 373–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1947). Elements of symbolic logic. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1976). Possible worlds. Noûs, 10, 65–75. Reprinted in The Possible and the Actual, ed. M. J. Loux, pp. 225–234. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press (1979).

  • Stanley, J. (2004). On the linguistic basis for contextualism. Philosophical Studies, 119, 119–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

I thank members of the audience at the Kirchberg Symposium, especially John Greco and Stewart Cohen, for comments that helped improve my argument significantly.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wayne A. Davis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Davis, W.A. On nonindexical contextualism. Philos Stud 163, 561–574 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9831-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9831-1

Keywords

Navigation