Skip to main content
Log in

Evolved cognitive biases and the epistemic status of scientific beliefs

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Our ability for scientific reasoning is a byproduct of cognitive faculties that evolved in response to problems related to survival and reproduction. Does this observation increase the epistemic standing of science, or should we treat scientific knowledge with suspicion? The conclusions one draws from applying evolutionary theory to scientific beliefs depend to an important extent on the validity of evolutionary arguments (EAs) or evolutionary debunking arguments (EDAs). In this paper we show through an analytical model that cultural transmission of scientific knowledge can lead toward representations that are more truth-approximating or more efficient at solving science-related problems under a broad range of circumstances, even under conditions where human cognitive faculties would be further off the mark than they actually are.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This broad position is not to be confused with evolutionary psychology in the narrow sense as developed by the so-called “Santa Barbara school”, in particular by John Tooby and Leda Cosmides.

  2. This is a type of extreme probability distribution that models long (finite) sequences of random variables.

  3. Thanks to the anonymous reviewer for pointing this out.

  4. Transmutation is a historical term for what is now denoted by biological evolution which avoids the anachronism of ‘pre-Darwinian evolutionary theory’. The term ‘evolution’ was not routinely used to denote the natural development of life on Earth until Herbert Spencer popularized this sense of the term in the second half of the nineteenth century. Darwin, for example, in his Origin of species (1859), only once used the derivative ‘evolved’.

References

  • Akins, K. (1996). Of sensory systems and the “aboutness” of mental states. Journal of Philosophy, 93, 337–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, H. C. (2004). Design versus descent in Shuar children’s reasoning about animals. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 4, 25–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, M. S., Lee, K. E., Haxby, J. V., & Martin, A. (2002). Parallel visual motion processing streams for manipulable objects and human movements. Neuron, 34, 149–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P. (2007). Religion is natural. Developmental Science, 10, 147–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonatti, L., Frot, E., Zangl, R., & Mehler, J. (2002). The human first hypothesis: Identification of conspecifics and individuation of objects in the young infant. Cognitive Psychology, 44, 388–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boulter, S. J. (2007). The “evolutionary argument” and the metaphilosophy of commonsense. Biology & Philosophy, 22, 369–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. (2003). Evolution. The history of an idea (3rd ed.). Berkeley & Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. (2008). What Darwin disturbed: The biology that might have been. Isis, 99, 560–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, P. (2000). Natural epistemology or evolved metaphysics? Developmental evidence for early-developed, intuitive, category-specific, incomplete, and stubborn metaphysical presumptions. Philosophical Psychology, 13, 277–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bräuer, J., Kaminski, J., Riedel, J., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2006). Making inferences about the location of hidden food: Social dog, causal ape. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 120, 38–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, W. F., Chinn, C. A., & Samarapungavan, A. (2000). Explanation in scientists and children. In F. C. Keil & R. A. Wilson (Eds.), Explanation and cognition (pp. 279–298). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callaghan, T., Rochat, P., Lillard, A., Claux, M. L., Odden, H., Itakura, S., Tapanya, S., & Singh, S. (2005). Synchrony in the onset of mental-state reasoning: Evidence from five cultures. Psychological Science, 16, 378–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chittka, L., & Niven, J. (2009). Are bigger brains better? Current Biology, 19, 995–1008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corsi, P. (2005). Before Darwin: Transformist concepts in European natural history. Journal of the History of Biology, 38, 67–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (2006). The God delusion. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Cruz, H., & De Smedt, J. (2007). The role of intuitive ontologies in scientific understanding—The case of human evolution. Biology & Philosophy, 22, 351–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farah, M. J., & Rabinowitz, C. (2003). Genetic and environmental influences on the organization of semantic memory in the brain: Is “living things” an innate category? Cognitive Neuropsychology, 20, 401–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1981). Representations: Philosophical essays on the foundations of cognitive science. Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. (2001). In the shadow of the modern synthesis? Alternative perspectives on the last fifty years of paleoanthropology. Evolutionary Anthropology, 10, 5–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, H. L., & Frith, C. (2003). Functional imaging of ‘theory of mind’. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 77–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, S. A. (2004). Psychological essentialism in children. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 404–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, S. A., & Wellman, H. M. (1991). Insides and essences: Early understandings of the non-obvious. Cognition, 38, 213–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glass, B. (1979). Milestones and rates of growth in the development of biology. Quarterly Review of Biology, 54, 31–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1991). Signal, decision, action. Journal of Philosophy, 88, 709–722.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. (1997). Words, thoughts and theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J. (2004). Demography and cultural evolution: How adaptive cultural processes can produce maladaptive losses—The Tasmanian case. American Antiquity, 69, 197–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., & Boyd, R. (2002). On modeling cognition and culture. Why cultural evolution does not require replication of representations. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 2, 87–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herbert, S. (2005). The Darwinian revolution revisited. Journal of the History of Biology, 38, 51–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1964). The effect of essentialism on taxonomy—Two thousand years of stasis. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 15, 314–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G. (in press). Evolutionary debunking arguments. Noûs.

  • Kelemen, D. (2004). Are children “intuitive theists”? Reasoning about purpose and design in nature. Psychological Science, 15, 295–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leakey, R. E., & Walker, A. C. (1976). Australopithecus, Homo erectus, and the single species hypothesis. Nature, 261, 572–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthew, P. (1831). On naval timber and arboriculture; with critical notes on authors who have recently treated the subject of planting. London: Longman, Rees, Orme, Brown & Green.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1982). The growth of biological thought. Diversity, evolution and inheritance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay, R. T., & Dennett, D. C. (2010). The evolution of misbelief. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 493–510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, R., Owens, S. J., & Rørslett, B. (2011). Plants and colour: Flowers and pollination. Optics and Laser Technology, 43, 282–294.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray, M. (2008). Four arguments that the cognitive psychology of religion undermines the justification of religious belief. In J. Bulbulia, R. Sosis, E. Harris, R. Genet, C. Genet, & K. Wyman (Eds.), The evolution of religion: Studies, theories, and critiques (pp. 393–398). Santa Margarita: Collins Foundation Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osawa, A., & Maeshima, S. (2009). Gerstmann’s syndrome in a patient with left thalamic hemorrhage. Neurology Asia, 14, 161–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2000). The evolution of knowledge. In P. Carruthers & A. Chamberlain (Eds.), Evolution and the human mind. Modularity, language and meta-cognition (pp. 170–206). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2005). So how does the mind work? Mind and Language, 20, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and proper function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Price, G. (1972). Extension of covariance selection mathematics. Annals of Human Genetics, 35, 485–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Real, L. A. (1991). Animal choice behavior and the evolution of cognitive architecture. Science, 253, 980–986.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reid, T. (1764). An inquiry into the human mind, on the principles of common sense. Edinburgh: Millar, Kincaid & Bell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (1997). Teleological semantics. Mind, 106, 279–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samarapungavan, A., & Wiers, R. W. (1997). Children’s thoughts on the origin of species: A study of explanatory coherence. Cognitive Science, 21, 147–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saxe, R., Tenenbaum, J., & Carey, S. (2005). Secret agents: Inferences about hidden causes by 10- and 12-month-old infants. Psychological Science, 16, 995–1001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaffer, M. (2008) Bayesianism, convergence and social epistemology. Episteme, 5, 203–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shtulman, A., & Schulz, L. (2008). The relation between essentialist beliefs and evolutionary reasoning. Cognitive Science, 32, 1049–1062.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelishch, P. B. (1982). A quantitative study of biologists in the 18th and 19th centuries. Scientometrics, 4, 317–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shultz, T. R. (1982). Causal reasoning in the social and nonsocial realms. Canadian Journal of Behavioural Science, 14, 307–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. S., Phillips, A., & Woodward, A. L. (1995). Infants’ knowledge of object motion and human action. In D. Sperber, D. Premack, & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cognition. A multidisciplinary debate (pp. 44–78). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stamos, D. N. (2005). Pre-Darwinian taxonomy and essentialism—A reply to Mary Winsor. Biology & Philosophy, 20, 79–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephens, C. L. (2001). When is it selectively advantageous to have true beliefs? Sandwiching the better safe than sorry argument. Philosophical Studies, 105, 161–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart-Williams, S. (2005). Innate ideas as a naturalistic source of metaphysical knowledge. Biology & Philosophy, 20, 791–814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, P. R. (2009). Objects limit human comprehension. Biology & Philosophy, 24, 65–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wägner-Dobler, R., & Berg, J. (1999). Physics 1800–1900: A quantitative outline. Scientometrics, 46, 213–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waxman, S. (2005). Why is the concept ’living thing’ so elusive? Concepts, languages, and the development of folkbiology. In W. K. Ahn, R. L. Goldstone, B. C. Love, A. B. Markman, & P. Wolff (Eds.), Categorization inside and outside the laboratory. Essays in honor of Douglas L. Medin (pp. 49–67). Washington: American Psychological Association.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M., & Muldoon, R. (2009). Epistemic landscapes and the division of cognitive labor. Philosophy of Science, 76, 225–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Igor Douven, Krist Vaesen, and an anonymous reviewer, for helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper, and Lesley De Cruz for help with programming in Mathematica. This research is supported by the Research Foundation Flanders and grant COM07/PWM/001 from Ghent University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Helen De Cruz.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary material (MPEG 1536 kb)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

De Cruz, H., De Smedt, J. Evolved cognitive biases and the epistemic status of scientific beliefs. Philos Stud 157, 411–429 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9661-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9661-6

keywords

Navigation