Skip to main content
Log in

Defeating Manipulation Arguments: Interventionist causation and compatibilist sourcehood

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Causation is a morass in which I for one refuse to set foot. Or not unless I am pushed.

—Peter van Inwagen (1983: 65)

… man is the source and begetter of his actions as a father is of his children… If we cannot trace back our actions to starting points other than those within ourselves, all actions in which the initiative lies in ourselves are in our power.

—Aristotle (Nicomachean Ethics III: 5)

Abstract

We use recent interventionist theories of causation to develop a compatibilist account of causal sourcehood, which provides a response to Manipulation Arguments for the incompatibility of free will and determinism. Our account explains the difference between manipulation and determinism, against the claim of Manipulation Arguments that there is no relevant difference. Interventionism allows us to see that causal determinism does not mean that variables outside of the agent causally explain her actions better than variables within the agent, whereas the causal source of a manipulated agent’s actions instead lies outside of the agent in the intentions of the manipulator. As a result, determined agents can have free will and be morally responsible in a way that manipulated agents cannot, contrary to what Manipulation Arguments conclude. In this way, our account demonstrates not only how Manipulation Arguments fail but also how compatibilism can be strengthened by means of a plausible account of causal sourcehood.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Exceptions include some agent-causal libertarians (e.g., O’Connor 1995), and more recently compatibilists such as Vihvelin (2013), Sartorio (e.g., 2013), Ismael (2013) and Roskies (2012).

  2. Determinism is sometimes defined in terms of entailment: a description of the universe at a time, in conjunction with the laws of nature, entails descriptions of the universe at other times (e.g., van Inwagen 1983).

  3. We will accept for the sake of argument the stipulation that Diana, as described, is nomologically possible, despite its being questionable whether she is.

  4. We use “Manipulation Argument” broadly to include Mele’s Zygote Argument. Debates have raged about whose intuitions are relevant to these arguments (e.g., McKenna 2014b, 2008; Mele 2013; Pereboom 2008). We take the consensus view that our audience is well-informed readers who are undecided (or neutral) about the compatibility of determinism and free will.

  5. McKenna defends the hard-line response, yet maintains that the compatibilist “needs to hold that an agent can be the ultimate source of her will and her acts even if there is a deterministic explanation for them that traces back to factors for which she is not ultimately responsible” (2014a: 85). We agree that determinism does not rule out the sort of sourcehood relevant to free will. If McKenna came to agree with us that some forms of intentional manipulation do rule out this sort of sourcehood, perhaps he would agree that our soft-line response should be deployed against arguments that appeal to such forms of manipulation.

  6. We do not take a stand on whether Manny lacks free will entirely or whether he has less or a lesser sort than Danny. We maintain that the Manipulation Argument fails if the NoDif Premise is false, and, contra Todd (2011), that offering a principled difference between manipulation and determinism that is relevant to the degree to which an agent is free or responsible is enough to show that this premise is false. For discussions of degrees of moral responsibility, see Nelkin (2016), Khoury (2014), Capes (2013), Coates and Swenson (2013) and Tierney (2013).

  7. See footnote 10, below, for an explanation of why this is so.

  8. We are defining causal sourcehood in terms of the causal variable that has the strongest invariance relation to the effect variable. However, because strength of invariance allows for relative comparisons between causal variables, we could also define relative causal sourcehood among selected causal variables (see also footnote 13). In cases in which the strength of invariance obtaining between Diana’s decision and Manny’s stealing is equal to that obtaining between the output of Manny’s CAS and his stealing, Diana and Manny may share equal responsibility. Similarly, different causal contributions may result in assignments of different degrees of responsibility to Diana and Manny (see footnote 6). This feature of our view enables us to deal with cases in which Diana’s decision is, for instance, only slightly more or less invariant as a cause of Manny’s stealing than the output of Manny’s own CAS is.

  9. The examples of Romeo and the iron filings are drawn from James (1890: 20).

  10. This is why the second of our two conditions on strength of causal invariance is important. In the case of Diana and Manny, condition (1) alone cannot explain whether DD or instead Manny is more strongly invariant regarding Steal. Yet in cases of “online” manipulation, where things do not work out as Diana had intended, such that she has to remain online and ready to step in again to ensure the outcome, condition (1) always shows that DD is more strongly invariant. The Manipulation Argument, however, is about “offline” manipulation—Diana makes an initial change to ensure that Steal takes a specific value (via Manny), after which she goes offline and allows events to unfold without stepping in again. As we will show, condition (2) explains why, in offline manipulation, DD is more strongly invariant regarding Steal than Manny is.

  11. Or imagine that Zeus, a more powerful deity than Diana, does not care about whether Manny steals the wallet. Yet he is settled on this: Either Diana decides to create Manny’s zygote in a particular way (which, as it happens, will result in Manny’s stealing the wallet) or Zeus will interfere to make Diana do so (i.e., Zeus is a Frankfurt-style intervener). In the actual case, Diana decides on her own; Zeus does nothing. Is Zeus the causal source of Manny’s stealing? No. Zeus’s deciding to do nothing is not an actual cause of Steal = s. So it is not the causal source of Steal = s, even though had Diana decided differently, it would have been. (Thanks to Al Mele for suggesting this case.) Similar reasoning indicates how our view offers a parsimonious account of Frankfurt (1969) cases. In such cases, the Frankfurt intervener (Black) can ensure what an agent (Jones) decides, but when we consider whether Jones is morally responsible in the actual case where Black does nothing, Black is not an actual cause of Jones’ decision, and hence Black is not the causal source of that decision. Instead, Jones is.

  12. The same is true in Pereboom’s cases 1 and 2, where neuroscientists can ensure, by manipulating Plum’s brain, that his action is caused by their relevant intentions. In case 3, it is less clear how the community that raises Plum could ensure his action. To respond to soft-line responses that reference the manipulator’s intentions, Pereboom introduces alterations to his cases involving a spontaneously generated machine or force field that produces the same outcome in Plum. Pereboom suggests these alterations are irrelevant to his argument (e.g., 2014: 79), but in these cases the causal invariance relation collapses, since those causes will not produce the action across different background conditions (our condition 2), nor would interventions on the values of the relevant variables (e.g., on the force field) cause systematic changes to Plum’s actions (our condition 1) (See Sect. 5 below.).

  13. We noted earlier (footnote 8) that since strength of invariance allows for relative comparisons among causal variables, we could also define relative causal sourcehood among selected causal variables. Doing so would alter some of the preceding presentation, but it would still support the conclusion that Diana’s decision is a relatively stronger causal source of Manny’s stealing than any variable in Manny’s CAS, whereas there is no causal source in Danny’s distant past that is a relatively stronger causal source of his decision than variables in his CAS.

  14. Recent studies indicate that ordinary causal judgments track the distinctions that our causal sourcehood condition suggests. In studies about manipulation cases, when people read that a manipulator causes another agent to do what she intends, they judge her to be the cause of, and responsible for, the relevant action (or to be more so than the manipulated agent), whereas people do not make those judgments (or not as strongly) when the manipulator causes another agent to do the same thing, but without the manipulator intending it (e.g., Murray and Lombrozo 2016; Phillips and Shaw 2014; Sripada 2012).

  15. An exception, of course, is for causal variables like Diana’s decision, since Diana is stipulated to be capable of controlling for a maximally wide range of possible changes to the background conditions (something we doubt is nomologically possible).

  16. In fact, there may be need for explicit contrastivity (Deery 2013); however, we do not have space to develop that point here.

  17. Even if a suitable invariance relation could be identified between some event(s), X, in the distant past and Danny’s decision (Danny), our conditions on strength of causal invariance would show that there would rarely, if ever, be a strong causal invariance relation between X and Danny, since X = x would not cause Danny = d across a wide range of changes to C.

  18. We also maintain that interventionism can be fruitfully applied to other debates about free will. For instance, it can explain why the agent in a Frankfurt case (1969) is the causal source of her action whereas the counterfactual intervener is not, offering a more parsimonious explanation of the lessons of those cases (see footnote 11). Additionally, interventionism can help to explain away features of our experience of free agency that appear to implicate indeterminism (Deery 2015). We hope to further develop these applications of interventionism in future work.

  19. Versions of this paper were presented at Duke University (March 22, 2013), the University of Fribourg, Switzerland (June 18, 2013), the Flickers of Freedom blog (July 2013), the University of Montreal (November 29, 2013), the 40th Annual Meeting of the Society for Philosophy and Psychology (June 20, 2014), and the University of Nevada, Las Vegas (October 24, 2014). Thanks to audiences at those venues for helpful comments. We also thank Terry Horgan, Derk Pereboom, Al Mele, Michael McKenna, Jenann Ismael, Carolina Sartorio, Adina Roskies, Paul Russell, Jonathan Phillips, Dylan Murray, Bryan Chambliss, Alex Von Stein, Yael Lowenstein, and several anonymous referees for their helpful comments and suggestions.

References

  • Aristotle. 350 BC/2011. Nicomachean ethics (R. C. Bartlett & S. D. Collins, Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Ayer, A. J. (1954). Freedom and necessity. Philosophical essays (pp. 271–284). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. C. (2013). Freedom, creativity, and manipulation. Noûs, 49(3), 560–588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2010). Control variables and mental causation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 110, 15–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capes, J. (2013). Mitigating soft compatibilism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 87(3), 640–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1979). Causal laws and effective strategies. Noûs, 13, 419–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coates, J., & Swenson, P. (2013). Reasons-responsiveness and degrees of responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 165, 629–645.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deery, O. (2013). Absences and late preemption. Theoria, 79(4), 309–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deery, O. (2015). Why people believe in indeterminist free will. Philosophical Studies, 172(8), 2033–2054.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demetriou, K. (2010). The soft-line solution to Pereboom’s four-case argument. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 88(4), 595–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1984). Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2000). Responsibility, history and manipulation. The Journal of Ethics, 4(4), 385–391.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1969). Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. Journal of Philosophy, 66(23), 829–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, 68(1), 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haji, I., & Cuypers, S. (2006). Hard- and soft-line responses to Pereboom’s four-case manipulation argument. Acta Analytica, 21(4), 19–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (2001). The intransitivity of causation revealed in equations and graphs. Journal of Philosophy, 98(6), 273–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ismael, J. (2013). Causation, free will, and naturalism. In H. Kincaid, J. Ladyman, & D. Ross (Eds.), Scientific metaphysics (pp. 208–235). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (1996). The significance of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khoury, A. (2014). Manipulation and mitigation. Philosophical Studies, 168(1), 283–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J. (2014). How to be a humean interventionist. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89(2), 333–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lagnado, D., Gerstenberg, T., & Zultan, R. (2013). Causal responsibility and counterfactuals. Cognitive Science, 37, 1036–1073.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Menzies, P. (2009). Nonreductive physicalism and the limits of the exclusion principle. Journal of Philosophy, 106, 475–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lombrozo, T. (2010). Causal–explanatory pluralism: How intentions, functions, and mechanisms influence causal ascriptions. Cognitive Psychology, 61(4), 303–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, K. E., & Canon, L. K. (1975). Environmental noise level as a determinant of helping behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 32(4), 571–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2012). The interventionist account of causation and the basing relation. Philosophical Studies, 159, 357–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2008). A hard-line reply to Pereboom’s four-case manipulation argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77(1), 142–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2014a). Compatibilist ultimacy: Resisting the threat of Kane’s U-condition. In D. Palmer (Ed.), Libertarian free will: Contemporary debates (pp. 71–87). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2014b). Resisting the manipulation argument: A hard-liner takes it on the chin. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89(2), 464–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (1995). Autonomous agents: From self-control to autonomy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2006). Free will and luck. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2013). Manipulation, moral responsibility, and bullet biting. Journal of Ethics, 17(3), 167–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P. (2004). Causal models, token causation, and processes. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 820–832.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mickelson, K. (2015). The zygote argument is invalid: Now what? Philosophical Studies, 172(11), 2911–2929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, D., & Lombrozo, T. (2016). Effects of manipulation on attributions of causation, free will, and moral responsibility. Cognitive Science. doi:10.1111/cogs.12338.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, D. (2016). Difficulty and degrees of moral praiseworthiness and blameworthiness. Noûs, 50(2), 356–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, T. (1995). Agent causation. In T. O’Connor (Ed.), Agents, causes, and events: Essays on indeterminism and free will (pp. 173–200). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2008). A hard-line reply to the multiple-case manipulation argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77(1), 160–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2014). Free will, agency, and meaning in life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, J., & Shaw, A. (2014). Manipulating morality: Third-party intentions alter moral judgments by changing causal reasoning. Cognitive Science, 39(6), 1320–1347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ragland, C. P. (2011). Softening Fischer’s hard compatibilism. The Modern Schoolman, 88(1/2), 51–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roskies, A. (2012). Don’t panic: Self-authorship without obscure metaphysics. Philosophical Perspectives, 26(1), 323–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartorio, C. (2013). Making a difference in a deterministic world. Philosophical Review, 122(2), 189–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlosser, M. (2015). Manipulation and the zygote argument: Another reply. Journal of Ethics, 19(1), 73–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloman, S. A. (2005). Causal models: How people think about the world and its alternatives. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sripada, C. (2012). What makes a manipulated agent unfree? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(3), 563–593.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tierney, H. (2013). A maneuver around the modified manipulation argument. Philosophical Studies, 165(3), 753–763.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, P. (2011). A new approach to manipulation arguments. Philosophical Studies, 152(1), 127–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1983). An essay on free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vihvelin, K. (2013). Causes, laws, and free will: Why determinism doesn’t matter. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waller, R. R. (2014). The threat of effective intentions to moral responsibility in the zygote argument. Philosophia, 42, 209–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, G. (2000). Soft libertarianism and hard compatibilism. In M. Betzler & B. Guckes (Eds.), Autonomes Handeln: Beitrage zur Philosophie von Harry G. Frankfurt (pp. 59–70). Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weslake, B. (2006). Review of James Woodward, Making things happen. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84(1), 136–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1987). Sanity and the metaphysics of responsibility. In F. Schoeman (Ed.), Responsibility, character and emotions: New essays on moral psychology (pp. 46–62). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2015). Interventionism and causal exclusion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91(2), 303–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (Forthcoming). Interventionism and the missing metaphysics: A dialogue. In M. Slater and Z. Yudell (Eds.), Metaphysics and the philosophy of science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Yang, E. (2013). Eliminativism, interventionism and the overdetermination argument. Philosophical Studies, 164, 321–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Oisín Deery.

Additional information

Oisín Deery and Eddy Nahmias: Authorship is equal.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Deery, O., Nahmias, E. Defeating Manipulation Arguments: Interventionist causation and compatibilist sourcehood. Philos Stud 174, 1255–1276 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0754-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0754-8

Keywords

Navigation