Skip to main content
Log in

Preference for flexibility and dynamic consistency with incomplete preferences

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We generalize a previous result about dynamically consistent menu preferences to the case where preferences are not necessarily complete. We show that, as it is the case when preferences are complete, a subjective state space version of dynamic consistency is linked to a comparative theory of preference for flexibility. In words, an objective signal is interpreted as an event in the agent’s subjective state space and the agent acts in a dynamically consistent way after that if and only if we can attribute all the differences between the agent’s preferences before and after the signal to the fact that the agent values flexibility more before the signal than after.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Anaïs Cadilhac, Nicholas Asher, … Farah Benamara

Notes

  1. In fact, the first result of this kind was provided by Kreps (1979). However, Krep’s result was entirely ordinal and it is not possible to uniquely pin down the subjective state space in Krep’s representation. In DLR’s setup, the objects of choice are lotteries and the agent’s future preferences are of the expected utility type. This allowed them to uniquely identify the subjective state space in their representation theorem.

  2. Notation. We write \(\mathrm{supp}(\mu )\) to represent the support of the measure \(\mu\).

  3. Proof.  It is clear that if \(\succsim\) has a finite IPAEU representation, then it satisfies Finiteness. Conversely, fix a full-support lottery \(p\in \Delta (X)\) and let \(\delta >0\) be small enough so that \(E:=\{q\in \Delta (X):\left\| p-q\right\| \le \delta \}\in \mathrm{int}(\mathcal {X})\). As pointed out by Dekel et al. (2009), each boundary point of E maximizes a unique nontrivial expected utility preference in E and each nontrivial expected utility preference on \(\Delta (X)\) has a unique maximum in E, which is a boundary point. Therefore, if \(\succsim\) is not represented by a finite state space, it is clear that Finiteness is violated, as no finite subset of E is indifferent to that set.

  4. That is, \(\mathcal {M}_{T}\) is the set with the Bayesian updates of all the priors in \(\mathcal {M}\) that assign positive probability to the event T.

  5. If this is not true, we can work with menus \(\frac{1}{2}A+\frac{1}{2}\{p\}\) and \(\frac{1}{2}B+\frac{1}{2}\{p\}\), where p is any lottery with full support.

  6. That is, \(F\in \mathrm{int}(\mathcal {X})\) is such that \(F=\{q\in \Delta (X):\left\| p-q\right\| \le \delta \}\) for some \(p\in \Delta (X)\) and \(\delta >0\).

  7. See Footnote 3 above.

  8. As discussed in Remark 1, statement 2 of Theorem 2 implies that \(S^{*}\subseteq S\), so we in fact have that \(T=S^{*}\).

References

  • Aumann, R. J. (1962). Utility theory without the completeness axiom. Econometrica, 30(3), 445–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bewley, T. F. (2002). Knightian uncertainty theory: Part i. Decisions in Economics and Finance, 25(2), 79–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dekel, E., Lipman, B. L., & Rustichini, A. (2001). Representing preferences with a unique subjective state space. Econometrica, 69(4), 891–934.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dekel, E., Lipman, B. L., & Rustichini, A. (2009). Temptation-driven preferences. Review of Economic Studies, 76(3), 937–971.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dekel, E., Lipman, B. L., Rustichini, A., & Sarver, T. (2007). Representing preferences with a unique subjective state space: A corrigendum. Econometrica, 75(2), 591–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliaz, K., & Ok, E. A. (2006). Indifference or indecisiveness? choice-theoretic foundations of incomplete preferences. Games and Economic Behavior, 56, 61–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L. G., Marinacci, M., & Seo, K. (2007). Coarse contingencies and ambiguity. Theoretical Economics, 2, 355–394.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (1989). Maxmim expected utility with non-unique prior. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 18(2), 141–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kochov, A. (2020). Subjective states without the completeness axiom. In G. Bosi, M. J. Campión, J. C. Candeal, & E. Indurain (Eds.), Mathematical Topics on representations of ordered structures and utility theory, studies in systems, decision and control (pp. 255–266). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kopylov, I. (2009). Finite additive utility representations for preferences over menus. Journal of Economic Theory, 144, 354–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D. M. (1979). A representation theorem for “preference for flexibility”. Econometrica, 47(3), 565–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riella, G. (2008). Preference for flexibility and bayesian updating. Working Paper 177, Central Bank of Brazil.

  • Riella, G. (2013). Preference for flexibility and dynamic consistency. Journal of Economic Theory, 148, 2467–2482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarver, T. (2008). Anticipating regret: Why fewer options may be better. Econometrica, 76(2), 263–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stovall, J. E. (2010). Multiple temptations. Econometrica, 78(1), 349–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gil Riella.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Proofs

Proofs

1.1 Proof of Theorem 2

[1 \(\implies\) 2] Suppose \(\succsim\) and \(\succsim ^{*}\) are finite IPAEU preferences. Let S and \(S^{*}\) be the unique subjective state spaces of \(\succsim\) and \(\succsim ^{*}\), respectively, and let \(U:(S\cup S^{*})\times \Delta (X)\rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) be such that, for any \(s\in S\cup S^{*}\), U(s, .) is an expected utility function that represents s. Now suppose there exist two menus A and B with

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{p\in A}U(s,p)=\max _{p\in B}U(s,p)\text { for all }s\in S{\setminus } S^{*}, \end{aligned}$$
(1)

but either \(A\succsim ^{*}B\) and it is not true that \(A\succsim B\) or \(B\succsim A\) and it is not true that \(B\succsim ^{*}A\). Without loss of generality, we may assume that \(A,B\in \mathrm{int}(\mathcal {X})\).Footnote 5 Now suppose C is a menu such that \(A\cup B\cup C\sim ^{*}A\cup C\). By the representation of \(\succsim ^{*}\), this can happen only if

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{p\in A\cup B\cup C}U(s,p)=\max _{p\in A\cup C}U(s,p)\text { for all }s\in S^{*}. \end{aligned}$$

Together with (1), this implies that

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{p\in A\cup B\cup C}U(s,p)=\max _{p\in A\cup C}U(s,p)\text { for all }s\in S, \end{aligned}$$

which, by the representation of \(\succsim\), implies that \(A\cup B\cup C\sim A\cup C\). That is, \(\succsim\) and \(\succsim ^{*}\) violate Flexibility Consistency II.

[2 \(\implies\) 3] Now suppose statement 2 is true and let \((S,\mathcal {M},U)\) and \((S^{*},\mathcal {M}^{*},U^{*})\) be finite IPAEU representations of \(\succsim\) and \(\succsim ^{*}\), respectively. Fix any two menus A and B and let F be any sphere in \(\mathrm{int}(\mathcal {X})\).Footnote 6 Let C be the subset of F that includes only the maximizers of s for all \(s\in S{\setminus } S^{*}\) and let D be the subset of F that includes only the maximizers of s for all \(s\in S^{*}\).Footnote 7 For each \(\lambda \in (0,1)\), define \(A_{\lambda }:=C\cup (\lambda D+(1-\lambda )A)\) and \(B_{\lambda }:=C\cup (\lambda D+(1-\lambda )B)\). For \(\lambda\) large enough, we have that \(\max _{p\in A_{\lambda }}U(s,p)=\max _{p\in B_{\lambda }}U(s,p)=\max _{p\in C}U(s,p)\) for every \(s\in S{\setminus } S^{*}\) and \(\max _{p\in A_{\lambda }}U^{*}(s,p)-\max _{p\in B_{\lambda }}U^{*}(s,p)=(1-\lambda )( \max _{p\in A}U^{*}(s,p)-\max _{p\in B}U^{*}(s,p))\) for every \(s\in S^{*}\). By statement 2 and the representations of \(\succsim\) and \(\succsim ^{*}\), we get that

$$\begin{aligned} A&\succsim ^{*}{B}\\&{\iff} \\ A_{\lambda }&\succsim ^{*}{B_{\lambda }}\\&{\iff} \\ A_{\lambda }&\succsim{B_{\lambda }}\\&{\iff} \\ \sum _{s\in S}\mu (s)\max _{p\in A_{\lambda }}U(s,p)&\ge \sum _{s\in S}\mu (s)\max _{p\in B_{\lambda }}U(s,p)\text { for every }\mu \in \mathcal {M}\\&{\iff} \\ \sum _{s\in S\cap S^{*}}\mu (s)\max _{p\in A_{\lambda }}U(s,p)&\ge \sum _{s\in S\cap S^{*}}\mu (s)\max _{p\in B_{\lambda }}U(s,p)\text { for every }\mu \in \mathcal {M}\\&{\iff} \\ \sum _{s\in S\cap S^{*}}\mu (s)\max _{p\in A}U(s,p)&\ge \sum _{s\in S\cap S^{*}}\mu (s)\max _{p\in B}U(s,p)\text { for every }\mu \in \mathcal {M}. \end{aligned}$$

Define \(T:=S\cap S^{*}\).Footnote 8 It is clear that \((T,\mathcal {M}_{T},U)\) is a finite IPAEU representation of \(\succsim ^{*}\).

[3 \(\implies\) 1] Let \(\left( S,\mathcal {M},U\right)\) and \(\left( T,\mathcal {M}_{T},U\right)\) be finite IPAEU representations of \(\succsim\) and \(\succsim ^{*}\), respectively, where \(\mathcal {M}_{T}\) is the set with the Bayesian updates of all (possible) priors in \(\mathcal {M}\) after the observation of T. Now suppose that \(A\in \mathcal {X}\) and \(B\in \mathrm{int}\left( \mathcal {X}\right)\) are such that \(B\succsim A\), but it is not true that \(B\succsim ^{*}A\), or \(A\succsim ^{*}B\), but it is not true that \(A\succsim B\). It is clear that this can happen only if there exists \(s^{*}\in S{\setminus } S^{*}\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{p\in B}U\left( s^{*},p\right) >\max _{p\in A}U\left( s^{*},p\right) . \end{aligned}$$

We now show that this implies that there exists a menu C such that

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{p\in A\cup B\cup C}U\left( s,p\right) =\max _{p\in A\cup C}U\left( s,p\right) \text {, for every }s\in S^{*}\text {,} \end{aligned}$$
(2)

but

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{p\in A\cup B\cup C}U\left( s^{*},p\right) >\max _{p\in A\cup C}U\left( s^{*},p\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(3)

For each \(s\in S^{*}\), define \(q_{s}\) as follows: if \(\max _{p\in A}U\left( s,p\right) \ge \max _{p\in B}U\left( s,p\right)\), let \(q_{s}\) be any lottery in \(\arg \max _{p\in A}U\left( s,p\right)\). If \(\max _{p\in B}U\left( s,p\right) >\max _{p\in A}U\left( s,p\right)\) and there exists \(q\in \arg \max _{p\in B}U\left( s,p\right)\) with \(U\left( s^{*},q\right) <\max _{p\in B}U\left( s^{*},p\right)\), let \(q_{s}:=q\). We are left with the case where \(\max _{p\in B}U\left( s,p\right) >\max _{p\in A}U\left( s,p\right)\), but \(U\left( s^{*},q\right) =\max _{p\in B}U\left( s^{*},p\right)\) for all \(q\in \arg \max _{p\in B}U\left( s,p\right)\). We first note that this implies that it cannot be the case that \(U\left( s,.\right)\) is cardinally equivalent to \(-U\left( s^{*},.\right)\). If this was the case, we would necessarily have \(\max _{p\in B}U\left( s^{*},p\right) <\max _{p\in A}U\left( s^{*},p\right)\). Therefore, there exist lotteries p and \(p^{\prime }\) such that \(U\left( s,p\right) =U\left( s,p^{\prime }\right)\), but \(U\left( s^{*},p\right) <U\left( s^{*},p^{\prime }\right)\). Fix \(q\in \arg \max _{p\in B}U\left( s,p\right)\) and let \(\xi :=q+p-p^{\prime }\). Note that, for every \(\lambda \in \left( 0,1\right)\), \(U\left( s,\lambda q+\left( 1-\lambda \right) \xi \right) =U\left( s,q\right)\), but \(U\left( s^{*},\lambda q+\left( 1-\lambda \right) \xi \right) <U\left( s^{*},q\right)\). Since \(B\in \mathrm{int}\left( \mathcal {X}\right)\), we have \(\lambda q+\left( 1-\lambda \right) \xi \in \Delta \left( X\right)\) when \(\lambda\) is large enough. In this case, let \(q_{s}:=\lambda q+\left( 1-\lambda \right) \xi\) for some \(\lambda \in \left( 0,1\right)\) such that \(\lambda q+\left( 1-\lambda \right) \xi \in \Delta \left( X\right)\). Now define \(C:=\left\{ q_{s}:s\in S^{*}\right\}\). It is clear that (2) and (3) hold for such menu C and, consequently, \(A\cup B\cup C\sim ^{*}A\cup C\), but \(A\cup B\cup C\succ A\cup C\). That is, \(\succsim\) and \(\succsim ^{*}\) satisfy Flexibility Consistency II.

1.2 Proof of Proposition 1

Suppose \(\{S_{1},\dots ,S_{I}\}\), the collection of subjective state spaces of the relations \(\succsim _{1},\cdots ,\succsim _{I}\), is a partion of S, the subjective state space of \(\succsim\). Fix menus A and B in \(\mathrm{int}(\mathcal {X})\) with \(B\subseteq A\) and \(A\succ B\). Let \(U:S\times \Delta (X)\rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) be such that, for any \(s\in S\), \(U\left( s,.\right)\) is an expected utility function that represents s. There must exist \(s^{*}\in S\) such that \(\max _{p\in A}U(s^{*},p)>\max _{p\in B}U(s^{*},p)\). Since \(S_{1},\dots ,S_{I}\) are a partition of S, there exists a unique \(i^{*}\in \{1,\dots ,I\}\) such that \(s^{*}\in S_{i^{*}}\). Replicating the argument in the [3 \(\implies\) 1] part of the proof of Theorem 2, we can find a menu C such that \(\max _{p\in A\cup C}U(s,p)=\max _{p\in B\cup C}U(s,p)\) for every \(s\in S{\setminus }\{s^{*}\}\), while \(\max _{p\in A\cup C}U(s^{*},p)>\max _{p\in B\cup C}U(s^{*},p)\). This implies that \(A\cup C\sim _{i}B\cup C\) for every \(i\ne i^{*}\) and \(A\cup C\succ _{i^{*}}B\cup C\). That is, \(\succsim ,\succsim _{1},\cdots ,\succsim _{I}\) satisfy Flexibility Separability.

Conversely, suppose \(\succsim ,\succsim _{1},\cdots ,\succsim _{I}\) satisfy Flexibility Separability. If there exists \(s^{*}\in S{\setminus }\bigcup _{i=1}^{I}S_{i}\), then it is easy to find menus A and B in \(\mathrm{int}(\mathcal {X})\) with \(B\subseteq A\), \(A\succ B\), but \(A\sim _{i}B\) for \(i=1,\dots ,I\), which contradicts Flexibility Separability. We conclude that \(\bigcup _{i=1}^{I}S_{i}=S\). Now suppose there exist distinct \(i,j\in \{1,\dots ,I\}\) with \(S_{i}\cap S_{j}\ne \emptyset\). Pick any \(s^{*}\in S_{i}\cap S_{j}\). It is easy to build menus A and B in \(\mathrm{int}(\mathcal {X})\) with \(B\subseteq A\), \(\max _{p\in A}U(s,p)=\max _{p\in B}U(s,p)\) for every \(s\in S{\setminus }\{s^{*}\}\) while \(\max _{p\in A}U(s^{*},p)>\max _{p\in B}U(s^{*},p)\). Since \(\bigcup _{i=1}^{I}S_{i}=S\), this implies that \(A\succ B\). However, it is clear that, for any menu C, \(A\cup C\sim _{i}B\cup C\iff A\cup C\sim _{j}B\cup C\), which again contradicts Flexibility Separability. We conclude that \(\{S_{1},\dots ,S_{I}\}\) is a partition of S.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

de Moura, F.S., Riella, G. Preference for flexibility and dynamic consistency with incomplete preferences. Theory Decis 90, 171–181 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-020-09776-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-020-09776-y

Keywords

Navigation