Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Is it wrong for God to create persons? A response to Monaghan

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Some have put forward a normative principle that it is immoral and highly disrespectful to create free, rational creatures (like human beings) without their prior consent. (See, for instance, Monaghan in Int J Philos Relig 88(2):181–195, 2020) If true, this principle constitutes a new argument against the existence of God since it is logically impossible to acquire the consent of someone before they are created. Thus, God’s existence is taken to be incompatible with creating any persons. I shall examine this normative claim and show that it is not plausible. In the first place, it fails to meet three criteria that are commonplace to the “logical problem of evil.” In the second place, the principle has clear counterexamples that show many plausible exceptions that could justify God in creating persons.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Monaghan (2020).

  2. For reasons he does not provide, Monaghan still affirms the soundness of Mackie’s argument, see Monaghan, 182. For the sake of this argument, however, he is willing to grant that Mackie’s argument is unsound.

  3. Monaghan, “God* Does Not Exist.” Monaghan uses the phrase of a being’s “perfectly moral character,” which I shall echo in this paper. I think it would be more accurate to say, “morally perfect character,” but since nothing of consequence turns on the point, I’ll defer to Monaghan’s verbiage.

  4. Monaghan’s normative principle overlooks the possibility that the scenario may be an overwhelmingly objectively positive good for person y. For example, it is hard to imagine that y has been disrespected if x freely and knowingly pays off all of y’s debts that total over $50,000, and all of the other conditions specified above have been met. My further discussion of Monaghan’s principle brings out the implicit prima facie nature of the principle’s intended moral force or that it is a defeasible moral principle with implied exceptions to the stated rule.

  5. Monaghan, “God* Does Not Exist,” 186.

  6. The quotations around my use of “disrespect” and “disrespectful” throughout my article intend to convey that these actions conform for Monaghan’s definition of “disrespect,” not that they actually are disrespectful.

  7. The reasons Monaghan’s argument is against God* stem from his idiosyncratic ideas about the origins of the idea of God and his concern that the traditional attributes of God lead to incoherence. See Monaghan, 182–84.

  8. Hume (1993).

  9. Mill (1874), Ducasse (1953, chap. 15), Flew (1955), Mackie (1955) and McCloskey (1960).

  10. Compare how this type of argument is described by Pike (1963).

  11. Mackie, “Evil and Omnipotence,” 200.

  12. Mackie, 200.

  13. The logical problem of evil is exclusively framed as one of logical consistency in Beebe, (2005), Tooley, (2013, Sects. 1.2 & 2).

  14. Two of the most prominent accounts of the evidential argument from evil are Rowe (1979) and Draper (1989). For some evidence of the general consensus that the evidential problem of evil acknowledges that theism is logically compatible with some evil see the following reputable encyclopedia articles: Tooley, “The Problem of Evil”; Trakakis (2013).

  15. This is a central tenet of Rowe’s “friendly atheism.” See Rowe, “The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism,” 339–41.

  16. If someone believes that the essential difference between the logical and evidential formulations of the problem of evil is simply that former is logically deductive and the latter is probabilistic, then Monaghan’s argument cannot even meet this criterion if it is to maintain prima facie plausibility.

  17. Some modern accounts of the goodness of being include: MacDonald (1991), Delio, (2009) and Oderberg (2014).

  18. Augustine (2021). See also Augustine (1992, bk. 13.1).

  19. Anselm (1995).

  20. Aquinas (1920).

  21. For example, Swinburne (1998, Chap. 3) and Plantinga, (2002, Chap. 2).

  22. Adams (1989).

  23. Monaghan, “God* Does Not Exist,” 188. An anonymous reviewer helpfully points out that the EMT case seems to be in tension with Monaghan’s application of the principle to a surprise party (189), which he takes to be a morally wrong instance of “disrespect.” This is perplexing given that surprise parties seem to have no significant moral downside. This example seems to support an absolutist reading of Monaghan’s principle, rather than a prima facie or defeasible approach to it. I’ve opted to work with the prima facie reading of Monaghan’s principle because it is the most charitable to his overall argument in my view.

  24. Monaghan, 184.

  25. Monaghan, 187.

  26. See, for example, Parfit (1982), Parfit (1984, pt. 4), Shiffrin (1999), Harman (2004) and Roberts and Wasserman (2009).

  27. A notable exception is Adams (1972).

  28. Similarly, Richard Swinburne argues that God’s moral obligation to His creatures is analogous to the moral obligations of carers for their dependents. See Swinburne, Providence and the Problem of Evil, chap. 12.

  29. See Adams, “Must God Create the Best?,” 320. I have excluded Adams’s condition that the created person does not exist in the best of all possible worlds because I believe that this condition is trivially satisfied because there is no best possible world, and it is a complication that does not need to be addressed in this paper.

  30. I direct interested readers to the work of Marilyn Adams who attempts to answer this type of question in her provocative and insightful book, Adams (2000).

  31. Specifically, I have in mind the validity of “noseeum inferences” and the applicability of skeptical theism. See the following influential essays and the vast literature that responds to them: Wykstra (1984), Alston (1996) and Bergmann (2001). My preferred approach to skeptical theism is given in DePoe (2014), DePoe, (2017), DePoe, (forthcoming).

References

  • Adams, M. M. (1989). Horrendous evils and the goodness of god. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 63, 297–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, M. (2000). horrendous evils and the goodness of god. Cornell University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, R. M. (1972). Must god create the best? The Philosophical Review, 81(3), 317–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. (1996). Some (temporarily) final thoughts on evidential arguments from evil. In D. Howard-Snyder (Ed.), The evidential argument from evil (pp. 311–332). Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anselm (1995). Monologion and proslogion: With the replies of Gaunilo and Anselm. Translated by Thomas Williams. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Augustine. On Christian Doctrine. Retrieved 22 November, 2021. https://ccel.org/ccel/augustine/doctrine/.

  • Augustine (1992). The confessions. Translated by Henry Chadwick. Reprint ed. Oxford University Press.

  • Beebe, J. R. (2005). Logical problem of evil. In Fieser, J., & Dowden, B. (Eds.), Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/evil-log/.

  • Bergmann, M. (2001). Skeptical theism and Rowe’s new evidential argument from evil. Noûs, 35(2), 278–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delio, I. (2009). Is creation really good? Bonaventure’s position. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 83(1), 3–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DePoe, J.M. (2014) The epistemic framework for skeptical theism. In Dougherty, T., & McBrayer, J. P. (Eds.), Skeptical theism: New essays (pp. 32–44). Oxford University Press.

  • DePoe, J. M. (2017). Positive skeptical theism and the problem of divine deception. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 82(1), 89–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DePoe, J. M. (forthcoming) Skeptical theism. In McGrew, T.J., & Stewart, R. (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to Christian apologetics. Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Draper, P. (1989). Pain and pleasure: An evidential problem for theists. Noûs, 23, 331–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ducasse, C. J. (1953). A philosophical scrutiny of religion. Berlin: Ronald Press Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flew, A. (1955). Divine omnipotence and human freedom. In A. Flew & A. C. MacIntyre (Eds.), New essays in philosophical theology (pp. 144–169). SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, E. (2004). Can we harm and benefit in creating? Philosophical Perspectives, 18, 89–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1993). Dialogues and natural history of religion. In Gaskin, J. C. A. (Ed.). Reprint ed. Oxford University Press.

  • MacDonald, S. (Ed.). (1991). Being and goodness: The concept of the good in metaphysics and philosophical theology. Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1955). Evil and omnipotence. Mind, 64(254), 200–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, H. J. (1960). God and evil. The Philosophical Quarterly, 10(39), 97–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart. Three Essays on Religion. New York: Henry Holt and Company, 1874.

  • Monaghan, P. X. (2020). God* does not exist: A novel logical problem of evil. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 88(2), 181–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. S. (2014). Being and goodness. American Philosophical Quarterly, 51(4), 345–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1982). Future generations: Further problems. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 11(2), 113–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pike, N. (1963). Hume on evil. The Philosophical Review, 72(2), 180–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, C. (2002). Engaging god’s world: A christian vision of faith, learning, and living. Eerdmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, M. A., & Wasserman, D. T. (Eds.). (2009). Harming future persons: Ethics. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, W. L. (1979). The problem of evil and some varieties of atheism. American Philosophical Quarterly, 16(4), 335–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin, S. V. (1999). Wrongful life, procreative responsibility, and the significance of harm. Legal Theory, 5(2), 117–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (1998). Providence and the problem of evil. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas Aquinas (1920). Summa Theologica. Translated by Fathers of the English Domincan Province. 2nd edn. http://www.newadvent.org/summa/.

  • Tooley, M. (2013). The problem of evil. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/evil/.

  • Trakakis, N. (2013) Evidential problem of evil, the. In Fieser, J., & Dowden, B. (Eds.), Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. Retrieved 13 June, 2013. http://www.iep.utm.edu/evil-evi/.

  • Wykstra, S. J. (1984). The humean obstacle to evidential arguments from suffering: On avoiding the evils of ‘appearance.’ International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 16(2), 73–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John M. DePoe.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interests

This paper and its author(s) have no conflicts of interests or competing interests to declare.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

DePoe, J.M. Is it wrong for God to create persons? A response to Monaghan. Int J Philos Relig 93, 227–237 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-023-09862-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-023-09862-5

Keywords

Navigation