Skip to main content
Log in

Object-sensitivity versus cognitive penetrability of perception

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Notes

  1. Bruner (1957).

  2. Macpherson (2012); Siegel (2012); Stokes (2012).

  3. Pylyshyn (1999). This is also called “encapsulation” (Fodor (1983)) and been captured by Pylyshyn as the “independence thesis” (Pylyshyn (2004) p. 21).

  4. Deciding on what we “genuinely” perceive is certainly a highly controversial matter, and not one which is totally independent from the debates on the cognitive penetrability of perception. To step aside these controversies, it is cautious to proceed with a content that everyone accepts as perceptual. Both “austere” and “liberal” views of perceptual content (Bayne 2009) can accept that color is such a candidate.

  5. The color signal is processed in the primary visual cortex, V1, through the ventral stream V2–V4 and reaches higher cortical areas in the inferior temporal cortex (IT). See Gegenfurtner (2001).

  6. There is good evidence for outputs of color processing that are not consciously experienced. But our current concerns is with conscious experience only.

  7. Nor even an agreement on the possibility of such a causal account, as shown by the controversies between dualists and physicalists.

  8. Again, I leave illusions and hallucinations on the side, although they can be described as experiences when one has a phenomenal experience of seeing red.

  9. For an overview of the realism issue, see for instance Byrne (2003).

  10. Although not all definitions of modularity preserve the feature of encapsulation (see for instance Sperber), most of the classical definitions do (see Fodor, Pylyshyn) and most modularist are ready to grant it at least for perceptual modules. On this, see Deroy (in press).

  11. For instance, it cannot be assumed that perception is conceptual and its structure predicative because thought is.

  12. What is meant then by ‘similar’ needs to be further discussed, especially relative to the qualitative aspect of perception and the plausibility of the inverted spectrum scenario. If one grants this scenario, then there is still a minimal sense in which two inverted spectra perceive the world in similar ways if each of their qualitatively distinct feel remains correlated to one and the same set of stimuli.

  13. For instance, if cognitive penetration is virtuous, or leads to reliable beliefs, there is still room for the penetrated contents of perception to play a role in justifying beliefs in certain epistemological models, like reliabilism. Several moves are also available to the representationalists, which I won’t review here.

  14. Burge (2009).

  15. Munsell chip R/5/12. R indicates the hue, the first number the saturation and the second the “chroma”.

  16. Munsell chip YR/6/10 to R/3/8.

  17. This expression borrows from Block’s notion of “considered phenomenal judgment”, which he explains as follows: “Anyone who has been a subject in an experiment in which brief stimuli have to be compared knows that subjects are often uncertain—the stimulus goes by so fast the subjects often feel as if their responses are partly a matter of guessing. Allowing the subjects to try the judgment repeatedly with the ability to change the timing is a way of boosting the credibility of the conscious source of the judgment” (Block 2010, p. 41).

  18. Delk and Fillenbaum (1965, p. 293).

  19. R/4/12 for “red-associated”, R/4/13 for geometrical figures and R/5/13 for “brown-associated” ones.

  20. Hansen and Gegenfurtner (2006); Hansen et al. (2006).

  21. Macpherson (2012, p. 49).

  22. See Deroy (forthcoming).

  23. Although questions can be raised about the degree of control in Duncker (1939) and in Delk and Fillenbaum (1965). Several elements are missing from their paper—noticeably controls for size and complexity of the figures’ lines, and controls for variations in the illumination conditions.

  24. On the label assignment underlying this effect, see Waltz (1975).

  25. Attending first to the eye-shaped form and the two curvy lines of the drawing, the attentional selection will be dictated by the hypothesis that it is a beak and the content of its percept is more likely to be organized in a way that makes the experience duck-like. If one attends to the eye-shape and the opposite circular bumpy curve, its attention will be guided by the hypothesis that it is a nose, and its percept is more likely to be organized in a way that makes the experience rabbit-like. This explanation is more difficult to articulate than the previous one about the angles.

  26. See for instance Siegel (2012), Macpherson (2012).

  27. See Block (2010).

  28. E.g. to a surface reflecting the same wavelength under the same illumination conditions.

  29. No eye-tracking data for instance is given in any of these experiments.

  30. Fodor (1991) and Churchland (1988).

  31. Bolles et al. (1959); Bruner et al. (1951).

  32. Perky (1910). See also Segal and Gordon (1969).

  33. I don’t think that these difficulties are impossible to overcome, but that the model needs more development on several respects. First, the way phenomenal contents are supposed to mix is not clear, beyond the mental paint metaphor. I think that the notion of super-imposition is better, but stands in need of clarification. Second, the Perky effect, mentioned to ground the indirect model, shows the influence of subliminal perception on imagination, and not the influence of imagination on conscious perception. To support this later claim, Macpherson mentions the case of hallucinatory insertions in perceived scenes, which is still controversial. More needs to be said about this influence of imagination on perception. Third, it is not clear in which sense this mode is indirect: is it because of the necessary mediation of imagination, or because higher cognitive contents penetrate perception only through penetrating experience, and not through influencing the underlying perceptual processing? If it is the former, one could wonder how much of this model depends on the idea that beliefs have no phenomenology. If believing that this is an apple comes with some phenomenal contents, does this model turn into a direct model of cognitive penetration?

  34. Other conditions than time need to obtain, but this point is not necessary for the present argument.

  35. McGurk and McDonald (1976).

  36. This is known as the sweetness enhancement effect. See for instance Stevenson and Prescott (1999).

  37. Kubovy and Shutz (2010).

  38. Gegenfurtner (2003); Cant et al. (2008).

  39. See also Massaro (1999).

  40. See Deroy (in press) for a discussion.

References

  • Bayne, T. (2009). Perceptual experience and the reach of phenomenal content. Philosophical Quarterly, 59, 385–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2010). Attention and mental pain. Philosophical Issues, 20, 23–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolles, R. C., Hulicka, I. M., & Hanly, B. (1959). Colour judgment as a function of stimulus conditions and memory colour. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 13, 175–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. S. (1957). On perceptual readiness. Psychological Review, 64, 123–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. S., Postman, L., & Rodrigues, J. (1951). Expectation and the perception of color. American Journal of Psychology, 64, 216–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2009). Perceptual objectivity. The Philosophical Review, 118, 285–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A., & Hilbert, D. (2003). Philosophical issues about color vision. In A. Nadel (Ed.), Encyclopedia of cognitive science (pp. 173–184). New York: Nature Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cant, J. S., Large, M. E., McCall, L., & Goodale, M. A. (2008). Independent processing of form, colour, and texture in object perception. Perception, 37, 57–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1988). Perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality: A reply to Jerry Fodor. Philosophy of Science, 55, 167–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delk, J. L., & Fillenbaum, S. (1965). Differences in perceived colour as a function of characteristic color. The American Journal of Psychology, 78(2), 290–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deroy (in press) Modularity of perception. In M. Matthen (Ed.), Oxford handbook in philosophy of perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Duncker, K. (1939). The influence of past experience upon perceptual properties. The American Journal of Psychology, 52(2), 255–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1983). Modularity of mind. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1991). The dogma that didn’t bark. Mind, 100(2), 201–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gegenfurtner, K. R. (2003). Cortical mechanisms of colour vision. Nature Reviews, Neuroscience, 4, 563–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gegenfurtner, K. R., & Sharpe, L. T. (2001). Color vision. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, T., & Gegenfurtner, K. R. (2006). Color scaling of discs and natural objects at different luminance levels. Visual Neuroscience, 23, 603–610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, T., Olkkonen, M., Walter, S., & Gegenfurtner, R. (2006). Memory modulates color appearance. Nature Neuroscience, 9, 1367–1368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hering, E. (1877/1964). Outlines of a theory of the light sense. (L. M. Hurvich & D. Jameson, Trans.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Kubovy, M., & Shutz, M. (2010). Audio-visual objects. European Review of Philosophy, 7, 49–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. (2012). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84, 24–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Massaro, D. W. (1998). Perceiving talking faces: From speech perception to a behavioral principle. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massaro, D. W. (1999). Speech reading: Illusion or window into pattern recognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 3, 310–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGurk, H., & McDonald, J. (1976). Hearing lips and seeing voices. Nature, 264(5588), 746–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olkkonen, M., Hansen, T., & Gegenfurtner, K. R. (2008). Colour appearance of familiar objects: Effects of object shape, texture and illumination changes. Journal of Vision, 8(5), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perky, C. W. (1910). An experimental study of imagination. American Journal of Psychology, 21, 422–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition? The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 341–423.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (2004). Seeing and visualizing: It’s not what you think. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Segal, S. J., & Gordon, P. E. (1969). The Perky effect revisited: Blocking of visual signals by imagery. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 28, 791–797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2012) Cognitive penetrability of perception and perceptual justification. Noûs, 46, 201–222.

  • Stevenson, R., & Prescott, J. (1999). Confusing tastes and smells. Chemical Senses, 24, 627–635.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, D. (2012) Perceiving and desiring: A new look at the cognitive penetrability of experience. Philosophical Studies, 158, 477–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waltz, R. (1975). Understanding line drawings of scenes with shadows. In P. H. Wilson (Ed.), The psychology of computer vision (pp. 19–91). New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper was presented in NYU, Rutgers, at the Centre for the Study of the Senses and at the Institut Jean Nicod. Thanks to the audience for their questions, and especially to Jerome Dokic, Jerry Fodor, Michael Martin, Zenon Pylyshyn for helpful comments. Thanks to Ned Block, Yasmina Jraissati, Fiona Macpherson, Barry C. Smith and Frederique de Vignemont for their detailed comments on earlier versions of this draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ophelia Deroy.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Deroy, O. Object-sensitivity versus cognitive penetrability of perception. Philos Stud 162, 87–107 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9989-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9989-1

Keywords

Navigation