Skip to main content

PERSPECTIVE article

Front. Psychol., 27 October 2022
Sec. Gender, Sex and Sexualities

Stardust and feminism: A creatureliness agenda

  • Department of Psychology, Occidental College, Los Angeles, CA, United States

People are living, breathing creatures. Dominant feminist discourses are situated within hegemonic human exceptionalism (HHE) which, by framing the body in terms of human forms of meaning-making and social life, eschews first-order embodiment (or creatureliness) as worthy of inquiry. Here, well-known reasons for avoidance of “the biological” are briefly summarized and an argument is advanced for meta-theoretical centering of creatureliness. A three-pronged agenda is proposed that embraces the creaturely body without the “-isms” (e.g., essentialism) and “-izings” (e.g., so-called “naturalizing”) that subvert feminist commitments. By unsettling HHE, executing the agenda would promote broader feminist coalitions and new scholarly collaborations aimed at fleshing out gender.

Introduction

The universe began with a bang about 14 billion years ago. Transformations of stardust, energy, and gravity over the next 10 billion years yielded, among other things, Earth. After a billion years of cooling and declining acidity, life debuted, with every living thing from then on carrying hydrogen as old as the cosmos (Schrijver and Schrijver, 2020). Since then, a dazzling array of life forms has emerged and glided, trod, swum, sprouted, burrowed, and otherwise animated the globe.

Certain individuals spend time as a cell adrift in an aqueous milieu before metamorphosing into a bilaterally symmetrical tetrapod tethered to a host and then embarking on terrestrial life. There, they breathe air, eat, and defecate. They participate in a complex society in flexible ways contingent on, and constitutive of, body form and size, behavioral repertoires, social structure and composition, other life forms, and features of geography and climate (de Waal and Tyack, 2005).

These life forms—bonobos, elephants, humans, wolves, and others—live in ways that are enabled and constrained by their bodies, from the trillions of microbes each body hosts to overall mass, organ systems and specialized attunements to the world within and beyond the skin. They share some ways of living with blue whales, bluebirds, and bluebells. At the same time, each is in some ways distinctive at species, population, group, and individual levels and mutable on time scales from evolutionary to momentary. Sooner or later, they die.

What are the implications for gender studies of regarding humans not as “exceptional,” as minds housed in bodies that are inert input/output devices, as nodes or relations in networks, as wrought through human meaning-making, but rather as fully embodied creatures—as animals, as vertebrates, as mammals, as primates, as a particular sort of hominid? Taking up this question can spur scholarly and curricular innovation in service to feminism.

The rub: As Frost (2011) put it, “For feminist philosophers and theorists, the body as a living organism is a vexed object, so vexed, in fact, that in philosophical and theoretical work, it is often sidelined, bracketed, or ignored” (p. 69). Resolving that vexation can facilitate engaging the creaturely body without unduly constraining scholars’ prerogatives to focus on species and topics of interest.

Rejecting the body

Unger (1979) argued that gender should be distinguished from sex because “‘sex’ implies biological mechanisms” (p. 1085). Unger did not refute human corporeality or biological sciences. The concern was with connotations of “the biological”: genetic determinism, reductionism, sex-typed behaviors as “hard wired.” The specter of an immutable sex binary was antithetical to feminist knowledge and commitments. Defining gender as sociocultural aimed to disrupt “-izing”– the binarizing, essentializing, and so-called “naturalizing” that sex evoked.

Unger’s call fostered vital change but reinforced dichotomies that undermine its purpose. Its “fatal flaw” was that “[I]n separating the biological from the social, it inadvertently reified both. If sex is to the biological as gender is to the cultural, the nature/nurture dichotomy is reinscribed” (Crawford and Fox, 2007, p. 483). The gender/sex, social/biological, nurture/nature dichotomies map onto each other and conjure others: fluid/immutable, mind/body, human/animal (e.g., Brescoll and LaFrance, 2004; Logan and Johnston, 2007; Overton, 2013). Nurture/fluid is to mind/human as nature/immutable is to body/animal. Thus, a gender [social/mind/human] cluster that enacts hegemonic human exceptionalism (HHE) is split from a sex [biological/body/animal] cluster. This G/S split reflects and perpetuates gender-and race-based segregation and stratification in academia as in society at large (Dess, 2022). Frost (2011) observed:

[F] eminists have been more comfortable with denaturalizing nature than with what we might call ‘deculturalizing culture’ – or admitting that matter or biology might have a form of agency or force that shapes, enhances, conditions, or delimits the agency of culture. Yet, this wary reluctance, understandable as it is given historical precedent, is structured by an understanding of causation that binds feminists to the binaries they have otherwise been deconstructing… the concern about unwitting essentialism is bound by the terms of Cartesian dualism that put rationality, freedom, and agency on one side of an ontological divide and matter, passivity, and determinism on the other. (p. 76)

To realize feminist goals, the G/S split and its proxies must be replaced with richer formulations.

Reclaiming the body

The time is ripe to leverage the work of feminist biologists (Anne Fausto-Sterling, Patricia Adair Gowaty, Sarah Blaffer Hrdy, and others) and new materialists in psychology and other disciplines (e.g., Grosz, 1994; Alaimo and Hekman, 2008; Frost, 2011) into a paradigm shift away from HHE. Here, three proposals are offered in service of that goal.

Adopt language reforms

The term biological should be used to refer to academic enterprises. This shift attends to the suffix of biology, the study of living things, and what biologists do. This institutional meaning is routinely conflated with the stuff of life at low levels of organization (e.g., cells, biochemicals). Biologists also take up how life is organized at higher levels (e.g., sociality, ecology), but such work is less schematic for “the biological.” The topics that draw the biologist’s eye and how they are studied vary wildly. Dumping them into a bucket labeled “the biological” and distinguishing them from “the social” makes no sense, especially given that the latter lacks institutional meaning comparable to biological. More precise terms, such as genes or nervous system, should be used when referring to topics in biological sciences. Similarly, sociocultural constructs should be identified with specificity (see Magnusson and Marecek, 2018, on unpacking “the social”), not termed nonbiological. Nothing about life is nonbiological in the sense that cells are not involved, and the institutional meaning—to wit, “things biologists do not study”—is hopelessly vague.

Replacing “the biological vs. the social” with a bigger, better lexicon will make the G/S split obsolete. Because this reform explodes exceptionalist dichotomies that remove humans from nature (natural/artificial, nature/people, “humans and animals”; Dess and Chapman, 1998), it will neutralize “naturalizing.” How to repurpose the terms gender and sex (again) will need to be negotiated.

Adopt an updated view of biological sciences

Transformations in biology—including epigenetics, developmental psychobiology, neuroscience, and evolutionary theory—debunk the linkage of “the biological” to immutability and system justification. The working vocabulary includes terms such as contingent, probabilistic, dynamical, and path-dependent. Genes are not a “blueprint”: They are expressed variably and contingently on the environment, sometimes transgenerationally (Ghai and Kader, 2022). Similarly, developmental trajectories are viewed as sensitive to in utero and postnatal contexts. No vertebrate brain is “female” or “male”; brains develop and function flexibly, are largely the same within a species, and are conceptualized as a mosaic (Joel, 2021), inherently bisexual (Crews, 2012), and experience dependent (Hines, 2018).

Today’s evolutionary theory likewise is no tale of genetic determinism or hard wiring. Rejection of such simplistic notions is not new: Decades ago, seminal work on human mating strategies (Buss and Schmitt, 1993) refuted the notion that evolution yielded intractable sex differences, showing instead that “Mate preferences, far from being impervious to varying circumstances, are highly sensitive to temporal contextual conditions” (p. 230). The Integrated Synthesis (Pigliucci and Müller, 2010), which incorporates culture, multi-level selection, plasticity, and environmental control of gene expression, increasingly undergirds evolutionary theory in psychology. This project is actively underway (Narvaez et al., 2022) and would benefit from more feminist voices.

The call to overcome “biophobia” has come from psychologists (Salk and Hyde, 2012), sociologists (Freese et al., 2003), political scientists (Frost, 2011), and biologists [cf. Fausto-Sterling’s observation that “Culture shapes bones,” Fausto-Sterling, 2005, p. 1491]. Movement toward that end in gender scholarship and teaching must accelerate for the body to become more than inert matter or human meaning.

Adopt inclusive meta-theoretical frameworks

Grappling with massively complex phenomena requires a large tool kit and some division of labor. How can labor over gender be divided without devolving to proverbial blind men fighting over what an elephant is? A modest step would be adoption of meta-theoretical frameworks that locate scholarly enterprises in relation to each other. Two such frameworks distinguish levels of organization from macro to micro and time scales from deep time to nanoseconds (e.g., Bronfenbrenner, 1992; Li, 2003; Overton, 2013; Dess, 2022). Although the number and labeling of levels/scales are somewhat arbitrary, getting beyond two levels/scales prevents binaries, and labels can be negotiated. The point is to foster a shared understanding that although life exists at all levels of organization and on all time scales, a scholarly lens necessarily focuses on certain levels and scales. Such an understanding transforms “turfs” and “siloes” to equal-status locations in relation to each other, with some common and some distinctive interests and commitments.

A crucial premise is that everything about bodies at every level of organization is mutable on some time scale(s). Far from an exception, gender/sex expressions at all levels vary across time and contexts in many species (cf. Roughgarden, 2004). Anybody who regards gender/sex comparatively will anticipate the mixy/matchy, blendy/bendy nature of gender/sex in Homo sapiens, a globe-roaming, omnivorous, time-traveling, symbol-using, obligately social primate (de Waal, 2022).

The wide world of gender/sex features both variation and constraint. An example at the subcellular level: allosomes (traditionally called sex chromosomes). An XX/XY scheme is not necessary for reproduction, and being homogametic (e.g., XX) is not “essentially female.” Across deep time, allosomes have been a flexible tool in the adaptation kit. Vertebrate species have 0–10 allosomes. In some reptiles and birds, the heterogametic individuals lay eggs, and some can reproduce either sexually or parthenogenetically. Moreover, allosomes do not determine sex-typed mating behavior. Every A. uniparens lizard, for instance, has XXX allosomes, is a parthenogen, and displays mating behaviors typical of egg-and sperm-producing members of related species (O’Connell and Crews, 2022).

On an evolutionary timescale, then, allosomes are flexibly related to bodies and behavior. On a developmental timescale, gene expression is probabilistic and context dependent so, for example, an XY human zygote will not necessarily grow up to have a penis, produce sperm, identify as a man or rajul, or in myriad other ways be like other XY individuals. However, those forms of contingency and mutability are different from how allosomes vary within a species on shorter time scales. Regardless of identity or intrauterine or cultural environment, at some stage every somatic cell in a human born alive has 1–5 allosomes, with XX and XY being the highest-frequency variants (~99%). An XY zygote will not grow a uterus—regardless of sex assigned at birth and adult identity—and will not gestate a fetus, seek an abortion, or die giving birth. Human allosomes do not generate two human “kinds,” nor do they determine identity, behavior, lived experience, or social organization, validate treating gender as binary, or justify injustices. But they are matter that matters.

Using levels/scales frameworks to grapple with gender is compatible with conceptualizing bodies in symbolic, discursive, and cultural terms. In fact, it compels doing so. But it exposes the insufficiency of those (and any other) conceptualizations by illuminating domains of inquiry that are not tractable from those standpoints. These frameworks also illuminate paths to integration. Events at various levels of organization are presumed to interact through recursive loops on various time scales, and those loops pull for “cross-country” work. Research by Lisa Diamond, Sari van Anders, and Felicia Pratto exemplifies effective use of multi-level/scale, dynamical systems, and multi-method approaches to the complexity of gender.

Discussion

Reclaiming the body will allow feminists to take up in a more fulsome way the role of unmediated corporeal realities in individual and social well-being. For instance, it affords seeing the project of overturning Roe v. Wade as partly about women and partly about members of a mammalian species able to gestate a fetus. Reproductive rights (or lack thereof) have everything to do with the traditional stocks-in-trade of feminists, such as challenging patriarchy, championing sexual and economic autonomy, and interrogating how family is defined. They also have everything to do with risks borne only by individuals on the receiving end of internal fertilization and gestation. If, like salmon and sparrows, humans laid eggs, gendering would play out differently in policy, practice, and everyday life.

If too much attention to reproductive biology smells of essentialism, too little attention seems awfully bourgeois given class, national, and racial disparities in maternal and infant mortality. Furthermore, a compelling case can be made that patriarchal control of gametic female reproductive prerogatives has dire fitness consequences for all stakeholders (Gowaty, 2020). Theory and policy arguments incorporating first-order embodiment can usefully complement those rooted in discursive practices or disembodied rights.

To be clear, defensively burying the creaturely body is not unique to mainstream feminism. Doing so pervades academia (Dess, 2022), perhaps due to a core implication of corporeality: mortality (Solomon, 2020). A silver lining of HHE’s pervasiveness, however, is that rejecting it has tremendous potential to positively impact academic culture and society at large. As David Abram observes in Becoming Animal (Abram, 2010):

Becoming earth. Becoming animal. Becoming, in this manner, fully human… Corporeal life is indeed difficult… Thus do we shelter ourselves from the harrowing vulnerability of bodied existence. But by the same gesture we also insulate ourselves from the deepest wellsprings of joy… Awakening to citizenship in this broader commonwealth… has real ramifications for how we humans get along with one another. It carries substantial consequences for the way a genuine democracy shapes itself – for the way that our body politic breathes (emphasis original; pp. 3-9).

The reforms proposed here transform the term gender into an inclusive rubric that subsumes sex – to wit, a large repertoire of loosely associated characteristics that vary and are constrained at various levels of organization and on various time scales. Comprehensive understanding may elude, but a shared vision of an expanded scope of inquiry that is not rooted in HHE can move feminist scholarship in new directions.

Author contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.

Conflict of interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the author and do not necessarily represent those of the affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewer. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

Abram, D. (2010). Becoming animal: An earthly cosmology. New York: Pantheon.

Google Scholar

Alaimo, S., and Hekman, S. (Eds.) (2008). Material feminisms. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

Google Scholar

Brescoll, V., and LaFrance, M. (2004). The correlates and consequences of newspaper reports of research on sex differences. Psychol. Sci. 15, 515–520. doi: 10.1111/j.0956-7976.2004.00712.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bronfenbrenner, U. (1992). “Ecological systems theory,” in Six theories of child development: Revised formulations and current issues. ed. R. Vasta (London: Jessica Kingsley Publishers), 187–249.

Google Scholar

Buss, D. M., and Schmitt, D. P. (1993). Sexual strategies theory: an evolutionary perspective on human mating. Psychol. Rev. 100, 204–232. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.100.2.204

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Crawford, M., and Fox, A. (2007). From sex to gender and back again: co-optation of a feminist language reform. Fem. Psychol. 17, 481–486. doi: 10.1177/0959353507084333

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Crews, D. (2012). The (b)sexual brain. EMBO Rep. 13, 779–784. doi: 10.1038/embor.2012.107

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

de Waal, F. B. M. (2022). Different: Gender through the eyes of a primatologist. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

Google Scholar

de Waal, F. B. M., and Tyack, P. L. (2005). Animal social complexity: Intelligence, culture, and individualized societies. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

Dess, N. K. (2022). “The end of disembodied mind: fleshing out psychology,” in Routledge international handbook of theoretical and philosophical psychology. eds. B. D. Slife, S. C. Yanchar, and F. C. Richardson (New York: Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group), 55–77.

Google Scholar

Dess, N. K., and Chapman, C. D. (1998). “Humans and animals”? On saying what we mean. Psychol. Sci. 9, 156–157. doi: 10.1111/1467-9280.00030

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fausto-Sterling, A. (2005). The bare bones of sex: part 1—sex and gender. Signs 30, 1491–1527. doi: 10.1086/424932

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Freese, J., Li, J. A., and Wade, L. D. (2003). The potential relevances of biology to social inquiry. Annu. Rev. Sociol. 29, 233–256. doi: 10.1146/annurev.soc.29.010202.100012

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Frost, S. (2011). “The implications of the new materialisms for feminist epistemology,” in Feminist epistemology and philosophy of science. ed. H. E. Grasswick (New York: Springer), 69–83.

Google Scholar

Ghai, M., and Kader, F. (2022). A review on epigenetic inheritance of experiences in humans. Biochem. Genet. 60, 1107–1140. doi: 10.1007/s10528-021-10155-7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gowaty, P. A. (2020). “Violating the inviolable: evolved reproductive prerogatives of individual women,” in A multidisciplinary approach to embodiment: Understanding human being. ed. N. K. Dess (New York: Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group), 96–101.

Google Scholar

Grosz, E. (1994). Volatile bodies: Towards a corporeal feminism. New York: Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group.

Google Scholar

Hines, M. (2018). “Integrative psychobiology of gender development,” in Gender, sex, and sexualities: Psychological perspectives, eds. N. K. Dess, J. Marecek, and L. C. Bell (New York: Oxford University Press), 247–270.

Google Scholar

Joel, D. (2021). Beyond the binary: rethinking sex and the brain. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 122, 165–175. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2020.11.018

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Li, S. (2003). Biocultural orchestration of developmental plasticity across levels: the interplay of biology and culture in shaping the mind and behavior across the life span. Psychol. Bull. 129, 171–194. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.129.2.171

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Logan, C. A., and Johnston, T. D. (2007). Synthesis and separation in the history of nature and nurture. Devel. Psychobiol. 49, 758–769. doi: 10.1002/dev.20274

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Magnusson, E., and Marecek, J. (2018). “Setting the stage: gender, sex, and sexualities,” in Gender, sex, and sexualities: Psychological perspectives, eds. N. K. Dess, J. Marecek, and L. C. Bell (New York: Oxford University Press), 3–28.

Google Scholar

Narvaez, D., Moore, D. S., Witherington, D. C., Vandiver, T. I., and Lickliter, R. (2022). Evolving evolutionary psychology. Am. Psychol. 77, 424–438. doi: 10.1037/amp0000849

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

O’Connell, L. A., and Crews, D. (2022). Evolutionary insights into sexual behavior from whiptail lizards. J. Exp. Zool. 337, 88–98. doi: 10.1002/jez.2467

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Overton, W. F. (2013). A new paradigm for developmental science: relationism and relational-developmental systems. App. Devel. Sci. 17, 94–107. doi: 10.1080/10888691.2013.778717

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pigliucci, M., and Müller, G. B. (Eds.) (2010). Evolution, the extended synthesis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Roughgarden, J. (2004). Evolution's rainbow: Diversity, gender and sexuality in nature and people. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

Google Scholar

Salk, R. H., and Hyde, J. S. (2012). Contemporary genetics for gender researchers: not your grandma’s genetics anymore. Psychol. Women Q. 36, 395–410. doi: 10.1177/0361684312461774

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schrijver, I., and Schrijver, K. (2020). “The matter of life and death: how humans embody the universe,” in A multidisciplinary approach to embodiment: Understanding human being. ed. N. K. Dess (New York: Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group), 9–13.

Google Scholar

Solomon, S. (2020). “A brief history of death,” in A multidisciplinary approach to embodiment: Understanding human being. ed. N. K. Dess (New York: Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group), 27–32.

Google Scholar

Unger, R. K. (1979). Toward a redefinition of sex and gender. Am. Psychol. 34, 1085–1094. doi: 10.1037/0003-066X.34.11.1085

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: embodiment, gender, hegemonic human exceptionalism, creatureliness, new materialisms

Citation: Dess NK (2022) Stardust and feminism: A creatureliness agenda. Front. Psychol. 13:1039210. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2022.1039210

Received: 07 September 2022; Accepted: 20 September 2022;
Published: 27 October 2022.

Edited by:

Kath Woodward, The Open University, United Kingdom

Reviewed by:

Peter J. Marshall, Temple University, United States

Copyright © 2022 Dess. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Nancy K. Dess, dessnk@oxy.edu

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.