Skip to main content
Log in

The Darwinian muddle on the division of labour: an attempt at clarification

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is of philosophical and epistemological interest to examine how Darwin conceived the process of division of labour within Natural History. Darwin observed the advantages brought by division of labour to the human economy, and considered that the principle of divergence within nature, which is, according to him, one of the two ‘keystones’ of his theory, gave comparable advantages. This led him to re-examine Milne-Edwards’ view on the notion of division of physiological labour, and to introduce this with modifications into his naturalist writings. After a short review of the Darwinian historiography dealing with this issue, I first show the conceptual confusion into which Darwin plunges, when using a so-called economic argument to defend his thesis of the maximization of beings in a given territory due to division of labour. Following this I propose several hypotheses to explain these shifts, recurring in Darwin’s texts, from one conception and from one application to another, of the division of labour.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Richards (2012) showed that, in the absence of any systematic, continuous favouring of extreme forms (as in artificial selection), sympatric speciation was considered by Darwin as the only solution to render the process referred to by naturalists as the ‘swamping problem’, (i.e. the dilution of extremes due to the effects of interbreeding) compatible with the empirical correlations he discovered when studying Botanical Statistics, namely between dominant species (species with many individuals, spread out through several regions) and large genera and species (with many distinctive species and varieties, respectively). On the importance of these statistical studies in botany in the formation of Darwin’s thought, see also Browne (1980).

  2. Thanks to Robert Richards for the reminder that Darwin had crossed out the word ‘land’ and replaced it with the word ‘labour’ in his manuscript. On this point, see also Kohn (2009, p. 90).

  3. This difference in extension of the concept of division of physiological labour, and its implications, has been once well perceived by the first French translator of The Origin of Species, Clémence Royer (1875).

  4. Several objections and strong convictions led Darwin to have a number of reservations about the validity of the old idea of a linear hierarchy of organization or scale of beings. These objections and convictions concern: (1) the critical implications of his evolutionary theory, involving the inevitability of the reference to the environment in any axiological consideration of species; (2) the existence of degenerative processes in the evolution of many lineages (this is particularly the case in parasitism); (3) the existence of an irreducible plurality of branches, as shown by Cuvier and Von Baer; (4) the naturalists’ ambiguity and the lack of consensus within the naturalist community as to the identity of the criteria of perfection of beings, and even the impossibility of ever establishing any consensus on this point. Nevertheless, Darwin remained attached to the idea of a hierarchy of living forms, and occasionally could not resist indulging in reflections as to its rational basis. It is this concern which led him on occasion to consider the division of physiological labour, with precisely the meaning and extension that Milne-Edwards conferred to it (DL1.1) (intra-organic division, cooperation between divided parts, effect on organic productivity), as the best criterion of organic perfection. His correspondence with J.D. Hooker in the 1850’s notably confirms this point. Thus, in a letter dated 27 June 1854, Darwin states: “With respect to ‘highness’ & ‘lowness’, my ideas are only eclectic & not very clear. It appears to me that an unavoidable wish to compare all animals with men, as supreme, causes some confusions; & I think that nothing besides some such vague comparison is intended, or perhaps is even possible, when the question is whether two kingdoms such as the articulata or mollusca are the highest. Within the same kingdom, I am inclined to think that ‘highest’ usually means that form which has undergone most ‘morphological differentiation’ from the common embryo or archetype of the class; but then every now & then one is bothered (as Milne Edwards has remarked) by ‘retrograde development’, ie the mature animal having fewer & less important organs than its own embryo. The specialisation of parts to different functions, or ‘the division of physiological labour’ of Milne Edwards exactly agrees (& to my mind is the best definition when it can be applied) with what you state in your idea in regard to plants.” (Darwin 1989, p. 197).

  5. We can find other passages from Darwin which instead suggest that the suboptimal exploitation of resources by organisms is not clear proof of the adaptive superiority of the specialist over the generalist, or of the differentiated body (i.e. herbivore or carnivore) over the less differentiated body (i.e. omnivore). The specialist is generally a better competitor than the generalist, but the generalist could be better at seizing new and non-occupied niches, and evading the competition. In the Descent of Man (1871), for instance, Darwin writes: “It must not, however, be supposed that groups of organic beings are always supplanted and disappear as soon as they have given birth to other and more perfect groups. The latter, though victorious over their predecessors, may not have become better adapted for all places in the economy of nature. Some old forms appear to have survived from inhabiting protected sites, where they have not been exposed to very severe competition […] we must not fall into the error of looking at the existing members of any lowly-organised group as perfect representatives of their ancient predecessors.” (Darwin 1871, p. 212). See also the developments in the Origin (Darwin 1872, pp. 98–99 and 307) and in Animals and Plants (Darwin 1868, p. 8).

  6. Pearce, and others scholars he refers to, do not seem to see the problem of comparing preexisting organic roles in the body with a new and unoccupied place in nature: “As Limoges and others have suggested, it is likely that Darwin saw a parallel between this tendency of parts to take on diverse roles in the animal economy and the tendency of species to diverge into new places in the economy of nature.” (Pearce 2010, p. 515).

  7. One could recall for instance the fable from Jean de La Fontaine, Les Membres et l’Estomac (1668), which tells the poetic story of organs abandoning their duties toward the stomach one by one, as an allegory of a people’s abandonment of its royalty.

References

  • Balan, B. (1979). L’ordre et le temps. L’anatomie comparée et l’histoire des vivants au XIX e siècle. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beddall, B. G. (1988). Darwin and divergence: The wallace connection. Journal of the History of Biology, 21, 1–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouzat, J. L. (2014). Darwin’s diagram of divergence of taxa as a causal model for the origin of species. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 89, 21–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. J. (1984). Evolution: The history of an idea. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. J. (1988). The non-Darwinian revolution. Reinterpreting a historical myth. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bronn, H. G. (1858). Morphologische Studien über die Gestaltungsgesetze der Naturkörper überhaupt, und der organischen insbesondere. Leipzig: Winter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Browne, J. (1980). Darwin’s botanical arithmetic and the ‘principle of divergence’, 1854–1858. Journal of the History of Biology, 13, 53–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, W. (1977). Biology in the nineteenth century: Problems of form, function, and transformation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Hombres, E. (2012). The ‘division of physiological labour’: The birth, life and death of a concept. Journal of the History of Biology, 45, 3–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1842). The structure and distribution of coral reefs. London: Smith, Elder and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1851). Living Cirripedia: A monograph on the sub-class Cirripedia, with figures of all the species. The Lepadidæ; or Pedunculated Cirripedes. London: The Ray Society.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1859). On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural selection. London: J. Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1868). The variation of animals and plants under domestication. London: J. Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1871). The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex. London: John Murray.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1872). The Origin of Species [1859] (6th ed.). London: J. Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1975). In R. C. Stauffer (Ed.), Charles Darwin’s Natural Selection: Being the Second Part of his big Species Book written from 1856 to 1858. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Darwin, C. (1989). In F. Burkhardt & S. Smith (Eds.), The Correspondence of Charles Darwin. Volume 5, 18511855. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Darwin, C. (1991). In F. Burkhardt & S. Smith (Eds.), The Correspondence of Charles Darwin. Volume 7, 18581859. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Fleming, L. (2013). The notion of limited perfect adaptedness in Darwin’s principle of divergence. Perspectives on Sciences, 21, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foley, D. K. (2006). Adam’s fallacy. A guide to economic theology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Francois, J. F. (1990). Producer services, scale, and the division of labor. Oxford Economic Papers, 42, 715–729.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (2009). De l’économie à la biologie et retour: la sélection naturelle. In T. Martin (Ed.), L’unité des sciences aujourd’hui (pp. 13–25). Paris: Vuibert.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, S. (1989). Darwin and political economy: The connection reconsidered. Journal of the History of Biology22, 437–459.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (2002). The structure of evolutionary theory. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guillo, D. (2003). Les figures de l’organisation. Sciences de la vie et sciences sociales au XIX e siècle. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamowy, R. (1968). Adam Smith, Adam Ferguson and the division of labour. Economica, 35, 249–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. (1744). Three treatises: The first concerning art; the second concerning music, painting and poetry; the third concerning happiness. London: Nourse.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, J. (1985). Darwin as a lifelong generation theorist. In D. Kohn (Ed.), The Darwinian heritage (pp. 207–243). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, J. (2013). Darwin’s Book: On the Origin of Species. Science & Education, 22, 2267–2294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchison, T. W. (1988). Before Adam Smith: The emergence of political economy. Oxford: Basic Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, T. H. (1856). Lectures on general natural history. Medical Times and Gazette, 12, 429–432.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohn, D. (1980). Theories to works by: Rejected theories, reproduction, and Darwin’s path to natural selection. Studies in History of Biology, 4, 67–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohn, D. (1985). Darwin’s principle of divergence as internal dialogue. In D. Kohn (Ed.), The Darwinian heritage (pp. 245–257). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohn, D. (2009). Darwin’s keystone: The principle of divergence. In M. Ruse & R. J. Richards (Eds.), Cambridge companion to the origin of species (pp. 87–108). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leuckart, R. (1851). Über den Polymorphismus der Individuen oder die Erscheinung der Arbeitstheilung in der Natur. Giessen: Ricker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Limoges, C. (1968). Darwin, Milne-Edwards et le principe de divergence. Actes du XIIe Congrès International d’Histoire des Sciences. Paris: Blanchard, pp. 111–115.

  • Limoges, C. (1994). Milne-Edwards, Darwin, Durkheim and the division of labour: A case study in reciprocal conceptual exchanges between the social and natural sciences. In I. B. Cohen (Ed.), The natural sciences and the social sciences (pp. 317–343). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mandeville, B. (1714–1727). The fable of the bees; or private vices, publick benefits (2 Vols.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Marx, K. (1909). Capital. A critique of political economy. Volume I: The process of capitalist production [1867]. (S. Moore & E. Aveling, Trans. from the 3rd German edition) Chicago: C.H. Kerr and Co.

  • Maxwell, J. (1727). A treatise of the laws of nature (English translation and notes on Cumberland, Richard, 1727) London: R. Philipps.

  • Mayr, E. (1992). Darwin’s principle of divergence. Journal of the History of Biology, 25, 343–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, C. P., & Coffey, S. (1990). Measuring productivity in services. International Journal of Service Industry Management, 1, 46–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milne-Edwards, H. (1826). Nerfs. In J.B. Bory de Saint-Vincent (Ed.) Dictionnaire classique d’Histoire Naturelle (1822–1831), 17 volumes (Vol. 11, pp. 522–534). Paris: Rey et Gravier.

  • Milne-Edwards, H. (1851). Introduction à la zoologie générale. Paris: Masson.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Milne-Edwards, H. (1857–1881). Leçons sur la physiologie et l’anatomie comparée de l’homme et des animaux (14 volumes). Paris: Masson.

  • Myers, M. L. (1967). Division of labour as a principle of social cohesion. The Canadian Journal of Economics and Political Science, 33, 432–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, D. J. (2010). Biological atomism and cell theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 41, 202–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nyhart, L. K., & Lidgard, S. (2011). Individuals at the Center of Biology: Rudolf Leuckart’s Polymorphismus der Individuen and the ongoing narrative of parts and wholes. With an annotated translation. Journal of the History of Biology, 44, 373–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ospovat, D. (1979). Darwin after Malthus. Journal of the History of Biology, 12, 211–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ospovat, D. (1981). The development of Darwin’s theory: Natural history, natural theology, and natural selection, 1838–1859. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, T. (2010). ‘A great complication of circumstances’—Darwin and the economy of nature. Journal of the History of Biology, 43, 493–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perru, O. (1997). Le concept d’individualité biologique chez Milne-Edwards. Bulletin d’histoire et d’épistémologie des sciences de la vie, 4, 147–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi, K. (1957) [1944]. The great transformation: The political and economic origins of our time. Boston: Beacon Press.

  • Priestley, J. (1768). An essay on the first principles of government, and on the nature of political, civil and religious liberty. Dublin: J. Williams.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rashid, S. (1986). Adam Smith and the division of labour: A historical view. Scottish Journal of Political Economy, 33, 292–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, A. (2007). The theory of the cell state and the question of cell autonomy in nineteenth and early twentieth-century biology. Science in Context, 20, 71–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ricardo, D. (1817). On the principles of political economy and taxations. London: J. Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. J. (1992). The meaning of evolution: The morphological construction and ideological reconstruction of Darwin’s theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. J. (2012). Darwin’s principles of divergence and natural selection: Why Fodor was almost right. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 256–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Royer, C. (1875). Des sociétés dans la série organique. Bulletins de la Société d’anthropologie de Paris, 10, 622–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sapp, J. (2003). Genesis: The evolution of biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schabas, M. (1990). Ricardo naturalized: Lyell and Darwin on the economy of nature. In D. E. Moggridge (Ed.), Perspectives on the history of economic thought (Vol. 3, pp. 40–49). London: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schweber, S. (1980). Darwin and the political economists: Divergence of character. Journal of the History of Biology, 13, 195–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schweber, S. (1985). The wider British context in Darwin's theorizing. In D. Kohn (Ed.), The Darwinian heritage (pp. 35–69). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Séris, J. P. (1994). Qu’est-ce que la division du travail ?. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanahan, T. (2004). The evolution of Darwinism: Selection, adaptation and progress in evolutionary biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1776). An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations, 2 Vols.. London: W. Strahan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stamos, D. N. (2007). Darwin and the nature of species. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tammone, W. (1995). Competititon, the division of labour, and Darwin’s principle of divergence. Journal of the History of Biology, 28, 109–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tort, P. (1996). Division du travail physiologique et division du travail social. In P. Tort (Ed.), Dictionnaire du darwinisme et de l’évolution, 3 Vols (Vol. 1, pp. 1221–1237). Paris: Presses universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trembley, A. (1744). Mémoire pour servir à l’histoire d’un genre de Polypes d’eau douce, à bras en forme de cornes, 2 Vols.. Paris: Durand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weindling, P. (1981). Theories of the cell state in imperial Germany. In C. Webster (Ed.), Biology, medicine and society, 1840–1940 (pp. 99–155). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, R. M. (1990). Darwinism and the division of labour. Science as Culture, 9, 110–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper was the topic of a talk in a shortened form, initially in French, at the 19th Annual Congress of the Société d’Histoire et d’Epistémologie des Sciences de la Vie (France, Lyon, March 28–29 2013). I would like to address my acknowledgments to Richard Crossley and Wendy Charvet for their valued assistance in the English translation of the paper, and to Robert Richards for his attentive reading of a prior version of the manuscript. Many thanks also to my two anonymous reviewers for their very useful criticisms, commentaries and suggestions, and to Staffan Mueller-Wille, Editor in Chief of History and Philosophy of Life Sciences, who has kindly offered a scrupulous proofreading of the whole text.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emmanuel D’Hombres.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

D’Hombres, E. The Darwinian muddle on the division of labour: an attempt at clarification. HPLS 38, 1–22 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-015-0090-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-015-0090-x

Keywords

Navigation