Skip to main content
Log in

Classifying material implications over minimal logic

  • Published:
Archive for Mathematical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The so-called paradoxes of material implication have motivated the development of many non-classical logics over the years, such as relevance logics, paraconsistent logics, fuzzy logics and so on. In this note, we investigate some of these paradoxes and classify them, over minimal logic. We provide proofs of equivalence and semantic models separating the paradoxes where appropriate. A number of equivalent groups arise, all of which collapse with unrestricted use of double negation elimination. Interestingly, the principle ex falso quodlibet, and several weaker principles, turn out to be distinguishable, giving perhaps supporting motivation for adopting minimal logic as the ambient logic for reasoning in the possible presence of inconsistency.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To align the two hierarchies, one may consider \(\mathbf {Lk}\) as corresponding to DNE, \(\mathbf {Li}\) to EFQ, \(\mathbf {Le}\) to PP. One can easily see that \(\mathbf {Le}^\prime \) is stronger than \(\mathbf {Lj}\)+WT, but the latter has \(\mathcal {W}_3^\prime \) as a model, whereas the former does not. Similarly DGP, LEM, WLEM, \(\text {DGP}^\rightarrow \) do not seem to have any correspondence in Odintsov’s hierarchy.

  2. The version \(( \varphi \rightarrow \lnot \varphi )\rightarrow \lnot \varphi \) is used in [19]. However, since ex falso quodlibet falsum (\(\bot \rightarrow \lnot \phi \)) holds in minimal logic, that version is provable over minimal logic. This suggests that while the present work illustrates many distinctions, there are still more distinctions that are not apparent here.

  3. Our name for this is based on the guiding principle of the protagonist of Douglas Adam’s novel Dirk Gently’s Holistic Detective Agency [1] who believes in the “fundamental interconnectedness of all things.” It also appears as an axiom in Gödel-Dummett logic, and is more commonly known as (weak) linearity.

  4. The Wikipedia page at https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Consequentia_mirabilis actually lists this as equivalent to 6, however that is not quite correct as we can see below. If we add the assumption that \(\varphi \rightarrow \psi \equiv \lnot \varphi \vee \psi \), then they do turn out to be equivalent. However that statement—interpreting \(\rightarrow \) as material implication—is minimally at least as strong as LEM.

  5. Connexive logics are closely related. There, instead, the antecedent is taken as axiom schema; thus connexive logics are entirely non-classical, since \(\lnot (\varphi \rightarrow \lnot \varphi )\) is not classically valid.

  6. Since all of these axioms are not provable in minimal logic, deducing them classically is not mechanical and they are therefore good exercises for students.

  7. Of course this is intuitionistically provable/definitional.

  8. An axiom in Jankov’s logic, and De Morgan logic.

  9. With judicious substitutions—in particular, using \(\varphi \equiv \top \) in the right-to-left implications.

  10. \(\text {WT} \) is introduced properly in Sect. 4; for the derivations of \(\text {WT} \) from \(\text {PP} \) or \(\text {EFQ} \) see Prop. 4. These proofs, involving only implications, are best kept with the implicational fragment.

  11. A historical perspective can be found in e.g. [6], which establishes links with Diego’s Theorem. The present paper focuses on classifying several well-known principles into clearly worked out equivalences and distinctions.

  12. Simply use \(\vee \)-introduction and the proposed translation; EFQ follows. To translate \(\varphi \vee \psi \) as \(\lnot \varphi \rightarrow \psi \) would therefore be disingenuous.

  13. Note that negated conjunction is a special case.

  14. It is not clear, however, that this makes no difference in proofs; more on this later.

  15. It may be interesting to note that at least one instance of contraction is used in this proof.

  16. Substitute \(\varphi \rightarrow \vartheta \) for \(\alpha \), and \(\psi \rightarrow \vartheta \) for \(\beta \).

  17. This is a point of departure for many other non-classical logics, such as relevant logics, logics of formal inconsistency, and the like. As mentioned, this is a preliminary investigation into the realm of non-classical reverse mathematics more generally; so we stick fairly close to the usual, classical, interpretation of negation.

  18. This holds if, for example, \(\mathcal {W}\) is finite, or one assumes Zorn’s Lemma.

  19. Nor can they distinguish between DNE, LEM, and PP (see Proposition 12), but these are all known to be intuitionistically equivalent anyway; see Sect. 6.

  20. The converse does not hold. See the model \(\mathcal {W}_4\) in Sect. 6.

References

  1. Adams, D.: Dirk Gently’s Holistic Detective Agency. William Heinemann Ltd., UK (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Anderson, A.R., Belnap, N.D.: Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, vol. 1. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1975)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Arruda, A.I.: Aspects of the historical development of paraconsistent logic. In: Priest, G., Routley, R., Norman, J. (eds.) Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, pp. 99–130 (1989)

  4. Belnap, N.D.: A useful four-valued logic. In: Dunn, J.M., Epstein, G. (eds.) Modern Uses of Multiple-Valued Logic, pp. 5–37. Springer, Dordrecht (1977)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  5. Chagrov, A., Zakharyaschev, M.: Modal Logic. Oxford Logic Guides. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1997)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. de Lavalette, G.R., Hendriks, L., de Jongh, D.: Intuitionistic implication without disjunction. J. Logic Comput. 22(3), 375–404 (2010)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  7. Haack, S.: Deviant Logic, Fuzzy Logic: Beyond the Formalism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1996)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Heerkens, N.: Studies in Minimal Mathematics. Ph.D. thesis. Master’s Thesis, University of Amsterdam (2008)

  9. Hosoi, T., Ono, H.: Intermediate propositional logics (a survey). J. Tsuda Coll. 5, 67–82 (1973)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  10. Ishihara, H.: Reverse mathematics in bishop’s constructive mathematics. Philos. Scientiæ Cahier spécial 6, 43–59 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ishihara, H., Schwichtenberg, H.: Embedding classical in minimal implicational logic. Math. Logic Q. (2016). https://doi.org/10.1002/malq.201400099

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Maksimova, L.L.: Interpolation and definability in extensions of the minimal logic. Algebra Log. 44(6), 407–421 (2005). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10469-005-0038-4

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Maksimova, L.L.: On interpolation problem in paraconsistent extensions of the minimal logic. Electron. Notes Theor. Comput. Sci. 165, 107–119 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1016/j.entcs.2006.05.040

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  14. Odintsov, S.P.: Negative equivalence of extensions of minimal logic. Stud. L. Int. J. Symb. Log. 78(3), 417–442 (2004)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  15. Odintsov, S.P.: On the structure of paraconsistent extensions of Johansson’s logic. J. Appl. Log. 3(1), 43–65 (2005)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  16. Odintsov, S.P.: Constructive Negations and Paraconsistency. Trends in Logic. Springer, Cham (2008)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  17. Paoli, F.: Substructural Logics: A Primer Trends in Logic. Springer, Cham (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Priest, G., Routley, R., Norman, J. (eds.): Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent. Philosophia Verlag, Munich (1989)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Sainsbury, R.: Paradoxes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1995)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  20. Umezawa, T.: On logics intermediate between intuitionistic and classical predicate logic. J. Symb. Log. 24(2), 141–153 (1959)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  21. Veldman, W.: An intuitionistic completeness theorem for intuitionistic predicate logic. J. Symb. Log. 41(1), 159–166 (1976)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. Vizcaíno, P.F.V.: Some uses of cut elimination. Ph.D. thesis (2013)

  23. Weich, K.: Improving proof search in intuitionistic propositional logic. Ph.D. thesis (2001)

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maarten McKubre-Jordens.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This research was carried out while McKubre-Jordens was partially supported on Marsden Grant UOC1205, funded by the Royal Society of New Zealand; and Diener and McKubre-Jordens were partially funded by the Royal Society of New Zealand’s Counterpart Funding Initiative PIRE for the FP7 Marie Curie project CORCON.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Diener, H., McKubre-Jordens, M. Classifying material implications over minimal logic. Arch. Math. Logic 59, 905–924 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00153-020-00722-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00153-020-00722-x

Keywords

Mathematics Subject Classification

Navigation