Skip to main content
Log in

Appropriate Slurs

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. I have adapted this rough definition of “slur” from Jeshion (2013, 232). Hom (2010, 165), Anderson and Lepore (2013a, 25), and Bianchi (2014, 12) provide a similar gloss. Anderson and Lepore (2013b) distinguish acts of slurring from slurring words. The former, which may include offensive jokes, need not constitutively involve the use of conventional slurring words, such as “dago” and “kike.” I will restrict my discussion here to conventional slurs and bracket questions about other slurring acts.

  2. One alleged difference is that slurs have neutral counterparts, whereas particularistic pejoratives do not (see, e.g., Hay 2013, 456). A neutral counterpart of a slur s is a non-evaluative term that refers to s’ target group, e.g., “Italian” is a neutral counterpart to “wop” (Hornsby 2001). However, Ashwell (2016) argues that having a possible neutral counterpart is not a necessary condition on a word’s being a slur.

  3. Camp (2013, 338) and Jeshion (2013, 237) allow that derogatory attitudes toward certain groups may be warranted (in the sense of fitting), yet neither argues that derogation with slurs is morally permissible nor do they purport to give an account of what is morally valuable about group derogation.

  4. Camp (2013, 338) claims that slurs function to distance speakers from targets.

  5. Bell (2013) argues that responding to people who manifest certain vices with contempt is a good way to protest their failure to meet standards one cares about and to thereby maintain one’s own integrity. My argument here does not depend on the success of Bell’s. If she is right, contempt is one form of protest, yet protest need not be contemptuous (see, e.g., Hill 1979). While some theorists hold that slurs are conventional vehicles for expressing contempt (see, e.g., Richard 2008), a number of theorists deny this (see, e.g., Anderson and Lepore 2013a and Camp 2013). In any event, my aim here is not to motivate having a certain reactive attitude such as contempt but rather to defend the practice of slurring certain groups.

  6. Bernard Boxill suggests that to protest the violation of one’s rights is not necessarily to argue that one has the rights in question, and that often “people protest when the time for argument and persuasion is past” (Boxill 1976, 63).

  7. Smiley (2010) attributes to Tuomela (1989) the view that crowds and mobs may be collectively responsible for harm and destruction, despite the fact that members may not intend to perform group actions, as long as some of the members directly contribute to harm and others either facilitate these contributions or fail to prevent them.

  8. Relatedly, Lampert and Ervin-Tripp (1998) report that ridiculing members of an out-group serves to foster solidarity among the sexes. Saka (2007, 145) notes that appropriated uses of slurs can foster camaraderie among in-group members.

  9. We can also imagine antinatalists using “breeder” as a slur for anyone who reproduces, rather than heterosexuals specifically.

  10. Here I am following the convention, suggested by Padden and Humphries (1990), of using “Deaf” to refer to a cultural group consisting of people who use a sign language and feel a shared sense of solidarity, and using "deaf" to refer to individuals who have the audiological condition of being unable to hear yet do not necessarily consider themselves members of a Deaf community.

  11. McIntosh (2000) articulates a number of privileges afforded to people on the basis of their perceived whiteness.

  12. I take it one can ridicule someone on the basis of membership in a white supremacist group without also disparaging them on the basis of membership in an innocent vulnerable group (e.g., being unemployed or living below the poverty line).

  13. However, we can imagine beings that ought to be vulnerable because of the kind of beings they are (cf. May 2005). Suppose a “race” of parasitic alien invaders show up to Earth. Arguably, the use of slurs intended to make this group vulnerable need not be objectionable.

  14. This is not to suggest that the use of slurs is wrong only to the extent that targets are offended. As I noted above, the use of a slur may be impermissible because of its role in cultivating an objectionable identity, and utterances of a slur may do this independently of whether anyone finds them insulting.

  15. Cf. hooks (1995, 13) on the dangers of expressing rage as a member of a marginalized group: “We learned when we were very little that black people could die from feeling rage and expressing it to the wrong white folks. …Rage was reserved for life at home—for one another.”

  16. Killmister (2012) defends an account of group rights based on groups’ interest in preserving their identity and cultural practices that take into account challenges posed by noxious group (see, e.g., Barry 2001).

  17. I will leave it open whether people whose hearing is typical and are not vulnerable in other ways are morally permissible ostensible targets of the ORAL slur.

References

  • Anderson, L., & Lepore, E. (2013a). Slurring words. Nous, 47(1), 25–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, L., & Lepore, E. (2013b). What did you call me? Slurs as prohibited words. AnalyticPhilosophy, 54, 350–363.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (1999). Nicomachean ethics, 2nd ed. (trans: Irwin, T.). Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Ashwell, L. (2016). Gendered slurs. Social Theory and Practice, 42(2), 228–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (2001). Culture and equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauvoir, S. (1984). The second sex, translated by H. M. Pashley. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

  • Bell, M. (2013). Hard feelings: the moral psychology of contempt. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi, C. (2014). Slurs and appropriation: an echoic account. Journal of Pragmatics, 66, 35–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blum, L. (2002). “I’m not racist, but…”: the moral quandary of race. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blume, S. (2010). The artificial ear: cochlear implants and the culture of deafness. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolinger, R. J. (2015). The pragmatics of slurs. Nous. doi:10.1111/nous.12090

    Google Scholar 

  • Boxill, B. (1976). Self-respect and protest. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6, 58–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brontsema, R. (2004). A queer revolution: reconceptualizing the debate over linguistic reclamation. Colorado Research in Linguistics, 17, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2013). Slurring perspectives. Analytic Philosophy, 54, 330–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Card, C. (1995). Lesbian choices. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnaghi, A., Maass, A., & Fasoli, F. (2011). Enhancing masculinity by slandering homosexuals: the role of homophobic epithets in heterosexual gender identity. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 37(12), 1655–1665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christiansen, J. B., & Leigh, I. W. (2004). Children with cochlear implants: changing parent and deaf community perspectives. Archives of Otolaryngology: Head and Neck Surgery, 130(5), 673–677.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Croom, A. (2015). Slurs, stereotypes, and in-equality: a critical review of “how epithets and stereotypes are racially unequal”. Language Sciences, 52, 139–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellinas, A. A. (2013). The rise of golden dawn: the new face of the far right in Greece. South European Society and Politics, 18(4), 543–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Embrick, D. G., & Henricks, K. (2013). Discursive colorlines at work: how epithets and stereotypes are racially unequal. Symbolic Interaction, 36(2), 197–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferber, A. L. (1998). Constructing whiteness: the intersections of race and gender in US white supremacist discourse. Ethnic and Racial Studies, 21(1), 48–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glickman, N. S. (1996). The development of culturally deaf identities. In N. S. Glickman & M. A. Harvey (Eds.), Culturally affirmative psychotherapy with deaf persons (pp. 115–153). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grushkin, D. (2003). The dilemma of the hard of hearing within the U.S. deaf community. In L. Monaghan, C. Schmaling, K. Nakamura, & G. H. Turner (Eds.), Many ways to be deaf: international variation in deaf communities (pp. 114–140). Washington, DC: Gallaudet University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, J. (1999). Civilized oppression. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hay, R. (2013). Hybrid expressivism and the analogy between pejoratives and moral language. European Journal of Philosophy, 21(3), 450–474.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. (2012). Identity politics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/identity-politis.

  • Hill, T. (1979). Symbolic protest and calculated silence. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 9(1), 83–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holcomb, T. K. (2013). Introduction to American deaf culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hom, C. (2008). The semantics of racial epithets. Journal of Philosophy, 105(8), 416–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hom, C. (2010). Pejoratives. Philosophy Compass, 5(2), 164–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooks, B. (1995). Killing rage: ending racism. New York: Henry Holt and Co..

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (2001). Meaning and uselessness: how to think about derogatory words. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 25, 128–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jay, T. (2009). Do offensive words harm people? Psychology, Public Policy, and Law, 15(2), 81–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeshion, R. (2013). Expressivism and the offensiveness of slurs. Philosophical Perspectives, 27(1), 237–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Killmister, S. (2012). Why group membership matters: a critical typology. Ethnicities, 12(3), 251–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Killmister, S. (2014). Resolving the dilemma of group membership. In G. Balder, M. Bessone, & F. Zuolo (Eds.), How groups matter (pp. 89–108). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, W. (1995). Multicultural citizenship: a liberal theory of minority rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lampert, M. D., & Ervin-Tripp, S. M. (1998). Exploring paradigms: the study of gender and sense of humor near the end of the 20th century. In W. Ruch (Ed.), The sense of humor: exploration of a personality characteristic (pp. 231–270). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lane, H. (2005). Ethnicity, ethics, and the deaf-word. Journal of Deaf Studies and Deaf Education, 10(3), 291–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, R. (2005). Bad words: remarks on mark Richard’s ‘epithets and attitudes’. USC workshop in the linguistics/philosophy interface: syntax and semantics with attitude. Santa Cruz: University of California.

    Google Scholar 

  • McIntosh, P. (2000). White privilege and male privilege: a personal account of coming to see correspondences through work in women’s studies. In A. Minas (Ed.), Gender basics: feminist perspectives on women and men (2nd ed., pp. 30–38). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nunberg, G. (forthcoming). The social life of slurs. In D. Fogal, D. Harris, & M. Moss (Eds.), New work on speech acts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Padden, C., & Humphries, T. (1990). Deaf in America: voices from a culture. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Padden, C., & Markowicz, H. (1997). Learning to be deaf: conflicts between hearing and deaf cultures. In M. Cole, Y. Engstron, & O. A. Vasquez (Eds.), Mind, culture, and activity: seminal papers from the laboratory of comparative human cognition (pp. 418–431). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Queen, R. (2007). Sociolinguistic horizons: language and sexuality. Language and LinguisticCompass, 1(4), 314–330.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richard, M. (2008). When truth gives out. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ritchie, K. (2015). The metaphysics of social groups. Philosophy Compass, 10(5), 310–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saka, P. (2007). How to think about meaning. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smiley, M. (2010). Collective responsibility. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/collective-responsibility

  • Thoutenhoofd, E. D. (2000). Philosophy’s real-world consequences for deaf people: thoughts on iconicity, sign language and being deaf. Human Studies, 23, 261–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela (1989). Actions by collectives. Philosophical Perspectives, 3, 471–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (2012). The harm in hate speech. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Young, I. M. (1990). Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ralph DiFranco.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

DiFranco, R. Appropriate Slurs. Acta Anal 32, 371–384 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-016-0313-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-016-0313-0

Keywords

Navigation