Skip to main content
Log in

Time Scales and Levels of Organization

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The concept of levels of organization, despite its widespread scientific currency, has recently been criticized by a number of philosophers of science. This paper diagnoses the main source of problems facing theories of levels. On this basis, the problems with the usual criteria for distinguishing levels are evaluated: compositional relations, organizational types, and spatial scales. Drawing on some work on hierarchies in ecology, I argue in favor of an alternative conception of levels defined by the criterion of rates or time scales of processes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In case there is any doubt that there is such a classical levels of organization concept, one can consult virtually any standard textbook in biology or ecology. See, for instance, Campbell et al. (2011, 3 ff.), Molles (2008, 2 ff.), or Starr et al. (2009, 4 ff.)

  2. In discussions of levels of organization, it has become customary since Hull (1980) to differentiate biological entities as “interactors” or “replicators,” with interactors forming an “ecological hierarchy” and replicators forming a “genealogical hierarchy” (see Eldredge and Salthe 1984; Salthe 1985). The notion of levels of organization to be treated here is concerned with causal interaction in general rather than replication in particular, thus it is more similar to the ecological hierarchy. Unlike in Hull’s framework, however, it is not restricted to interactors conceived as units of selection—i.e. entities that interact with the environment “in such a way that replication is differential” (Hull 1980, 318).

  3. Note that with this formulation Craver offers only a “partial answer” (2007, 192) to the question of when two items are at the same level, in the form of a necessary condition (“only if”). However, other remarks seem to require there to be a sufficient condition as well. For example, it is said that like Wimsatt’s (2007) levels of organization, “Levels of mechanisms are also loci of stable generalizations, and consequently can be seen as local maxima of regularity and predictability. This is because parts of the mechanism that make an intelligible (that is, regular and predictable) contribution to the behavior of the mechanism as a whole are identified at levels” (Craver 2007, 190; see also ibid., 195). It is unclear how one could generalize over levels in this way without there being some sufficient condition for two parts to be at the same level. Since no sufficient condition is given elsewhere, it seems justifiable to examine the stated definition as if it comprised more than a partial account of the intralevel relation—as a potential necessary and sufficient condition. This interpretation fits with Bechtel’s (2008, 146 ff.) remarks on the intralevel relation.

  4. A partition is a level-like separation of a single part and its encompassing whole. I use the term “partition” here as an alternative to “level,” because whether partitions can successfully define levels is what is at issue. In the above symbolism, the partitions would include <M, C1, and S1> or <M, C2, and S2>—not <M, C1 and C2, and S1 and S2.>.

  5. The idea that an ontological account of higher levels is normatively constrained by what would be recognizable to the sciences indicates that the two kinds of hierarchy distinguished earlier—ontological hierarchies and hierarchies of the sciences—might not be so independent after all. In particular, the presence of functions and functionally individuated entities is an important differentiating factor between the physical sciences, on the one hand, and the biological and social sciences, on the other hand, and it often correlates with differences of level in ontological hierarchies. It may be useful in some contexts to trace this difference between sciences as a difference of “level,” reflecting different investigatory practices, interests, and/or different “levels of explanation.” Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out.

  6. Of course, the mechanistic account does not attempt to define a concept of level that can be used for systems like entire organisms, populations, or ecosystems, and probably none of its proponents would claim that such systems are mechanisms. The question, then, is whether there is some causal structure that should be captured by an account of levels but that is not accessible through the concept of mechanism.

  7. In documenting an evolutionary trend toward increased hierarchical structure in organisms, McShea (2001) usefully distinguishes between at least 10 organizational types based on their degree of internal nestedness and individualization (e.g., solitary prokaryotic cell, aggregate of prokaryotic cells, solitary eukaryotic cell, solitary metazoan, metazoan colony, etc.). Applied in the present context, McShea’s typology is limited by two factors: (1) it does not include types for symbiotic associations between organisms having different internal hierarchical structures (ibid., 412), and (2) it is restricted to entities that are homologous to organisms in a free-living state (408). As a result of (2), the entities referred to by these different types are not composed of each another—for example, “higher-level” solitary metazoans are not composed of “lower-level” solitary prokaryotes. McShea’s types are therefore not vertically arranged types in the same compositional hierarchy, but are organizational types for the organism level in different compositional hierarchies.

  8. The type-token distinction could also be applied to the members of mechanistic levels: in describing the mechanism of long-term potentiation one may be interested in the mechanism type or in a specific mechanism token. However, more recently, Craver (2015, 18) has suggested that only tokens are members of mechanistic levels. In general, token hierarchies face fewer consistency problems but sacrifice inferential and explanatory scope. Note also that allowing members of levels to be types does not imply that types are being used as the levels-criterion. The specific problems raised in 4.2 with using organizational types as a levels-criterion therefore do not affect compositional hierarchies of mechanism types or time scale hierarchies of process types.

  9. The individuation of processes is also discussed in the epistemological debate surrounding reliabilism. Reliabilism holds that a belief is epistemically justified iff it is the product of a reliable belief-forming process. A core problem, with several proposed solutions but no general consensus, concerns how to individuate “reliable belief-forming processes” (see Connee and Feldman 1998).

  10. For an argument against the categorial reducibility of certain thermodynamic processes to changes in the states of objects, see Needham (2013).

References

  • Allen, T. F. H., & Hoekstra, T. W. (1992). Toward a unified ecology. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, T. F. H., & Starr, T. B. (1982). Hierarchy: Perspectives for ecological complexity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashby, W. R. (1954). Design for a brain. New York: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, N. A., Reece, J. B., Urry, L. A., Cain, M. L., Wasserman, S. A., Minorsky, P. V., et al. (2011). Campbell biology (9th ed.). San Francisco: Pearson Benjamin Cummings.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connee, E., & Feldman, R. (1998). The generality problem for reliabilism. Philosophical Studies, 89, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2015). Levels. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND: 8(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F., & Bechtel, W. (2007). Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biology and Philosophy, 20, 715–734.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2012). Processes of life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2013). Living causes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 87, 19–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge, N., & Salthe, S. (1984). Hierarchy and evolution. Oxford Surveys in Evolutionary Biology, 1, 184–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, M. I. (2013). No levels, no problems: Downward causation in neuroscience. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 1042–1052.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, M. I. (2015). Levels of organization: A deflationary account. Biology and Philosophy, 30(1), 39–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis, 44, 50–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, B. C. (1963). Temporal organization in cells. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorban, A. N., & Radulescu, O. (2007). Dynamical robustness of biological networks with hierarchical distribution of time scales. IET Systems Biology, 1(4), 238–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1980). Individuality and selection. Annual Review of Ecology Evolution and Systematics, 11, 311–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalised. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levandowsky, M., & White, B. S. (1977). Randomness, time scales, and the evolution of biological communities. Evolutionary Biology, 10, 69–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, D., & Rossi, E. L. (Eds.). (1992). Ultradian rhythms in life processes. London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1961). Cause and effect in biology. Science, 134, 1501–1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McShea, D. (2001). The hierarchical structure of organisms: A scale and documentation of a trend in the maximum. Paleobiology, 27(2), 405–423.

  • Molles, M. C., Jr. (2008). Ecology: Concepts and applications (4th ed.). New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Needham, P. (2013). Process and change: From a thermodynamic perspective. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64, 395–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, R. V., DeAngelis, D. L., Waide, J. B., & Allen, T. F. H. (1986). A hierarchical concept of ecosystems. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheim, P., & Putnam, H. (1958). Unity of science as a working hypothesis. In H. Feigl, G. Maxwell, & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (pp. 3–36). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattee, H. (Ed.). (1973). Hierarchy theory. New York: Braziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perdikis, D., Huys, R., & Jirsa, V. (2011a). Complex processes from dynamical architectures with time-scale hierarchy. PLoS One, 6(2), e16589. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0016589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perdikis, D., Huys, R., & Jirsa, V. K. (2011b). Time scale hierarchies in the functional organization of complex behaviors. PLoS Computational Biology, 7(9), e1002198. doi:10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A., & McGill, B. (2012). The limitations of hierarchical organization. Philosophy of Science, 79, 120–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radulescu, O., Gorban, A. N., Vakulenko, S., & Zinovyev, A. (2006). Hierarchies and modules in complex biological systems. In Proceedings of the European conference on complex biological systems. Oxford, UK.

  • Rueger, A., & McGivern, P. (2010). Hierarchies and levels of reality. Synthese, 176, 379–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salthe, S. (1985). Evolving hierarchical systems: Their structure and representation. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2003). Is there a fundamental level? Noûs, 38(3), 498–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seibt, J. (2004). Free process theory: Towards a typology of occurrings. Axiomathes, 14, 23–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1962). The architecture of complexity. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 106, 467–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1973). The organization of complex systems. In H. Theory (Ed.), Pattee (pp. 3–27). New York: Braziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, P. (2003). Events. In M. Loux & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 357–385). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starr, C., Taggart, R., Evers, C., & Starr, L. (2009). Biology: The unity and diversity of life. Belmont, CA: Brooks/Cole.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steward, H. (2013). Processes, continuants, and individuals. Mind, 122, 781–812.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teggart, F. J. (1925/1977). Theory and processes of history. Repr. Berkeley: University of California Press.

  • Umerez, J., & Mossio, M. (2013). Constraint. In W. Dubitzky, O. Wolkenhauer, K. Cho, & Y. Yokota (Eds.), Encyclopedia of systems biology. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bertalanffy, L. (1969). General system theory. New York: Braziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waddington, C. H. (1957). The strategy of the genes. London: Routlege.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whyte, L. L., Wilson, A. G., & Wilson, D. (Eds.). (1969). Hierarchical structures. New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. (1972). Complexity and organization. In K. F. Schaffner & R. S. Cohen (Eds.), PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (pp. 67–86). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. (2007). Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author would like to thank Markus I. Eronen, Andreas De Block, Daniel S. Brooks, Jan Heylen, Jonathan Sholl, Stephan Güttinger, two anonymous referees, and the audience of the Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research at EASPLS 2014 for valuable input on earlier drafts of this paper.

Funding

This work was supported by an individual grant from the Scientific Research Fund—Flanders (FWO), and a postdoctoral fellowship from the Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James DiFrisco.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

DiFrisco, J. Time Scales and Levels of Organization. Erkenn 82, 795–818 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9844-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9844-4

Keywords

Navigation