Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Criminalizing Dangerousness: How to Preventively Detain Dangerous Offenders

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I defend a form of preventive detention through the creation of an offence of ‘being a persistent violent dangerous offender’ (PVDO). This differs from alternative proposals and actual habitual offender laws that impose extra periods of incarceration on offenders after they have completed the sentence for their most recent crime(s) or as a result of a certain number of prior convictions (as in three strikes laws). I, instead, would make ‘being a persistent violent dangerous offender’ an offence itself. Persons to be preventively detained (imprisoned) would be tried and convicted of this offence (on the usual standards of proof and after a criminal trial in which they enjoyed all the normal protections of due process and just criminal procedure). My approach would then have one significant advantage: provided the elements of being a PVDO could be rendered sufficiently determinate, punishing persons under such an offence would comport with central rule of law values, most importantly legality and fair notice, as well as principles of proportionality in sentencing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Duff (1998).

  2. Duff (1998, p. 161).

  3. Tonry (2006, p. 2).

  4. Tonry (2006, p. 11).

  5. Tonry (2006, p. 13).

  6. Tonry (2006, p. 31).

  7. Tonry (2006, p. 31).

  8. Tonry (2006, pp. 31–32).

  9. Floud and Young (1981).

  10. Walker (1982, pp. 282–283).

  11. Halliday et al. (2011, p. 538).

  12. Though increased use of compensatory awards paid to victims as part of criminal punishments could (partially) mitigate the impact of, at least, many crimes.

  13. Feeley and Simon (1992, p. 452).

  14. Feeley and Simon (1992, p. 455).

  15. Feeley and Simon (1992, p. 457).

  16. Feeley and Simon (1992, p. 458).

  17. Feeley and Simon (1992, p. 458). One might quibble with the claim that judgments about offenders’ character play no role in selective incapacitation when that strategy proceeds from assessments of ‘dangerousness’. And one might have hoped that the flip side Feeley and Simon identified—which would see lighter sentences imposed on lower-risk offenders—would have been followed more fully, rather than the steady escalation of all sentences, including those imposed on low-risk offenders, that we have seen.

  18. Zedner (2007, p. 261).

  19. Zedner (2007, p. 262).

  20. Zedner (2007, p. 262).

  21. Zedner (2007, p. 263).

  22. Zedner (2007, p. 264).

  23. Zedner (2007, p. 265).

  24. How violence is understood in criminal law has been explored by Alice Ristroph in an excellent article: Ristroph (2011).

  25. The distinction between attacks and endangerments is Duff’s: Duff (2007, Chap. 7).

  26. Though, as Stephen Morse points out, the U.S. Supreme Court has refused to make violence a constitutional requirement for civil commitment after an insanity plea: Morse (2004, fn. 36).

  27. O’Hear (2011).

  28. Husak (1998).

  29. Husak (1998).

  30. Duff (2007, pp. 106–107).

  31. Dimock (2012).

  32. Dimock (2012).

  33. Ashworth (2011).

  34. Duff (1998, p. 141).

  35. Duff (1998, p. 141).

  36. On the need to confine the dangerous offender laws to only seriously violent offenders, rather than just habitual offenders or recidivists, see Katkin (1972).

  37. Duff (1998, p. 152), quoting Morris (1992).

  38. Duff (1998, p. 153).

  39. Duff (1998, p. 155).

  40. Duff (1998, p. 155).

  41. On age as predictor of future violence: Gottfredson and Gottfredson (1994, p. 457); Robinson (1988, p. 23, fn. 17; Robinson (2001, p. 1451); and Robinson (2010, p. 1102).

  42. Walker (1982, p. 276).

  43. Gordon (1982, p. 300).

  44. Gordon (1982, p. 300).

  45. Walker (1982, p. 277).

  46. Morris and Miller (1985, p. 6).

  47. Morris and Miller (1985, p. 11).

  48. Morris and Miller (1985, p. 16).

  49. Morris and Miller (1985, p. 17).

  50. Morris and Miller (1985, p. 18) internal notes omitted.

  51. Morris and Miller (1985, p. 21).

  52. Morris and Miller (1985, p. 18).

  53. Modifying Morris and Miller (1985, p. 27).

  54. Robinson (1993).

  55. Robinson (2001).

  56. Robinson (2001, p. 1432), references to Webster’s New College Dictionary omitted.

  57. Robinson (2001, p. 1438).

  58. Robinson (2001, p. 1446).

  59. Robinson (2001, p. 1446).

  60. Robinson (2001, p. 1447). I’m not sure that something like ‘the least intrusive restraint adequate for protection’ and the entitlement to treatment where possible are not requirements even within deserved punishments for more standard crimes, however, so I’m not sure that this is quite the right position to take on these two issues. My contractarian inclinations might justify both a ‘minimum-restraint principle’ and an entitlement to services that would conduce to law-abidingness, but here I grant Robinson his assumptions to the contrary arguendo.

  61. Robinson (2001, p. 1450).

  62. Robinson (2001, p. 1452).

  63. On the need for clear communication with offenders to achieve the deterrent ambitions of the law, see Robinson and Darley (2003).

  64. Conrad (1982).

  65. Morris and Miller (1985, p. 21); Floud and Young (1981, p. xvii).

  66. Morris and Miller (1985, pp. 23-24) internal notes omitted.

  67. Floud and Young (1981, p. 55).

  68. Honderich (1982, p. 274).

  69. Montague (1999, p. 177).

  70. Montague (1999, p. 178).

  71. Finkelstein (2003) and (2013).

  72. Duff call such harms “secondary harms”: Duff (2005, p. 51).

  73. As, for example, Alexander and Ferzan (2008) would require.

  74. Victor Tadros defended something like this view at a workshop, and I think he was right to do so.

  75. Sorell (2011, p. 6). His topic is the more limited case of terrorism, rather than crimes of violence generally.

  76. Thus I largely agree with Ferzan’s treatment of self-defence in (2008).

  77. Morse (2004, p. 69).

  78. Morse (2004, p. 56).

  79. See Dimock (1997).

  80. Ashworth (2011, p. 242).

  81. Morris and Miller (1985, p. 14).

  82. Duff (1998); Bottoms and Brownsword (1982).

  83. Von Hirsch and Wasik (1997, p. 607).

  84. Gottfredson and Gottfredson (1994, p. 443).

  85. Robinson (2010, p. 1101).

  86. Morris and Miller (1985, p. 14 fn. 12).

  87. Morse (1994, 1996, 2002, 2004, 2011).

  88. Gottfredson and Gottfredson (1994, p. 462).

  89. Tonry (2006, pp. 32–34).

  90. Robinson (1997, p. 218), § 51 of his Draft Code of Conduct. He would require at least recklessness with respect to the risk: p. 225, § 200 of his Draft Code of Adjudication. Referenced in Duff (2005, p. 57, fn. 59).

  91. Morse (1994, 1996, 2002, 2004, 2011); Lippke (2008); objections to the blurring of retributive and preventive functions within criminal law have also been raised by Robinson (op. cit.).

  92. Lippke (2008, pp. 404–405).

  93. Hudson (1998) remains one of the best treatments of the issue.

References

  • Alexander, L. and K. Kessler Ferzan (2008). Culpable Acts of Risk Creation. Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 5, 375–406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashworth, A. (2011). The Unfairness of Risk-Based Possession Offences. Criminal Law and Philosophy 5, 237–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bottoms, A.E. and R. Brownsword (1982). The Dangerousness Debate after the Floud Report. British Journal of Criminology 22, 229–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad, J.P. (1982). The Quandary of Dangerousness. British Journal of Criminology 22(3), 255–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dimock, S. (1997). Retributivism and Trust. Law and Philosophy 16(1), 37–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dimock, S. (2012). Intoxication and the Act/Control/Agency Requirement. Criminal Law and Philosophy 6(2), 341–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R.A. (1998). Dangerousness and Citizenship. In A. Ashworth and M. Wasik (Eds.), Fundamentals of Sentencing Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R.A. (2005). Criminalizing Endangerment. In R.A. Duff and Stuart P. Green (Eds.) Defining Crimes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Duff, R.A. (2007). Answering for Crime: Responsibility and Liability in the Criminal Law (Oxford: Hart Publishing).

    Google Scholar 

  • Feeley. M.M. and J. Simon (1992). The New Penology: Notes on the Emerging Strategy of Corrections and Its Implications. Criminology 30(4), 449–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferzan, K.K. (2008). Self-Defense and the State. Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 5: 449–478.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finkelstein, C. (2003). Is Risk a Harm? University of Pennsylvania Law Review 151, 963–1001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finkelstein, C. (2013). Pragmatic Rationality and Risk. Ethics 123(4), 673–699.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floud, J. and W. Young (1981). Dangerousness and Criminal Justice (London: Heinemann).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R.A. (1982). Preventive Sentencing and the Dangerous Offender. British Journal of Criminology 22(3), 285–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gottfredson, S.D. and D.M. Gottfredson (1994). Behavioral Prediction and the Problem of Incapacitation. Criminology 32(3), 441–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halliday, S., J. Ilan and C. Scott (2011). The Public Management of Liability Risks. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 31(3), 527–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Honderich, T. (1982). On Justifying Protective Punishment. British Journal of Criminology 22(3), 268–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, B.A. (1998). Doing Justice to Difference. In A. Ashworth and M. Wasik (Eds.), Fundamentals of Sentencing Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husak, D. (1998). Does Criminal Liability Require an Act? In R.A. Duff (Ed.) Philosophy and the Criminal Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katkin, D. (1972). Habitual Offender Laws: A Reconsideration. Buffalo Law Review 21:99, 99–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lippke, R.L. (2008). No Easy Way Out: Dangerous Offenders and Preventive Detention. Law and Philosophy 27, 383–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, P. (1999). Justifying Preventive Detention. Law and Philosophy 18: 173–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, N. and M. Miller (1985). Predictions of Dangerousness. Crime and Justice 6(1), 1–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, N. (1992). Incapacitation within Limits. In A. von Hirsch and A.J. Ashworth (Eds.), Principled Sentencing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Morse, S.J. (1994). Culpability and Control. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 142, 1587–1660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morse, S.J. (1996). Blame and Danger: An Essay on Preventive Detention. Buffalo University Law Review 76, 141–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morse, S.J. (2002). Uncontrollable Urges and Irrational People. Virginia Law Review 88, 1025–1078.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morse, S.J. (2004). Preventive Confinement of Dangerous Offenders. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 32, 56–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morse, S.J. (2011). Mental Disorder and Crime. Journal of Criminal Law & Criminology 101, 885–968.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Hear, M.M. (2011). Beyond Rehabilitation: A New Theory of Indeterminate Sentencing. American Criminal Law Review 48(3), 1247–1292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ristroph, A. (2011). Criminal Law in the Shadow of Violence. Alabama Law Review 62(3), 571–622.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, P.H. (1988). Hybrid Principles for the Distribution of Criminal Sanctions. Northwestern University Law Review 82(1), 19–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, P.H. (1993). Forward: The Criminal-Civil Distinction and Dangerous Blameless Offenders. Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 83(4), 693–717.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, P.H. (1997). Structure and Function in Criminal Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson P.H. (2001). Punishing Dangerousness: Cloaking Preventive Detention as Criminal Justice. Harvard Law Review 114(5), 1429–1456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, P.H. (2010). The Ongoing Revolution in Punishment Theory: Doing Justice as Controlling Crime. Arizona State Law Journal 42, 1089–1111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, P.H. and J.M. Darley (2003). The Role of Deterrence in the Formulation of Criminal Law: At its Worst when Doing its Best. Georgetown Law Review 91, 949–1002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorell, T. (2011). Preventive Policing, Surveillance, and European Counter-Terrorism. Criminal Justice Ethics 30(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tonry, M. (2006). Purposes and Functions of Sentencing. Crime and Justice 34(1), 1–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Hirsch, A. and M. Wasik (1997) Civil disqualificationa attending conviction. Cambridge Law Journal 56.

  • Walker, N. (1982). Unscientific, Unwise, Unprofitable or Unjust? The Anti-Protectionist Arguments. British Journal of Criminology 22(3), 276–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zedner, L. (2007). Pre-crime and post-criminology? Theoretical Criminology 11(2), 261–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Antony Duff, Andrew Ashworth and Lucia Zedner for inviting me to participate in that thought-provoking event, to the many participants from whose insights I learned so much, and special thanks to my official commentator—Patrick Tomlin—whose comments forced me to rethink a number of fundamental issues in the paper and whose generosity has made the paper better than it would otherwise have been. Thanks are also due to participants of the CS-IVR meeting, June 1, 2013, especially Marc Ramsay.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Susan Dimock.

Additional information

This paper was originally prepared for the Robina Workshop on Preventive Justice, University of Minnesota Law School, September 21–22, 2012.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dimock, S. Criminalizing Dangerousness: How to Preventively Detain Dangerous Offenders. Criminal Law, Philosophy 9, 537–560 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-013-9270-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-013-9270-5

Keywords

Navigation