Skip to main content
Log in

Confusion about concessive knowledge attributions

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Concessive knowledge attributions (CKAs) are knowledge attributions of the form ‘S knows p, but it’s possible that q’, where q obviously entails not-p (Rysiew, Nous (Detroit, Mich.) 35:477–514, 2001). The significance of CKAs has been widely discussed recently. It’s agreed by all that CKAs are infelicitous, at least typically. But the agreement ends there. Different writers have invoked them in their defenses of all sorts of philosophical theses; to name just a few: contextualism, invariantism, fallibilism, infallibilism, and that the knowledge rules for assertion and practical reasoning are false. In fact, there is a lot of confusion about CKAs and their significance. I try to clear some of this confusion up, as well as show what their significance is with respect to the debate between fallibilists and infallibilists about knowledge in particular.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Brown J. (2006) Contextualism and warranted assertability manoeuvres. Philosophical Studies 130: 407–435. doi:10.1007/s11098-004-5747-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dell, M., Jones, B. F., & Olken, B. A. (2008). Climate change and economic growth: Evidence from the last half century. NBER Working Paper No. 14132.

  • DeRose K. (1991) Epistemic possibilities. The Philosophical Review 100: 581–605. doi:10.2307/2185175

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose K. (1996) Knowledge, assertion and lotteries. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 568–580. doi:10.1080/00048409612347531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose K. (2006) “Bamboozled by our own words”: Semantic blindness and some arguments against contextualism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73: 316–338. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2006.tb00620.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dougherty, T., & Rysiew, P. Fallibilism, epistemic possibility, and concessive knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (forthcoming).

  • Egan A. (2007) Epistemic modals, relativism, and assertion. Philosophical Studies 133: 1–22. doi:10.1007/s11098-006-9003-x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan A., Hawthorne J., Weatherson B. (2005) Epistemic modals in context. In: Preyer G., Peter G. (eds) Contextualism in philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fantl J., McGrath M. (2002) Evidence, pragmatics, and justification. The Philosophical Review 111: 67–94

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillies A., von Fintel K. (2008a) CIA leaks. The Philosophical Review 117: 77–98. doi:10.1215/00318108-2007-025

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillies A., von Fintel K. et al (2008) An opinionated guide to epistemic modals. In: Gendler T. (eds) Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 2). Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1989). Logic and conversation. In H. P. Grice (Ed.), Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press.

  • Groenendijk, J., & Stockhof, M. (1984). Studies on the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Amsterdam.

  • Groenendijk, J., & Stockhof, M. (1989). Type-shifting rules and the semantics of interrogatives. In G. Chierchia, B. Partee, & R. Turner (Eds.), Properties, types and meanings. Volume 2: Semantic issues. Kluwer Academic Publishers. Reprinted in Portner, P., & Partee, B. (Eds.). (2002). Formal semantics: The essential readings. Blackwell Publishing.

  • Hacking I. (1967) Possibility. The Philosophical Review 76: 143–168. doi:10.2307/2183640

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne J. (2004) Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill C., Schechter J. (2007) Hawthorne’s lottery puzzle and the nature of belief. Philosophical Issues 17: 102–122. doi:10.1111/j.1533-6077.2007.00125.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief. Cornell University Press.

  • Kratzer A. (1977) What ‘must’ and ‘can’ must and can mean. Linguistics and Philosophy 1: 337–355. doi:10.1007/BF00353453

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D. (1996) Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 549–567. doi:10.1080/00048409612347521

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. Epistemic modals are assessment-sensitive. In A. Egan, et al (Eds.), Epistemic Modality (forthcoming).

  • Rysiew P. (2001) The context-sensitivity of knowledge attributions. Nous (Detroit, Mich.) 35: 477–514. doi:10.1111/0029-4624.00349

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer J. (2004) From contextualism to contrastivism. Philosophical Studies 119: 73–103. doi:10.1023/B:PHIL.0000029351.56460.8c

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. The contrast-sensitivity of knowledge ascriptions. Social Epistemology (forthcoming a).

  • Schaffer, J. Knowledge in the image of assertion. Philosophical Issues, 18 (forthcoming b).

  • Schiffer S. (1996) Contextualist solutions to scepticism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96: 317–333

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. In Syntax and semantics (Vol. 9). Academic Press.

  • Stalnaker R. (1998) On the representation of context. Journal of Logic Language and Information 7: 3–19. doi:10.1023/A:1008254815298

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley J. (2004) On the linguistic basis for contextualism. Philosophical Studies 119: 119–146. doi:10.1023/B:PHIL.0000029353.14987.34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley J. (2005a) Knowledge and practial interests. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley J. (2005b) Fallibilism and concessive knowledge attributions. Analysis 65: 126–131. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8284.2005.00537.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephenson T. (2008) Judge dependence, epistemic modals, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy 30: 487–525

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teller P. (1972) Epistemic possibility. Philosophia 2: 303–320. doi:10.1007/BF02381591

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel J. (1999) The new relevant alternatives theory. Philosophical Perspectives: Epistemology 13: 155–180

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T. (2000) Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dylan Dodd.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dodd, D. Confusion about concessive knowledge attributions. Synthese 172, 381–396 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9400-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9400-0

Keywords

Navigation