Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wg55d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-24T16:46:53.542Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

From Symbolic Forms to Lexical Semantics: Where Modern Linguistics and Cassirer's Philosophy Start to Converge

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 September 2008

Daniel Dor
Affiliation:
Department of CommunicationsTel Aviv University

Abstract

Ernst Cassirer's theory of language as a symbolic form, one of the richest and most insightful philosophies of language of the twentieth century, went virtually unnoticed in the mainstreams of modern linguistics. This was so for what seems to be a good metatheoretical reason: Cassirer insisted on the constitutive role of meaning in the explanation of linguistic phenomena, a position which was explicitly rejected by both American Structuralists and Chomskian Generativists. In the last decade, however, a new and promising linguistic framework has emerged — the framework of lexical semantics — which seems to bear close theoretical resemblance to Cassirer's theory. In this paper, I show how the empirical results accumulated within the framework of lexical semantics serve to validate Cassirer's most fundamental philosophical insights, and suggest that Cassirer's philosophy helps position these empirical results in their appropriate epistemological context. I discuss the following fundamental points, which, for me, constitute the backbone of both Cassirer's philosophy and the theory of lexical semantics: (i) natural language grammars constitute structural reflections of a deeply-rooted, highly structured level of semantic organization; (ii) the representational level of linguistic meaning, which is prior to experience in the Kantian sense, comprises a partial set of semantic notions, which language selects as centers of perceptual attention; (iii) this partial set is potentially different from the sets selected by other symbolic forms, such as myth, science, and art; and (iv) linguistic variability is to be explained in universalistic terms, thus allowing for specific patterns of variability within universally-constrained limits.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bolinger, D. 1968. “Entailment and the Meaning of Structures.” Glossa 2: 119127.Google Scholar
Cassirer, E. 1944. An Essay on Man. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Cassirer, E. 1953. The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, Volume 1: Language. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Elkana, Y. 1998. “The Historical Sociology of Symbolic Forms.” Talk Given at the Workshop Titled Ernst Cassirer: Symbol, Science and Culture. Tel Aviv University.Google Scholar
Frawley, W. 1992. Linguistic Semazntics. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Rappaport-Hovav, M. and Levin, B.. 1997. “Building Verb Meanings.” In The Projection of Arguments: Lexical and Compositional Factors, edited by Butt, Miriam and Geuder, Wilhelm, 97134. Stanford, California: CSLI.Google Scholar
Urban, W. M. 1949. “Cassirer's Philosophy of Language.” In The Philosophy of Ernst Cassirer, edited by Schilpp, Paul A., 401442. Evanston: Library of Living Philosophers.Google Scholar