Skip to main content
Log in

Divine Hiddenness and Divine Humility

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

If God exists, and if our ultimate well-being depends on having a positive relationship with Him (which requires as a first step that we believe He exists), why doesn't He make sure that we all believe in Him? Why doesn't He make His existence obvious? This traditional theological question is today much-used as an argument for atheism. In this paper I argue that the answer may have something to do with God's character, specifically God's humility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Found in Velimirović, N., Saint (2008, p. 304).

  2. It is worth noting that while Keller rejects traditional theism, he is open to alternative models of God (specifically, process theology) and employs the problem of divine hiddenness more in support of such an alternative model (one on which God is not omnipotent and so may not have the power to reveal Himself to all) rather than atheism per se. My thanks to an anonymous referee for this point.

  3. To draw an analogy with the problem of evil: Schellenberg’s formulation is closer to the logical problem of evil, whereas those of Drange, Keller, and Maitzen are more like versions of the evidential problem of evil.

  4. See, for instance, Aijaz and Weidler (2007), Cullison (2010), Dumsday (2010a, b, 2012), Evans (2006, 2010), Henry (2001, 2008), King (2008), Howard-Snyder (1996), Marsh (2008), McBrayer and Swenson (2012), McKim (2001), Moser (2008), Murray (2002), Oakes (2008), O’Connell (2013), Poston and Dougherty (2007), Rea (2009), Swinburne (1998, 2004), van Inwagen (2002, 2006), and Tucker (2008).

  5. See especially Cordry (2008), Maitzen (2008), and Schellenberg (1996, 2002, 2005a, b, c, 2007b, 2008a, b).

  6. As in Swinburne (1998, pp. 203-210, 2004, pp. 267-272) and Murray (2002), building on Kant (1956, p. 152, 1978, p. 123).

  7. As suggested by Howard-Snyder (1996).

  8. As in Cullison (2010).

  9. I’m ignoring complications that would arise if the incarnation were brought into the discussion.

  10. For a more detailed case against the possibility of divine humility, see Campana (1992).

  11. My guess is that the same holds for many Jewish and Islamic treatments of humility, but since (to my discredit) I am unacquainted with these, I will speak only of my own tradition.

  12. Aquinas (1920) Summa Theologiae, IIa IIae, q. 161, art. 6, resp.

  13. Aquinas (1920) Summa Theologiae, IIa IIae, q. 162, art. 4, resp.

  14. Aquinas (1920) Summa Theologiae, IIa IIae, q. 162, art. 5, resp.

  15. Aquinas (1920) Summa Theologiae, IIa IIae, q. 161, art. 1, ad. 4.

  16. Kreider (2011, p. 37) says of Christ that ‘to treat those who are inferior to him as greater, to submit himself to them for their sakes is the height of, and perhaps even the definition of, humility.’ For elaboration of this point, see also Copan (2006) and Pardue (2012).

  17. In Orthodox iconography one never finds a signature of any kind.

  18. Such as those discussed by O’Connell (2013) and van Inwagen (2002, 2006).

  19. Though King (2008) argues that even direct religious experiences of the sort suggested by Schellenberg would carry with them serious obstacles as routes to supposedly indubitable belief in God – obstacles inevitable even for an omnipotent being. If King is right, this goes a very long way to addressing the problem of divine hiddenness. For the sake of argument, I will assume throughout that Schellenberg is correct in thinking that God can reveal Himself unambiguously and indubitably as God to any rational being via direct religious experience.

  20. I am assuming that God does not possess middle knowledge. If He did, part of my approach here would not work, though other approaches to the hiddenness problem would open up, as Marsh (2008) shows.

  21. Just how long does the ‘as long as possible’ here refer to? That will depend to some extent on one’s views concerning the afterlife and the possibilities for development and repentance after death. Differences here have the potential to make a substantial impact on one’s views concerning the problem of divine hiddenness, though their relevance has not been much explored in the literature.

  22. Studies by sociologists of religion have consistently shown that religious experiences are quite common across the population, with more than a third of all people having at least one in the course of a lifetime. For a brief summary of 45 years’ worth of international survey data, see Spilka et al. (2003, pp. 299–312). Naturally, not all of these experiences are explicitly theistic in content, but quite a large proportion are experiences of a Being possessed of attributes traditionally ascribed to God. I encourage the reader to examine this and related empirical sources.

  23. It is worth making this point over and against views that would consider this narcissistic of God, as Bede [2004, p. 18 – quoted in Copan (2006, p. 313)] claims.

  24. An anonymous referee casts doubt on this reading of the Abraham narrative, writing as follows: ‘I have some reservations about the author’s claim that God’s making a covenant with Abraham shows humility. In the ancient Near East many great sovereigns made treaties with their subordinates (e.g., suzerainty treaties) indicating not humility on the part of the great ruler but his generosity and desire to make his name more widely known. Remember that Abraham is promised that through him all nations on earth would be blessed.’ I think though that the analogy with suzerainty treaties can only be carried so far, given the important fact that Abraham was genuinely free to walk away and reject the covenant being suggested. This is not, I think, a feature of typical suzerainty arrangements and bespeaks God’s willing subordination of His plans to the free choice of a single mortal.

  25. My thanks to an anonymous referee for this objection, which I have reproduced here verbatim.

  26. My thanks to another anonymous referee for this objection.

  27. Though it is worth noting that Saint Paul also seems much more optimistic about what the resources of natural theology are capable of providing us, if we are open to them, than is supposed by many proponents of the problem of divine hiddenness. See Romans 1:18-20.

References

  • Aijaz, I., & Weidler, M. (2007). Some critical reflections on the hiddenness argument. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 61, 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas (1920). Summa Theologica. Translated by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province. Accessed on CD ROM edition distributed by www.newadvent.org.

  • Bede, R. (2004). Why is there something rather than nothing? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campana, D. (1992). On ‘The vanity of God’: a reply to Taliaferro. Faith and Philosophy, 9, 105–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copan, P. (2006). Divine narcissism? A further defense of God’s humility. Philosophia Christi, 8, 313–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cordry, B. (2008). Divine hiddenness and belief De Re. Religious Studies, 45, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cullison, A. (2010). Two solutions to the problem of divine hiddenness. American Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 119–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drange, T. (1993). The argument from non-belief. Religious Studies, 29, 417–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drange, T. (1998). Nonbelief and evil: An argument for the nonexistence of God. Amherst: Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dumsday, T. (2010a). Divine hiddenness, free-will, and the victims of wrongdoing. Faith and Philosophy, 27, 423–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dumsday, T. (2010b). Divine hiddenness and the responsibility argument. Philosophia Christi, 12, 357–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dumsday, T. (2012). Divine hiddenness as divine mercy. Religious Studies, 48, 183–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, C. S. (2006). Can God Be Hidden and Evident at the Same Time? Some Kierkegaardian Reflections. Faith and Philosophy, 23, 241–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, C. S. (2010). Natural signs and knowledge of God: A new look at theistic arguments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, D. (2001). Does reasonable nonbelief exist? Faith and Philosophy, 18, 75–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, D. (2008). Reasonable doubts about reasonable nonbelief. Faith and Philosophy, 25, 276–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howard-Snyder, D. (1996). The argument from divine hiddenness. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26, 433–453.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1956). Critique of Practical Reason (trans: Beck, L.). Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

  • Kant, I. (1978). Lectures on Philosophical Theology (trans: Wood, A. & Clark, G.). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  • Keller, J. (1995). The hiddenness of God and the problem of evil. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 37, 13–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, R. (2008). Obstacles to revelation: God and the reorientation of human reason. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreider, G. (2011). God’s humility: Reflections on an unappreciated attribute of the father, son, and holy spirit. Criswell Theological Review, 9, 33–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C. S. (1952). Mere christianity. London: Geoffrey Bles.

  • Maitzen, S. (2006). Divine hiddenness and the demographics of theism. Religious Studies, 42, 177–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maitzen, S. (2008). Does molinism explain the demographics of theism? Religious Studies, 44, 473–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marsh, J. (2008). Do the demographics of theistic belief disconfirm theism? A reply to Maitzen. Religious Studies, 44, 465–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McBrayer, J., & Swenson, P. (2012). Scepticism about the argument from divine hiddenness. Religious Studies, 48, 129–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKim, R. (2001). Religious ambiguity and religious diversity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moser, P. (2008). The elusive God: Reorienting religious epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, M. (2002). Deus absconditus. In D. Howard-Snyder & P. Moser (Eds.), Divine hiddenness: New essays (pp. 62–82). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connell, J. (2013). Divine hiddenness: Would more miracles solve the problem? Heythrop Journal, 54, 261–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oakes, R. (2008). Life, death, and the hiddenness of God. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 64, 155–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pardue, S. (2012). Kenosis and its discontents: Towards an Augustinian account of divine humility. Scottish Journal of Theology, 65, 271–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poston, T., & Dougherty, T. (2007). Divine hiddenness and the nature of belief. Religious Studies, 43, 183–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rea, M. (2009). Narrative, liturgy, and the hiddenness of God. In K. Timpe (Ed.), Metaphysics and God: Essays in honor of Eleonore stump (pp. 76–96). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (1993). Divine hiddenness and human reason. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (1996). Response to Howard-Snyder. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26, 455–462.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2002). What the hiddenness of God reveals’. In D. Howard-Snyder & P. Moser (Eds.), Divine hiddenness: New essays (pp. 33–61). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2005a). The hiddenness argument revisited (I). Religious Studies, 41, 201–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2005b). The hiddenness argument revisited (II). Religious Studies, 41, 287–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2005c). On reasonable nonbelief and perfect love: replies to Henry and Lehe. Faith and Philosophy, 22, 330–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2007a). The wisdom to doubt: A justification of religious skepticism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2007b). On not unnecessarily darkening the glass: A reply to Poston and Dougherty. Religious Studies, 43, 199–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2008a). Response to Tucker on hiddenness. Religious Studies, 44, 289–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2008b). Reply to Aijaz and Weidler on hiddenness. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 64, 135–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spilka, et al. (2003). The psychology of religion: An empirical approach. New York: Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (1998). Providence and the problem of evil. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2004). The existence of God (2 Revisedth ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, C. (2008). Divine hiddenness and the value of divine-creature relationships. Religious Studies, 44, 269–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (2002). What is the problem of the hiddenness of God? In D. Howard-Snyder & P. Moser (Eds.), Divine hiddenness: New essays (pp. 24–32). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (2006). The problem of evil. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Velimirović, N., Saint. (2008) The prologue of Ohrid, vol. I: January to June. Trans: Fr. T. T. Tepsi. Ed. Fr. J. Trbovi. (Alhambra, CA: Western American Diocese of the Serbian Orthodox Church) First published in modern Serbian in 1928, collected from traditional Orthodox sources.

Download references

Acknowledgements

My sincere thanks to several anonymous referees for their valuable comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Travis Dumsday.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dumsday, T. Divine Hiddenness and Divine Humility. SOPHIA 53, 51–65 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-013-0381-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-013-0381-1

Keywords

Navigation