Skip to main content
Log in

Rejecting Society: Misanthropy, Friendship and Montaigne

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Widespread misanthropy, understood as the disposition to reject society, is at once a permanent source of instability and injustice, and yet also a valuable support of cherished liberal practices, such as toleration. We must seek therefore to ‘civilise’ the misanthropic temper. Michel de Montaigne provides an instructive case study in this context, for he successfully moderated his misanthropy by his conviviality and friendship. The non-conditional character of Montaignean friendship functions to moderate rational misanthropic antipathy and thereby suggests a striking reinterpretation of civic friendship. Montaigne may seem an unpromising ally for contemporary defenders of civic friendship, but in fact his essays provide a valuable resource for the political theory of community.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Compare Judith Shklar’s suggestion that the ‘absence of friendship might well serve as a definition of misanthropy’ (Shklar 1984, pp. 198–199). Whilst I shall ultimately question that claim, I agree with Shklar’s characterisation of misanthropy as having more to do with human relationships (or rather the lack thereof) than with any particular sentiment.

  2. In adopting this approach, I take my cue from Judith Shklar’s work on Montaigne and the idea of misanthropy (see Shklar 1984). However, my discussion is not intended as an interpretation of Shklar’s position, nor do I consider it an extension of her view. Rather, I begin from a cluster of issues that Shklar identifies and seek to develop them in a somewhat different direction.

  3. Relatedly, it is also very hard for misanthropes to exercise effective leadership of intolerant social movements. As Florence King writes, ‘I am unable to detect anything as simple as misanthropy in the great monsters of history. Some were insane, like Caligula and Ivan the Terrible. Others, like Hitler, Mussolini and Stalin exuded a certain heavy-handed bonhomie … that suggests normal conviviality, or at least a willingness to give it a try. … As leaders of great masses of people, monsters must be able to use their personality to mesmerize their followers and forge primal bonds with them by becoming father figures. Whatever the gift is called—heart, the common touch, public relations—no misanthrope could hold such a pose for more than 5 min, and then only on a good day’ (King 1992, pp. 4–5).

  4. Chandran Kukathas, for example, writes that ‘it is the understandings people share that make them into a community’ (2003, p. 170).

  5. The claim made in this paragraph is one that I have developed and defended at much greater length elsewhere (see Edyvane 2007).

  6. Along with J.B. Priestley, another wartime political thinker I have in mind here is Richard Titmuss, who emphasised the important connection between social perceptions of collective vulnerability and enthusiasm for various forms of social altruism (see, for example Titmuss 1958). A contemporary account that offers a somewhat similar message is Tony Judt’s Ill Fares the Land (Judt 2010).

References

  • Aristotle. 1976. [350 BC] Ethics (trans: Thomson, J.A.K.). London: Penguin.

  • Aristotle. 1996. [350 BC] The politics and the constitution of Athens, ed. Stephen Everson (trans: Jonathan Barnes). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Bakewell, Sarah. 2010. How to live: A life of Montaigne in one question and twenty attempts at an answer. London: Chatto & Windus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, Brian. 2001. Culture and equality: An egalitarian critique of multiculturalism. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellah, Robert. 1985. Habits of the heart: Middle America observed. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicero. 1991. [44 BC] De amicitia. In Other selves: Philosophers on friendship, ed. Michael Pakaluk, 79–116 (trans: Frank Copley). Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Edyvane, Derek. 2003. Against unconditional love. Journal of Applied Philosophy 20: 59–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edyvane, Derek. 2007. Community and conflict: The sources of liberal solidarity. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, George. 1996. The instability of tolerance. In Toleration: An elusive virtue, ed. David Heyd, 158–172. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horton, John. 2011. Why the traditional conception of toleration still matters. Critical Review of Social and Political Philosophy 14: 289–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Judt, Tony. 2010. Ill fares the land. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, Florence. 1992. With charity toward none: A fond look at misanthropy. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukathas, Chandran. 2003. The liberal archipelago: A theory of diversity and freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, Will. 1995. Multicultural citizenship: A liberal theory of minority rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1985. After virtue: A study in moral theory, 2nd ed. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moliere. 2000. [1666] The misanthrope. In The misanthrope and other plays, ed. John Wood and David Coward, 89–142 (trans: John Wood and David Coward). London: Penguin.

  • Montaigne, Michel de. 2003. [1580] The complete works (trans: Donald Frame). London: Everyman.

  • Priestley, J.B. 1969. An inspector calls and other plays. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Robert. 2000. Bowling alone: The collapse and revival of American community. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, Charles M. 1959. Peanuts, 12 November 1959. Gocomics. http://www.gocomics.com/peanuts/1959/11/12/. Accessed 31 March 2011.

  • Shakespeare, William. 2004. [1623] Timon of Athens. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Shklar, Judith. 1984. Ordinary vices. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Titmuss, Richard. 1958. War and social policy. In his Essays on the welfare state, 75–87. London: George Allen & Unwin.

Download references

Acknowledgments

An earlier version of this paper was presented at the 2010 Manchester Metropolitan University Workshops in Political Theory. I am grateful to all participants in the workshop, to Kerri Woods and also to an anonymous reviewer for Res Publica for extremely helpful comments and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Derek Edyvane.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Edyvane, D. Rejecting Society: Misanthropy, Friendship and Montaigne. Res Publica 19, 53–65 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-012-9206-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-012-9206-2

Keywords

Navigation