Skip to main content
Log in

Kuhn and the Question of Pursuit Worthiness

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The aim of this paper is, on the one hand, to critically investigate Kuhn’s stance on the assessment of the pursuit worthiness of scientific theories, and, on the other hand, to show the actuality of some of Kuhn’s points on this issue, in view of their critical analysis. To this end we show that Kuhn presents certain tools, which may help scientists to overcome communication breakdowns when engaging in the process of rational deliberation regarding the question whether a theory is worthy of further pursuit. These tools are persuasion, translation and interpretation. However, we argue that the perspective of epistemic semantic monism present in Kuhn’s work obstructs the full applicability of these tools. We show that dropping this perspective makes the notions of persuasion and interpretation more fruitful, and moreover, allows for a pluralism of scientific theories and practices that complements the pluralism based on disagreement among scientists, emphasized by Kuhn.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is important to notice that the relationship between paradigms and theories is ambiguous in Kuhn’s work already due to the ambiguous nature of the former notion. For a detailed discussion on this ambiguity we refer the reader to (Hoyningen-Huene 1993, Chapter 4). For the purposes of this paper it will suffice to use these two terms loosely, allowing for the assessment of pursuit worthiness to be applicable to both terms (paradigms and theories). Where a given paradigm is a unit of appraisal that encompasses one or more theories, the assessment of its pursuit worthiness is also essentially informed by the pursuit worthiness of these respective theories.

  2. Different authors (e.g. those just mentioned) have emphasized different values as indices of pursuit worthiness, but explanatory and heuristic virtues of the given theory have often been considered as some of the crucial ones. For instance, the capability of the theory to offer explanations that its rivals have not managed to offer so far can be seen as such an indicator. This explanatory virtue is different from the one usually required for theory acceptance, where we are not only interested in what the theory can explain, but also in what it cannot explain, that is, in its explanatory anomalies. In contrast, when we evaluate whether a theory is worthy of pursuit, instead of focusing on its explanatory anomalies, we are rather interested in its programmatic character which indicates that the investigation can proceed in spite of the current anomalies and towards their resolution. Hence, we are interested in the prospective values, which allow for a prospective assessment, rather than a retrospective one, which is typical for the context of acceptance.

  3. The third and final phase is acceptance.

  4. It is important to notice that the above distinction is not exhaustive when it comes to different claims of pursuit worthiness. For an elaborate discussion on this topic see [Šešelja et al. (2012)]. Moreover, since cognitive issues were of primary interest in Kuhn’s work, we speak here only of cognitive pursuit worthiness. It is important to keep in mind though that the assessment of pursuit worthiness may usually include a broader set of both cognitive and non-cognitive values, in which case we can speak of practical pursuit worthiness. The latter should not be confused with cognitive pursuit worthiness as a research directive, since practical pursuit worthiness also appears in the form of an evaluative stance and (a decision making form of) a research directive.

  5. See (Šešelja and Straßer 2009, p. 323).

  6. See also (Kuhn 2000, p. 96).

  7. Kuhn also points out that

    … despite the incompleteness of their communication, proponents of different theories can exhibit to each other, not always easily, the concrete technical results achievable by those who practice within each theory. Little or no translation is required to apply at least some value criteria to those results. (Accuracy and fruitfulness are most immediately applicable, perhaps followed by scope. Consistency and simplicity are far more problematic). (Kuhn 1977, p. 339, italics added)

    Moreover, for some scientists these considerations may be decisive to change their research directive:

    … each language community can usually produce from the start a few concrete research results that, though describable in sentences understood in the same way by both groups, cannot yet be accounted for by the other community in its own terms. If the new viewpoint endures for a time and continues to be fruitful, the research results verbalizable in this way are likely to grow in number. For some men such results alone will be decisive. They can say I don’t know how the proponents of the new view succeed, but I must learn, whatever they are doing, it is clearly right. (p. 203, italics added)

    Kuhn here suggests that some initial results of a theory can only be described by the scientists working in a rivaling paradigm, but they cannot be accounted for, explained in their own terminology. In order for that to be possible, scientists need to learn the new theory.

  8. “The claim that two theories are incommensurable is then the claim that there is no language, neutral or otherwise, into which both theories, conceived as sets of sentences, can be translated without residue or loss”. (Kuhn 2000, p. 36).

  9. However, this is not the whole truth since there is also a pluralist side to Kuhn as we discuss below.

  10. Also, in Hoyningen-Huene’s reading of Kuhn, such a disagreement is considered as vital for the development of science (Hoyningen-Huene 2006, p. 128).

References

  • Chang H (2011) The persistence of epistemic objects through scientific change. Erkenntnis 75:413–429

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene P (1993) Reconstructing scientific revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn’s philosophy of science. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene P (2006) Context of discovery versus context of justification and thomas kuhn. In: Schickore J, Steinle F (eds) Revisiting discovery and justification: historical and philosophical perspectives on the context distinction. Springer, Netherlands, pp 119–131

  • Kuhn T (1962 [1996]) Structure of scientific revolutions 3rd edn. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Kuhn T (1970) Reflections on my critics. In: Lakatos I, Musgrave A (eds) Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Kuhn T (1977) The essential tension: selected studies in scientific tradition and change. University of Chicago press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn T (2000) The road since structure. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I, Musgrave A (eds) (1970) Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan L (1977) Progress and its problems. Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles T (ed) (1980) Introductory essay: scientific discovery and the future of philosophy of science. In: Scientific discovery: case studies, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, pp xiii–xxv

  • Nickles T (2006) Heuristic appraisal: context of discovery or justification? In: Schickore J, Steinle F (eds) Revisiting discovery and justification: historical and philosophical perspectives on the context distinction. Springer, Netherlands, pp 159–182

  • Nickles T (2009) Life at the frontier: the relevance of heuristic appraisal to policy. Axiomathes 19:441–464

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach H (1938) Experience and prediction. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowbottom DP (2011) Kuhn vs. popper on criticism and dogmatism in science: a resolution at the group level. Stud Hist Philos Sci A 42:117–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schickore J, Steinle F (eds) (2006) Revisiting discovery and justification: historical and philosophical perspectives on the context distinction. Springer, Netherlands

    Google Scholar 

  • Šešelja D, Kosolosky L, Straßer C (2012) Rationality of scientific reasoning in the context of pursuit: drawing appropriate distinctions. Philosophica, accepted for publication

  • Šešelja D, Straßer C (2009) Kuhn and coherentist epistemology. Stud Hist Philos Sci 40:322–327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Šešelja D, Straßer C (201x). Epistemic justification in the context of pursuit: a coherentist approach. Synthese, accepted for publication

  • Whitt LA (1990) Theory pursuit: between discovery and acceptance. In PSA: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association vol 1, pp 467–483

  • Whitt LA (1992) Indices of theory promise. Philos Sci 59:612–634

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The research for this paper has been supported by grants of Bijzonder Onderzoeksfonds (BOF) of Ghent University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dunja Šešelja.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Šešelja, D., Straßer, C. Kuhn and the Question of Pursuit Worthiness. Topoi 32, 9–19 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-012-9144-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-012-9144-9

Keywords

Navigation