Skip to main content
Log in

The case for multiple realization in biology

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Polger and Shapiro argue that their official recipe, a criterion for judging when the phenomenon of multiple realization (MR) exists, renders MR less widespread than its proponents have assumed. I argue that, although Polger and Shapiro’s criterion is a useful contribution, they arrive at their conclusion too hastily. Contrary to Polger and Shapiro, I claim that the phenomenon of multiple realization in the biological world, judged by their criterion, is not as scarce as they suggest. To show this, an updated official recipe, namely a multiple mechanistic realization thesis, integrating Polger and Shapiro’s criterion with a compositional conception of realization, is developed. Then, three examples of varied kinds are examined, showing that cases of MR are not so hard to find in the biological world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some philosophers may be skeptical of the talk of “levels”, e.g., Potochnik and McGill (2012). However, since the talk of levels has a well-defined meaning through the essay (i.e., compositional organization), and this essay’s argument does not hinge on the talk of levels, I will not address this dispute in the essay. I thank Jay Odenbaugh for letting me notice this dispute.

  2. Shapiro is not the first to have proposed a “causally relevant differences” criterion. Shoemaker makes a similar point in his causal theory of properties, stating that two properties are different when they contribute different powers to the individuals in which they are instantiated when under the same conditions (Shoemaker 1980; Cf. Gillett 2010, 169). Kim’s principle of causal individuation of kinds also asserts that “kinds in science are individuated on the basis of causal powers; that is, objects and events fall under a kind, or share a property, insofar as they have similar causal powers” (Kim 1992, 17).

  3. With respect to the conception of function, they say that “for some entities—properties, states, kinds, objects—being that entity is a matter of having a certain function” (Polger and Shapiro 2016, 23; original emphasis).

  4. Note that this is by no means denying that there might be other kind of realization in the biological world, e.g., functional realization. Functional realization may have different forms depending on what one means by function. For example, it might refer to the evolutionary history of the function through which that function was selected, or the causal process in which one thing is caused or causing other things, etc. For a discussion of functional realization see Polger (2004). However, given that concentrating on compositional realization is sufficient to show that the biological world is abundant in the phenomenon of multiple realization, this essay will not consider other potential kinds of realization.

  5. According to this theory, a property is individuated by the causal powers it contributes to the individual in which it is instantiated (Shoemaker 1980, 109–135).

  6. This definition draws heavily on Aizawa and Gillett’s account (2009a, b), though this account differs in two substantial ways: (1) it makes clear that realization in the biological world is mechanistic realization (i.e., a type of compositional realization); and (2) it attempts to integrate Polger and Shapiro’s criterion for MR.

  7. Note that properties and kinds are two different concepts. However, I sometimes use kinds to mean that something has a property \(P\) such that, due to having this property, it is classified into the kind \(X\). I thank Patrick McGivern for alerting me to the difference between them. Also notice that we here do not use the shorthand way of talking about realization (i.e., property \(P\) realizes property \(Q\)), but rather use the full-fledged way introduced in “The full-fledged form of realization” section (i.e., individual \(S_{i}\) as a realizer realizes property \(Q\)).

  8. “Have the similar property” should be understood as having the same property with different property-values, e.g., being crimson and being scarlet are different property-values of being red. I thank Jay Odenbaugh for helping me clarify this point.

  9. Piccinini and Maley also make this distinction (2014, 137–141).

  10. There is another reason for re-examining Polger and Shapiro’s example: it is meant to show that the examination of various examples in this essay does not proceed in a cherry-picking way, only selecting cases in favor of my position while ignoring cases speaking against my position.

  11. I thank an anonymous referee for suggesting me comparing the similarities and dissimilarities between the various normal ferrets and the similarities and dissimilarities between the rewired and normal ferrets.

  12. Note that the inter-level realization scenario described here differs from the intra-level causation scenario, because in the latter case a difference in effect can in principle be tracked back to a difference in cause and thus there does exist such a similarity-dissimilarity mapping. Exploring how the similarity-dissimilarity mapping does not arise in the non-causal, inter-level realization case, however, must wait for another occasion.

  13. Note that here convergent evolution constitutes an important source for MR to emerge. However, there might be other ways for MR to arise, e.g., parallel evolution, evolution by chance, divergent evolution, etc. For a discussion of how divergent evolution could modify the active sites of certain enzymes but the enzymes modified can still perform the same or similar function, see Gerlt and Babbitt (2001), Todd et al. (2001) and Bartlett et al. (2002). I thank an anonymous referee for letting me notice this point.

  14. For a discussion of the EC number, see Webb (1992).

  15. This is not denying that there might exist the extreme case of MR where things sharing no essential property at all could realize the same function. However, though this might be the case, this paper only needs to meet the more moderate goal that there exist middle ground cases where things that both share some essential properties and do not share some essential properties can realize the same function.

  16. Note that the concern here is not with the amount of transformational analogues but with the frequent occurrences of their associated functions. I think one anonymous referee for helping me clarify this.

  17. I thank an anonymous referee for alerting me to this possible line of objection.

References

  • Aizawa K (2007) The biochemistry of memory consolidation: a model system for the philosophy of mind. Synthese 155:65–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa K (2009) Neuroscience and multiple realization: a reply to Bechtel and Mundale. Synthese 167:493–510

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa K (2013) Multiple realization by compensatory differences. Eur J Philos Sci 3:69–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa K, Gillett C (2009a) Levels, individual variation, and massive multiple realization in neurobiology. In: Bickle J (ed) The Oxford handbook of philosophy and neuroscience. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 539–582

    Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa K, Gillett C (2009b) The (multiple) realization of psychological and other properties in the sciences. Mind Lang 24:181–208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa K, Gillett C (2011) The autonomy of psychology in the age of neuroscience. In: Illari PM, Russo F, Williamson J (eds) Causality in the sciences. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 202–223

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Balari S, Lorenzo G (2015) Ahistorical homology and multiple realizability. Philos Psychol 28(6):881–902

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barabási A-L, Oltvai ZN (2004) Network biology: understanding the cell’s functional organization. Nat Rev Genet 5:101–113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartlett GJ, Porter CT, Borkakoti N, Thornton JM (2002) Analysis of catalytic residues in enzyme active sites. J Mol Biol 324:105–121

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baysan U (2015) Realization relations in metaphysics. Mind Mach 25:247–260

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W (2007) Reducing psychology while maintaining its autonomy via mechanistic explanation. In: Schouten M, Jong HL (eds) The matter of the mind: philosophical essays on psychology, neuroscience and reduction. Blackwell Publishing, New York, pp 172–198

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W, Mundale J (1999) Multiple realizability revisited: linking cognitive and neural states. Philos Sci 66(2):175–207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle J (2003) Philosophy and neuroscience: a ruthlessly reductive account. Kluwer, Drodrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle J (2010) Has the last decade of challenges to the multiple realization argument provided aid and comfort to psychoneural reductionists? Synthese 177:247–260

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle J (2013) Multiple realizability. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Spring 2013 edn. Accessed 22 May 2016

  • Boyd R (1980) Materialism without reductionism: what physicalism does not entail. In: Block N (ed) Readings in philosophy of psychology, vol 1. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 1–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Clapp LJ (2001) Disjunctive properties: multiple realizations. J Philos 98:111–136

    Google Scholar 

  • Couch MB (2004) Discussion: a defense of Bechtel and Mundale. Philos Sci 71:198–204

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF (2004) Dissociable realization and kind splitting. Philos Sci 71:960–971

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF, Bechtel W (2007) Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biol Philos 22:547–563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feller G, Gerday C (1997) Adaptations of the hemoglobinless Antarctic icefish (Channichthyidae) to hypoxia tolerance. Comp Biochem Physiol A Physiol 118:981–987

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor JA (1974) Special sciences (or: the disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese 28:97–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galperin MY, Walker DR, Koonin EV (1998) Analogous enzymes: independent inventions in enzyme evolution. Genome Res 8:779–790

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garofalo F, Pellegrino D, Amelio D, Tota B (2009) The Antarctic hemoglobinless icefish, fifty five years later: a unique cardiocirculatory interplay of disaptation and phenotypic plasticity. Comp Biochem Physiol A Mol Integr Physiol 154:10–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • George RA, Spriggs RV, Thornton JM, AlLazikani B, Swindells MB (2004) Scopec: a database of protein catalytic domains. Bioinformatics 20(Suppl. 1):I130–I136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerlt JA, Babbitt PC (2001) Divergent evolution of enzymatic function: mechanistically diverse superfamilies and functionally distinct suprafamilies. Annu Rev Biochem 70:209–246

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gherardini PF, Wass MN, Helmer-Citterich M, Sternberg MJE (2007) Convergent evolution of enzyme active sites is not a rare phenomenon. J Mol Biol 372:817–845

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett C (2002) The dimensions of realization: a critique of the standard view. Analysis 62:316–323

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett C (2003) The metaphysics of realization, multiple realizability, and the special sciences. J Philos 100:591–603

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillett C (2007) Understanding the new reductionism: the metaphysics of science and compositional reduction. J Philos 104:193–216

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett C (2010) Moving beyond the subset model of realization: the problem of qualitative distinctness in the metaphysics of science. Synthese 177:165–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gursoy A, Keskin O, Nussinov R (2008) Topological properties of protein interaction networks from a structural perspective. Biochem Soc Trans 36:1398–1403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haug MC (2010) Realization, determination, and mechanisms. Philos Stud 150:313–330

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heaton J (2015) Artificial intelligence for humans, volume 3: deep learning and neural networks. Heaton Research, St. Louis

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegyi H, Gerstein M (1999) The relationship between protein structure and function: a comprehensive survey with application to the yeast genome. J Mol Biol 288:147–164

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heil J (1992) The nature of true minds. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heil J (1999) Multiple realizability. Am Philos Q 36:189–208

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1992) Multiple realization and the metaphysics of reduction. Philos Phenomenol Res 52:1–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1998) Mind in a physical world: an essay on the mind-body problem and mental causation. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1999) Making sense of emergency. Philos Stud 95:3–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1984) 1953 and all that. A tale of two sciences. Philos Rev 93:335–373

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein C (2013) Multiple realizability and the semantic view of theories. Philos Stud 163:683–695

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer P, Darden L, Craver CF (2000) Thinking about mechanisms. Philos Sci 67:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnus KA, Ton-That H, Carpenter JE (1994) Recent structural work on the oxygen transport protein hemocyanin. Chem Rev 94(3):727–735

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martindale C (1991) Cognitive psychology: a neural-network approach. Thomson Brooks/Cole Publishing Co, Pacific Grove

    Google Scholar 

  • Mostafavi S, Goldenberg A, Morris Q (2011) Predicting node characteristics from molecular networks. In: Cagney G, Emili A (eds) Network biology: methods and applications. Humana Press, New York, pp 399–414

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom D (2002) Robust nonreductive materialism. J Philos 99:499–531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini G, Maley C (2014) The metaphysics of mind and the multiple sources of multiple realizability. In: Sprevak M, Kallestrup J (eds) New waves in the philosophy of mind. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, pp 125–152

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Polger TW (2004) Natural minds. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Polger TW (2008) Two confusions concerning multiple realization. Philos Sci 75:537–547

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polger TW (2009) Evaluating the evidence for multiple realization. Synthese 167:457–472

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polger TW, Shapiro LA (2016) The multiple realization book. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik A, McGill B (2012) The limitations of hierarchical organization. Philos Sci 79:120–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1967) Psychological predicates. In: Capitan WH, Merrill DD (eds) Art, mind, and religion. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, pp 37–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson RC (2008) Autonomy and multiple realization. Philos Sci 75:526–536

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roe AW, Pallas SL, Hahm J-O, Sur M (1990) A map of visual space induced in primary auditory cortex. Science 250:818–820

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A (2001) On multiple realization and the special sciences. J Philos 98:365–373

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A (2006) Darwinian reductionism: or, how to stop worrying and love molecular biology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ruthazer ES, Stryker MP (1996) The role of activity in the development of long-range horizontal connections in area 17á of the ferret. J Neurosci 16:7253–7269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro LA (2000) Multiple realizations. J Philos 97:635–654

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro LA (2004) The mind incarnate. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro LA (2008) How to test for multiple realization. Philos Sci 75:514–525

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro LA, Polger TW (2012) Identity, variability, and multiple realization in the special sciences. In: Gozzano S, Hill CS (eds) New perspectives on type identity: the mental and the physical. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 264–288

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sharma J, Angelucci A, Sur M (2000) Induction of visual orientation modules in auditory cortex. Nature 404:841–847

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S (1980) Causality and properties. In: Inwagen PV (ed) Time and cause. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 109–135

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S (2001) Realization and mental causation. In: Gillett C, Loewer B (eds) Physicalism and its discontents. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 74–98

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S (2007) Physical realization. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1999) The multiple realizability argument against reductionism. Philos Sci 66:542–564

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (1996) Explanatory pluralism in evolutionary biology. Biol Philos 11(2):193–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan JA (2008) Memory consolidation, multiple realizations, and modest reductions. Philos Sci 75:501–513

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd AE, Orengo CA, Thornton JM (2001) Evolution of function in protein superfamilies, from a structural perspective. J Mol Biol 307:1113–1143

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tota B, Cerra MC, Mazza R et al (1997) The heart of the Antarctic icefish as paradigm of cold adaptation. J Therm Biol 22:409–417

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Melchner L, Pallas SL, Sur M (2000) Visual behaviour mediated by retinal projections directed to the auditory pathway. Nature 404:871–876

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Webb EC (1992) Enzyme nomenclature. Recommendations of the nomenclature committee of the international union of biochemistry and molecular biology. Academic Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson RA (2001) Two views of realization. Philos Stud 104:1–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1976a) Reductive explanation: a functional account. In: PSA: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association 1974, pp 671–710

  • Wimsatt WC (1976b) Reductionism, levels of organization, and the mind-body problem. In: Globus GG, Maxwell G, Savodnik I (eds) Consciousness and the brain. Plenum Press, New York, pp 202–267

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1994) The ontology of complex systems: levels of organization, perspectives, and causal thickets. Can J Philos 24:207–274

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright CS (1972) Comparison of the active site stereochemistry and substrate conformation in-chymotrypsin and subtilisin bpn’. J Mol Biol 67:151–163

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu CH, McLarty JW (2000) Neural networks and genome informatics. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to a number of friends and colleagues for feedback on early drafts of this work, including Pierrick Bourrat, Mischa Davenport, Stefan Gawronski, Paul Griffiths, Kate Lynch, Qiaoying Lu, John Matthewson, Patrick McGivern, Jay Odenbaugh, Wendy Parker, Arnaud Pocheville, Elena Walsh and two anonymous referees. Special thanks is due to Paul Griffiths and Arnaud Pocheville, who gave me extremely useful help and encouragement over the course of developing this work. Also thanks to the National Social Science Fund of China (Grant no.: 14ZDB018).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wei Fang.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fang, W. The case for multiple realization in biology. Biol Philos 33, 3 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9613-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9613-7

Keywords

Navigation