Skip to main content
Log in

What (Good) is Historical Epistemology? Editors’ Introduction

  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We provide an overview of three ways in which the expression “Historical epistemology” (HE) is often understood: (1) HE as a study of the history of higher-order epistemic concepts such as objectivity, observation, experimentation, or probability; (2) HE as a study of the historical trajectories of the objects of research, such as the electron, DNA, or phlogiston; (3) HE as the long-term study of scientific developments. After laying out various ways in which these agendas touch on current debates within both epistemology and philosophy of science (e.g., skepticism, realism, rationality of scientific change), we conclude by highlighting three topics as especially worthy of further philosophical investigation. The first concerns the methods, aims and systematic ambitions of the history of epistemology. The second concerns the ways in versions of HE can be connected to versions of naturalized and social epistemologies. The third concerns the philosophy of history, and in particular the level of analysis at which a historical analysis should aim.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The “Lorenz Krüger postdoctoral fellowship” at the MPIWG is explicitly given to young researchers who combine the history of science with the philosophy of science and/or the history of philosophy.

  2. The latter of the three has recently retired from his directorship.

  3. http://www.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/en/institute/index.html, accessed March 15, 2011.

  4. Critics of traditional history of ideas often view it as closely related to a history of concepts, where such concepts are assumed to be consciously represented in the minds of the historical actors. Distancing herself from such a view, Lorraine Daston therefore views the expression “epistemic concept” as an unfortunate choice of words to describe her approach. Instead she prefers to speak of the histories of epistemic categories as covering explicit concepts as well as tacit epistemic practices. Because of the traditional meanings of the term “category”, however, this expression would be misleading, so we avoid it here.

  5. More accurately, we should say that even though Rheinberger’s work was influenced by Hacking’s epistemology of experimentation, we have not been able to find evidence that he was also influenced by Hacking’s writings on historical epistemology.

  6. In this quote, Rheinberger uses the term “object”, but he mostly prefers the term “epistemic thing”. Much of the literature uses “thing” and “object” interchangeably.

  7. This version of historical epistemology is close to what Hacking (2002, pp. 7–12) prefers to call “historical ontology” and Daston (2000, p. 1) “applied metaphysics”.

  8. For example, Jürgen Renn views the works of Marx, Freud, Piaget, Einstein, Fleck und Lakatos as the more immediate inspirations of his approach (personal communication).

  9. We owe this point and phrase to Sandra Mitchell.

References

  • Andersen, H., Barker, P., & Chen, X. (2006). The cognitive structure of scientific revolutions. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burian, R. M. (1977). More than a marriage of convenience: On the inextricability of the history and philosophy of science. Philosophy of Science, 44, 1–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Canguilhem, G. (2006). Wissenschaft, Technik, Leben: Beiträge zur historischen Epistemologie, Transl. by R. Voullié et al., with an afterword by H. Schmidgen. (Berlin: Merve).

  • Chimisso, C. (2003). The tribunal of philosophy and its norms: History and philosophy in Georges Canguilhem’s historical epistemology. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 34, 297–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damerow, P. (2006). The material culture of calculation: A theoretical framework for a historical epistemology of the concept of number. In U. Gellert & E. Jablonka (Eds.), Mathematisation and demathematisation: Social, philosophical and educational ramifications (pp. 19–56). Rotterdam: Sense Publ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L. (1988). Classical probability in the enlightenment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L. (1994). Historical epistemology. In J. Chandler, A. I. Davidson, & H. Harootunian (Eds.), Questions of evidence (pp. 282–289). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L. (Ed.). (2000). Biographies of scientific objects. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L. (2007). The history of emergences. Isis, 98, 801–808.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L. (2008). On scientific observation. Isis, 99, 97–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L., & Galison, P. (2007). Objectivity. New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L., & Lunbeck, E. (Eds.). (2011). Histories of scientific observation. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, A. I. (2002). The emergence of sexuality: Historical epistemology and the formation of concepts. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Domsky, M., & Dickson, M. (Eds.). (2010). Discourse on a new method: Reinvigorating the marriage of history and philosophy of science. La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1993). Remarks on the history of science and the history of philosophy. In P. Horwich (Ed.), World changes: Thomas Kuhn and the nature of science (pp. 36–54). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentner, D., & Stevens, A. L. (Eds.). (1983). Mental models. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1973). History and philosophy of science: Intimate relation or marriage of convenience? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 24, 282–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gingras, Y. (2010). Naming without necessity: On the geneaology and uses of the label ‘historical epistemology’. Revue de Synthese, 131, 439–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1999). Historical meta-epistemology. In W. Carl & L. Daston (Eds.), Wahrheit und Geschichte: Ein Kolloquium zu Ehren des 60. Geburtstages von Lorenz Krüger (pp. 53–77). Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2002). Historical ontology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2006). The emergence of probability (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hatfield, G. (1996). The importance of the history of science for philosophy in general. Synthese, 106, 113–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hyder, D. (2003). Foucault, Cavaillès, and Husserl on the historical epistemology of the sciences. Perspectives on Science, 11, 107–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1983). Mental models. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleeberg, B. & Vidal, F. (2007). Knowing God, believing nature. Science in Context, Special Issue, 20(3).

  • Kmita, J. (1988). Problems in historical epistemology. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Krüger, L. (1973). Falsification, revolution, and continuity in the development of science. In P. Suppes et al. (Eds.), Logic, methodology and philosophy of science, Vol. IV (pp. 333–343), Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

  • Krüger, L. (1982). History and philosophy of science—a marriage for the sake of reason. In L. J. Cohen, J. Łoś, H. Pfeiffer & K.-P. Podewski (Eds.), Proceedings of the VI. International congress for logic, methodology and philosophy of science, Hannover 1979 (pp. 108–112). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

  • Krüger, L. (1986) Why do we study the history of philosophy? In: L. Krüger (2005) Why does history matter to philosophy and the sciences? (pp. 231–254). Ed. by T. Sturm, W. Carl & L. Daston. Berlin: De Gruyter.

  • Krüger, L. (1987). Einheit der Welt–Vielheit der Wissenschaft. In J. Kocka (Ed.), Interdisziplinarität (pp. 106–125). Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krüger, L. (2005). Why does history matter to philosophy and the sciences? Ed. by T. Sturm, W. Carl & L. Daston. Berlin: De Gruyter.

  • Krüger, L., Daston, L., & Heidelberger, M. (Eds.). (1987a). The probabilistic revolution. Vol. 1: Ideas in history. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krüger, L., Gigerenzer, G., & Morgan, M. (Eds.). (1987b). The probabilistic revolution. Vol. 2: Ideas in the sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch, M. (2010). Social epistemology. In S. Bernecker, & D. Pritchard (Eds.), The Routledge companion to epistemology (pp. 873–884). London: Routledge).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lecourt, D. (1969). L’Epistémologie historique de Gaston Bachelard. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lecourt, D. (1975). Marxism and epistemology: Bachelard, Canguilhem, and Foucault. London: New Left Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mash, R. (1987). How important for philosophers is the history of philosophy? History and Theory, 26, 278–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1976). History and philosophy of science–a marriage of convenience? In R. S. Cohen, et al. (Eds.), PSA 1974, Boston studies in the philosophy of science 32 (pp. 585–601). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Méthot, P.-O. (2011). From concepts to experimental systems. Trends in historical epistemology. In: H. Schmidgen, P. Schöttler, J.-F. Braunstein (Eds.), History and epistemology. From Bachelard and Canguilhem to today’s history of science. Berlin: Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Preprint Series (forthcoming).

  • Müller-Wille, S., & Rheinberger, H.-J. (Eds.). (2007). Heredity produced: At the crossroads of biology, politics, and culture 1500–1870. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Wille, S., & Rheinberger, H.-J. (2009). Vererbung: Geschichte und Kultur eines biologischen Konzepts. Frankfurt a.M.: Fischer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Privitera, W. (1995). Michel Foucault’s epistemology. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renn, J. (1995a). Address at the opening ceremony of the Institute. Max Planck-Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte, Annual Report, 1995. Berlin: Max-Planck-Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte—http://www.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/ANNREP95/ABTOC.HTM.

  • Renn, J. (1995b). Historical epistemology and interdisciplinarity. In Kostas. Gavroglu, et al. (Eds.), Physics, philosophy and the scientific community (pp. 241–251). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renn, J. (1996). Historical epistemology and the advancement of science. Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Preprint Series, Preprint 36. Berlin: Max Planck Institute for the History of Science (http://www.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/Preprints/P36.PDF).

  • Renn, J. (2004). The relativity revolution from the perspective of historical epistemology. Isis, 95, 640–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Renn, J. (2008). The historical epistemology of mechanics. Foreword to Matthias Schemmel, The English Galileo. Thomas Harriot’s work on motion as an example of preclassical mechanics (pp. vii–x). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Renn, J., & Damerow, P. (2007). Mentale Modelle als kognitive Instrumente der Transformation von technischem Wissen. In H. Böhme, C. Rapp, & W. Rösler (Eds.), Übersetzung und transformation (pp. 311–332). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Renn, J., Damerow, P., & McLaughlin, P. (2004). Aristotle, Archimedes, and the origins of mechanics: The perspective of historical epistemology. In J. L. Montesinos Sirera (Ed.), Symposium Arquímedes (pp. 43–59). Fundación Canaria Orotava de Historia de la Ciencia.

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (1997). Toward a history of epistemic things. Synthesizing proteins in the test tube. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (2005a). Gaston Bachelard and the notion of ‘phenomenotechnique’. Perspectives on Science, 13, 313–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (2005b). Reassessing the historical epistemology of Georges Canguilhem. In C. Gutting (Ed.), Continental philosophy of science (pp. 187–197). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (2005c). A reply to Bloor: ‘Toward a sociology of epistemic things’”. Perspectives on Science, 13, 406–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (2010). On historicizing epistemology. Transl. by D. Fernbach. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Schickore, J. (2011). More thoughts on HPS: Another 20 years later. Perspectives on Science, 19, 455–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapere, D. (1977). What can the theory of knowledge learn from the history of knowledge? The Monist, 60, 488–508.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorell, T., & Rogers, G. (Eds.). (2005). Analytic philosophy and history of philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiles, M. (1984). Bachelard: Science and objectivity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tiles, M. (1987). Epistemological history: The legacy of Bachelard and Canguilhem. In A. Phillips Griffiths (Ed.), Contemporary French philosophy (pp. 141–156). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiles, M., & Tiles, J. (1993). The authority of knowledge: An introduction to historical epistemology. Oxford: Backwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wartofsky, M. (1976). The mind’s eye and the hand’s brain: Toward an historical epistemology of medicine. In H. T. Engelhardt Jr. & D. Callaghan (Eds.), Science, ethics, and medicine (pp. 167–194). New York: University Publications of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wartofsky, M. (1979a). The relation between philosophy of science and history of science (written 1977). In M. Wartofsky (Ed.), Models: Representation and the scientific understanding (pp. 119–139). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wartofsky, M. (1979b). Perception, representations, and the forms of action: Towards an historical epistemology (written 1973). In M. Wartofsky (Ed.), Models: Representation and the scientific understanding (pp. 188–210). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wartofsky, M. (1983a). From genetic epistemology to historical epistemology: Kant, Marx, and Piaget. In L. S. Liben (Ed.), Piaget and the foundations of knowledge (pp. 1–18). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wartofsky, M. (1983b). The child’s construction of the world and the world’s construction of the child: From historical epistemology to historical psychology. In F. S. Kessel & A. S. Siegel (Eds.), The child and other cultural inventions (pp. 1–18). New York: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wartofsky, M. (1987). Epistemology historicized. In A. Shimony & D. Nails (Eds.), Naturalistic epistemology (pp. 357–374). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zwijtink, Z. (1995). Lorenz Krüger and the relation between history and philosophy of science. In Memorial symposium for Lorenz Krüger. Max Planck-Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte, Preprint 38, 21–26.

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank the speakers, commentators and other participants of the 2008 conference. In addition to that, the authors are especially grateful to the anonymous referees as well as John Carson, Lorraine Daston, Pierre-Olivier Methot, Jürgen Renn, and Hans-Jörg Rheinberger for various comments and suggestions. Thomas Sturm’s work on this article was supported by the Spanish Ministry for Science and Innovation, Reference number FFI 2008-01559/FISO.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Uljana Feest.

Additional information

Uljana Feest and Thomas Sturm have contributed equally to this article.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Feest, U., Sturm, T. What (Good) is Historical Epistemology? Editors’ Introduction. Erkenn 75, 285–302 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-011-9345-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-011-9345-4

Keywords

Navigation