Skip to main content
Log in

Harm and the concept of medical disorder

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to Jerome Wakefield’s harmful dysfunction analysis (HDA) of medical disorder, the inability of some internal part or mechanism to perform its natural function is necessary, but not sufficient, for disorder. HDA also requires that the part dysfunction be harmful to the individual. I consider several problems for HDA’s harm criterion in this article. Other accounts on which harm is necessary for disorder will suffer from all or almost all of these problems. Comparative accounts of harm imply that one is harmed when one is made worse off, that is, worse off than one otherwise would have been. Non-comparative accounts imply that one is harmed when one is put into some kind of condition or state that is, in some way, bad in itself. I argue that whether harm is construed comparatively or non-comparatively, HDA’s harm criterion is problematic. I tentatively conclude that an analysis of medical disorder should not make use of the concept of harm.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See [1,2,3]. Many of the arguments will also threaten views that employ similar notions, for example, the malady account defended by Culver and Gert [4].

  2. The division of accounts of harm into comparative and non-comparative ones is common and useful. For some more discussion of the taxonomy, see Bradley [5] and Hanser [6].

  3. See especially [7, p. 384].

  4. For example, a doctor might administer drugs that will slow the rate of increase of a patient’s pain and suffering, so that the patient is worse off after the treatment than she was before it, but is much better off than she would have been without it. It is fairly clear that the doctor has benefited rather than harmed the patient, which indicates that we compare levels of well-being across worlds or outcomes, not times. For additional criticism of the temporal account, see [9, p. 368; 10, pp. 149–150].

  5. For more discussion, see Wakefield [8, pp. 674–676] and Spitzer [11].

  6. For an introduction to these issues and a nice review of the challenges to cultural relativism, see [12, ch. 2]. For some more critical discussion, see [13, ch. 11].

  7. I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this example.

  8. This terminology comes from Barnes [14].

  9. For discussion of the problem that preemption poses for the comparative account, see [5, 6, 10, 18, 19]. See also Parfit [20, ch. 3].

  10. See, for example, [15, p. 23; 21, p. 89].

  11. Cf. [6, p. 434].

  12. Reznek [3, pp. 161–162] holds that standard members of a species, not all members, need be harmed.

  13. A detailed account along these lines appears in [19]. See also [20, pp. 70–83; 22, pp. 127–135].

  14. There are cases in which a group of conditions or events can harm an individual even though there is no smallest group of the sort described in the text. I discuss and account for such cases in [19]. The complication is irrelevant here, however, and so I shall ignore it.

  15. For some discussion of the harm of events in a sequence, see [5, 6, 19].

  16. Wakefield [personal communication] has suggested, in the abstract case, that the disorder is the group, or complex, that results from X and Y taken together.

  17. The non-identity problem is most closely associated with the work of Derek Parfit. See [23; 20, ch. 16]. It has since been extremely widely discussed. For an excellent, recent, and thorough book length discussion, see [24].

  18. I find it plausible that if the sperm and egg whose fusion brought me about had never come together, then I would not have existed. This claim is widely accepted, but it is controversial. For a recent example see Lewens [25, ch. 6], who argues generally that interventions that affect one’s identity are quite likely rarer than they are widely believed to be. Again, however, the strong metaphysical claim is not needed.

  19. See [26] for a detailed discussion and defense of this perspective.

  20. One might claim that every dysfunction is harmful, so that the harm criterion is redundant and disorder can be analyzed merely in terms of dysfunction. This would allow one to accept Harman’s account and say that disorders are harmful dysfunctions. Of course, we might as well say they are dysfunctions since “harmful” has become redundant. De Block [28] defends a view like this, but his notion of dysfunction differs from that of Wakefield. See also Boorse [15, pp. 34–5] for some discussion.

  21. For a widely discussed non-comparative account, see [29]. See also [30, 31]. For critical discussion of non-comparative accounts generally, see [5, 6].

  22. For more discussion, see [5, pp. 400–401].

  23. For some recent discussion of this issue, see [33, 34]. In fact, Schwartz (see [34]), who argues that an account of disease is best understood as a proposal about how to define and use terms, thinks that Boorse’s naturalistic account (the BST) is to be preferred.

  24. I would like to thank audience members at the 2015 PANTC (Plato’s Academy North Tonawanda Campus) Conference on Bioethics and the Philosophy of Medicine for extremely helpful comments and suggestions. In particular, I am grateful to Christopher Boorse, Stephen Kershnar, Jerome Wakefield, and (especially) to David Hershenov.

References

  1. Cooper, Rachel. 2002. Disease. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biology & the Biomedical Sciences 33: 263–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Harris, John. 2007. Enhancing evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Reznek, Lawrie. 1987. The nature of disease. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Culver, Charles M., and Bernard Gert. 1982. Philosophy in medicine. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Bradley, Ben. 2012. Doing away with harm. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85: 390–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Hanser, Matthew. 2008. The metaphysics of harm. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77: 421–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Wakefield, Jerome C. 1992. The concept of mental disorder: On the boundary between biological facts and social values. American Psychologist 47: 373–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Wakefield, Jerome C. 2014. The biostatistical theory versus the harmful dysfunction analysis, part 1: Is part-dysfunction sufficient for medical disorder? Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 39: 648–682.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Holtug, Nils. 2002. The harm principle. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 5: 357–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Norcross, Alastair. 2005. Harming in context. Philosophical Studies 123: 149–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Spitzer, Robert L. 1981. The diagnostic status of homosexuality in DSM-III: A reformulation of the issues. American Journal of Psychiatry 138: 210–215.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Rachels, James, and Stuart Rachels. 2014. The elements of moral philosophy. 8th ed. New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Feldman, Fred. 1978. Introductory ethics. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Barnes, Elizabeth. 2014. Valuing disability, causing disability. Ethics 125: 88–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Boorse, Christopher. 2011. Concepts of health and disease. In Philosophy of medicine, vol. 16 of the Handbook of the philosophy of science, ed. Fred Gifford, 13–64. New York: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  16. Wakefield, Jerome C. 2006. Personality disorder as harmful dysfunction: DSM’s cultural deviance criterion reconsidered. Journal of Personality Disorders 20: 157–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Wakefield, Jerome C. 2013. Addiction, the concept of disorder, and pathways to harm: Comment on Levy. Frontiers in Addictive Disorders & Behavioral Dyscontrol 4: 1–2.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Klocksiem, Justin. 2012. A defense of the counterfactual comparative account of harm. American Philosophical Quarterly 49: 285–300.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Feit, Neil. 2015. Plural harm. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 90: 361–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and persons. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Boorse, Christopher. 1997. A rebuttal on health. In What is disease? ed. James M. Humber and Robert F. Almeder, 1–134. Totowa, NJ: Humana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. McMahan, Jeff. 2002. The ethics of killing: Problems at the margins of life. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  23. Parfit, Derek. 1976. On doing the best for our children. In Ethics and population, ed. Michael D. Bayles, 100–115. Cambridge, MA: Schenkman.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Boonin, David. 2014. The non-identity problem and the ethics of future people. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  25. Lewens, Tim. 2015. The biological foundations of bioethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  26. Feit, Neil. 2016. Comparative harm, creation and death. Utilitas 28: 136–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Harman, Elizabeth. 2009. Harming as causing harm. In Harming future persons, ed. Melinda A. Roberts and David T. Wasserman, 137–154. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  28. De Block, Andreas. 2008. Why mental disorders are just mental dysfunctions (and nothing more): Some Darwinian arguments. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C 39: 338–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Shiffrin, Seana. 1999. Wrongful life, procreative responsibility, and the significance of harm. Legal Theory 5: 117–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Harman, Elizabeth. 2004. Can we harm and benefit in creating? Philosophical Perspectives 18: 89–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Rivera-Lopez, Eduardo. 2009. Individual procreative responsibility and the non-identity problem. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90: 336–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Nagel, Thomas. 1970. Death. Noûs 4: 73–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Lemoine, Mael. 2013. Defining disease beyond conceptual analysis: An analysis of conceptual analysis in philosophy of medicine. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 34: 309–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Schwartz, Peter. 2014. Reframing the disease debate and defending the biostatistical theory. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 39: 572–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Neil Feit.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Ethical approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Feit, N. Harm and the concept of medical disorder. Theor Med Bioeth 38, 367–385 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-017-9418-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-017-9418-8

Keywords

Navigation