Skip to main content
Log in

How children approach the false belief test: social development, pragmatics, and the assembly of Theory of Mind

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Evidence from the knowledge access task and the diverse belief task suggests that, before age four, children may find it difficult to attribute false beliefs to others, despite demonstrating a basic comprehension of the concept of belief. Challenging this view, this article assumes a sociopragmatic perspective on language to argue that even children younger than four may not understand at all the concept of belief but may nevertheless master naïvely the pragmatics of belief reports in specific conversational contexts. The proposal suggests a novel interpretation of both the reasons behind younger children’s difficulty with (elicited-response) false belief tasks, and the critical factors enabling children’s success in them. On the one hand, it proposes that younger children fail (elicited-response) false belief tasks because they do not understand the importance of focusing on an agent’s (verbally ascribed) mental states to infer her practical commitments. On the other hand, it suggests that children’s active engagement in conversations where the caregiver credits an agent with a belief is the critical factor integrating their initially scattered mastery of the pragmatics of belief reports, teaches them to track belief reports across contexts, and accordingly shapes their understanding of belief as a representational mental state.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In what follows, I will usually confine the discussion to the location-change version of FBT as meta-analyses (Wellman et al. 2001) showed that children perform similarly in this and other tasks like the unexpected content FBT (Hogrefe et al. 1986), and the unexpected identity FBT (Gopnik and Astington 1988).

  2. Interestingly enough, cross-cultural studies have shown significant variation in the developmental trajectories for KAT, DBT, and FBT. While children from the United States and Australia first pass DBT and then KAT (Wellman and Liu 2004), Chinese and Iranian children reliably pass these two tasks in the reverse order (Shahaeian et al. 2011; Wellman et al. 2006, 2011). Although the reason for such a variation are still debated, it is sufficient for the present discussion that children reliably pass KAT and DBT earlier than FBT.

  3. Accordingly, Wellman and Liu (2004) write that children’s correct answering in KAT attests that they “understand ignorance (e.g., that … [Polly] does not know what is in a container)” (p. 529, my emphasis), and that passing DBT indicates that “children can judge that they and someone else can have differing beliefs about the same situation” (p. 536).

  4. In fact, I have argued more in detail in other works (Fenici 2015a; Fenici and Zawidzki 2016) that infants’ socio-cognitive abilities depend on a basic capacity to form expectations about the outcome of others’ actions. This capacity is a particular case of the general capacity to learn from observed events what is normal and habitual in their environment, and does not originally involve knowledge specific to the social domain. However, it improves progressively through learning in the first years of life facilitated by social interaction up to the point of tracking first what other agents can (and cannot) gaze at, and then what other agents did (and did not) gaze at in the past—and thus still believe in the present (see also Fenici 2016, 2017b; Fenici and Garofoli 2020 for critical discussion of competitive accounts).

  5. For the sake of simplicity, I will hereafter use ‘FBT’ to refer exclusively to elicited-response FBTs.

  6. See Budwig (2002) for another extremely significant report on the limited understanding of desires manifested by children’s earlier uses of want, and how it progresses through the interaction with the caregiver.

  7. This is particularly relevant in the process of solving disputes, where expressing uncertainty about the truth of a stated sentence may be relevant to focus the discussion on whether to accept a practically committing statement as a common ground or rather reject it.

References

  • Allen, J. W. P., & Bickhard, M. H. (2011). Emergent constructivism. Child Development Perspectives, 5(3), 164–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, J. W. P., & Bickhard, M. H. (2013). Stepping off the pendulum: Why only an action-based approach can transcend the nativist–empiricist debate. Cognitive Development, 28(2), 96–133. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogdev.2013.01.002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, J. W. P., & Bickhard, M. H. (2018). Stage fright: Internal reflection as a domain general enabling constraint on the emergence of explicit thought. Cognitive Development, 45, 77–91. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogdev.2017.12.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amsterlaw, J., & Wellman, H. M. (2006). Theories of mind in transition: A microgenetic study of the development of false belief understanding. Journal of Cognition and Development, 7(2), 139–172. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15327647jcd0702_1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, K. (2012). Do apes read minds?: Toward a new folk psychology. MIT Press.

  • Apperly, I. A., & Butterfill, S. A. (2009). Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states? Psychological Review, 116(4), 953–970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appleton, M., & Reddy, V. (1996). Teaching three year-olds to pass false belief tests: A conversational approach. Social Development, 5(3), 275–291. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9507.1996.tb00086.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Astington, J. W., & Baird, J. A. (Eds.). (2005). Why language matters for theory of mind. Oxford University Press.

  • Atance, C. M., & O’Neill, D. K. (2004). Acting and planning on the basis of a false belief: Its effects on 3-year-old children’s reasoning about their own false beliefs. Developmental Psychology, 40(6), 953–964.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R., Scott, R. M., & He, Z. (2010). False-belief understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(3), 110–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R., Scott, R. M., & Bian, L. (2016). Psychological reasoning in infancy. Annual Review of Psychology, 67, 159–186. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-psych-010213-115033.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banovsky, J. (2016). Theories, structures and simulations in the research of early mentalizing. Cognitive Systems Research, 40, 129–143. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogsys.2016.05.003.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A. M., & Frith, U. (1985). Does the autistic child have a “theory of mind”? Cognition, 21(1), 37–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartsch, K., & Wellman, H. M. (1995). Children talk about the mind. Oxford University Press.

  • Bigelow, A. E., & Dugas, K. (2008). Relations among preschool children’s understanding of visual perspective taking, false belief, and lying. Journal of Cognition and Development, 9(4), 411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. S. (1983). Child’s talk: Learning to use language. W W Norton & Co Inc..

  • Bruner, J. S. (1990). Acts of meaning. Harvard University Press.

  • Budwig, N. (2002). A developmental-functionalist approach to mental state talk. Language, Literacy, and Cognitive Development: The Development and Consequences of Symbolic Communication, 59–86.

  • Butterfill, S. A., & Apperly, I. A. (2013). How to construct a minimal theory of mind. Mind & Language, 28, 606–637.

    Google Scholar 

  • Canfield, J. V. (2007). Becoming human. The Development of Language, Self and Consciousness. Palgrave Macmillan. http://www.palgrave.com/la/book/9780230552937

  • Carlson, S. M., & Moses, L. J. (2001). Individual differences in inhibitory control and children’s theory of mind. Child Development, 72(4), 1032–1053.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carpendale, J. I. M., & Lewis, C. (2006). How children develop social understanding. Wiley.

  • Carpendale, J. I. M., & Lewis, C. (2015). The development of social understanding. In Handbook of Child Psychology and Developmental Science. John Wiley & Sons, Inc.

  • Carruthers, P. (2016). Two Systems for Mindreading? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 7(1), 141–162. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0259-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1994). Beliefs and desires incorporated. Journal of Philosophy, 91(8), 404–425.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2006). Language, embodiment, and the cognitive niche. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10(8), 370–374. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2006.06.012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowley, S. J., Moodley, S., & Fiori-Cowley, A. (2004). Grounding signs of culture: Primary Intersubjectivity in social Semiosis. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 11(2), 109–132. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15327884mca1102_3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2014). Teleological understanding of actions. In M. Banaji & S. A. Gelman (Eds.), Navigating the social world: What infants, Chidren, and other species can teach us. Oxford University Press.

  • de Bruin, L. C., & Newen, A. (2012). The developmental paradox of false belief understanding: A dual-system solution. Synthese, 1–24.

  • de Villiers, J. G. (2005). Can language acquisition give children a point of view? In J. W. Astington & J. A. Baird (Eds.), Why Language Matters for Theory of Mind (pp. 186–219). Oxford University Press.

  • de Villiers, J. G., & de Villiers, P. A. (2000). Linguistic determinism and the understanding of false beliefs. In P. Mitchell & K. J. Riggs, Children’s Reasoning and the Mind (pp. 191–228). Psychology press.

  • de Villiers, J. G., & Pyers, J. E. (2002). Complements to cognition: A longitudinal study of the relationship between complex syntax and false-belief-understanding. Cognitive Development, 17(1), 1037–1060.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1987). The intentional stance. The MIT Press.

  • Diessel, H., & Tomasello, M. (2001). The acquisition of finite complement clauses in English: A corpus-based analysis. Cognitive Linguistics, 12(2), 97–142. https://doi.org/10.1515/cogl.12.2.97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J., & Brophy, M. (2005). Communication, relationships, and individual differences in children’s understanding of mind. In J. W. Astington & J. A. Baird (Eds.), Why Language Matters for Theory of Mind (pp. 50–69). Oxford University Press.

  • Dunn, J., Brown, J. R., & Beardsall, L. (1991). Family talk about feeling states and children’s later understanding of others’ emotions. Developmental Psychology, 27(3), 448–455.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farrant, B. M., Fletcher, J., & Maybery, M. T. (2006). Specific language impairment, theory of mind, and visual perspective taking: Evidence for simulation theory and the developmental role of language. Child Development, 77(6), 1842–1853.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenici, M. (2012). Embodied social cognition and embedded theory of mind. Biolinguistics, 6(3–4), 276–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenici, M. (2015a). A simple explanation of apparent early mindreading: Infants’ sensitivity to goals and gaze direction. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14(3), 497–515. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-014-9345-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fenici, M. (2015b). Social cognitive abilities in infancy: Is mindreading the best explanation? Philosophical Psychology, 28(3), 387–411. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2013.865096.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fenici, M. (2016). Comments on Helming, Strick land, and Jacob, “solving the puzzle about early belief-ascription". In R. Briscoe (Ed.), Symposium on Helming, Strickland, and Jacob, “Solving the Puzzle about Early Belief-Ascription.” The Brains Blog. http://philosophyofbrains.com/2016/10/17/symposium-on-helming-strickland-and-jacob-solving-the-puzzle-about-early-belief-ascription.aspx

  • Fenici, M. (2017a). Rebuilding the landscape of psychological understanding after the mindreading war. Phenomenology and Mind, 12, 142–150. https://doi.org/10.13128/Phe_Mi-21113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fenici, M. (2017b). What is the role of experience in children’s success in the false belief test: Maturation, facilitation, attunement or induction? Mind & Language, 32(3), 308–337. https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fenici, M., & Garofoli, D. (2017). The biocultural emergence of mindreading: Integrating cognitive archaeology and human development. Journal of Cultural Cognitive Science, 1(2), 89–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenici, M., & Garofoli, D. (2020). An Associationist Bias explains different processing demands for toddlers in different traditional false-belief tasks. Human Development, 64(1), 4–6. https://doi.org/10.1159/000505208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fenici, M., & Zawidzki, T. W. (2016). Action understanding in infancy: Do infant interpreters attribute enduring mental states or track relational properties of transient bouts of behavior? Studia Philosophica Estonica, 9(2), 237–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenici, M., & Zawidzki, T. W. (2020). The origins of mindreading: How interpretive socio-cognitive practices get off the ground. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02577-4.

  • Fernyhough, C. (2008). Getting Vygotskian about theory of mind: Mediation, dialogue, and the development of social understanding. Developmental Review, 28(2), 225–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, O., Griffin, R., Brownell, H., & Winner, E. (2003). Problems with the seeing = knowing rule. Developmental Science, 6(5), 505–513. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-7687.00308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Hutto, D. D. (2008). Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In J. Zlatev, T. P. Racine, C. Sinha, & E. Itkonen (Eds.), The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity (pp. 17–38). John Benjamins Publishing Company.

  • Gopnik, A. (1996). The scientist as child. Philosophy of Science, 63(4), 485–514.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Astington, J. W. (1988). Children’s understanding of representational change and its telation to the understanding of false belief and the appearance-reality distinction. Child Development, 59(1), 26–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Graf, P. (1988). Knowing how you know: Young children’s ability to identify and remember the sources of their beliefs. Child Development, 59(5), 1366–1371. https://doi.org/10.2307/1130499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1996). Words, thoughts, and theories. The MIT Press.

  • Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (1994). The Theory Theory. In L. A. Hirschfeld & S. A. Gelman, Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity in Cognition and Culture (pp. 257–293). Cambridge University press.

  • Gordon, R. M. (1986). Folk psychology as simulation. Mind & Language, 1(2), 158–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guajardo, N. R., Parker, J., & Turley-Ames, K. (2009). Associations among false belief understanding, counterfactual reasoning, and executive function. The British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 27(3), 681–702.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, M. B. (2010). If you know something, say something: Young children’s problem with false beliefs. Developmental Psychology, 1, 23. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2010.00023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, P. L. (1996). Desires, beliefs, and language. In P. Carruthers & P. K. Smith (Eds.), Theories of Theories of Mind (pp. 200–220). Cambridge University Press.

  • Harris, P. L. (1999). Acquiring the art of conversation: Children’s developing conception of their conversation partner. In M. Bennett (Ed.), Developmental Psychology: Achievements and Prospects (pp. 89–105). Psychology Press.

  • Helming, K. A., Strickland, B., & Jacob, P. (2016). Solving the puzzle about early belief-ascription. Mind & Language, 31(4), 438–469. https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. M. (2014). False belief in infancy: A fresh look. Developmental Psychology.

  • Heyes, C. M. (2018). Cognitive gadgets: The cultural evolution of thinking. Belknap Press: An Imprint of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. M., & Frith, C. D. (2014). The cultural evolution of mind reading. Science (New York, N.Y.), 344(6190), 1243091. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1243091.

  • Hogrefe, G.-J., Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1986). Ignorance versus false belief: A developmental lag in attribution of epistemic states. Child Development, 57, 567–582.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2004). The limits of spectatorial folk psychology. Mind & Language, 19(5), 548–573.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2008). Folk psychological narratives. The MIT Press.

  • Hutto, D. D. (2015). Basic social cognition without mindreading: Minding minds without attributing contents. Synthese, 194, 1–20. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0831-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iliopoulos, A., & Garofoli, D. (2016). The material dimensions of cognition: Reexamining the nature and emergence of the human mind. Quaternary International, 405, Part A (The material dimensions of cognition), 1–7.

  • Kirk, E., Pine, K., Wheatley, L., Howlett, N., Schulz, J., & Fletcher, B. (C). (2015). A longitudinal investigation of the relationship between maternal mind-mindedness and theory of mind. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 33(4), 434–445. https://doi.org/10.1111/bjdp.12104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenig, M. A. (2002). Children’s understanding of belief as a normative concept. New Ideas in Psychology, 20(2–3), 107–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (2005). Developmental parallels in understanding minds and bodies. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9(10), 459–462. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2005.08.002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Low, J., & Edwards, K. (2017). The curious case of adults’ interpretations of violation-of-expectation false belief scenarios. Cognitive Development., 46, 86–96. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogdev.2017.07.004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2013). How things shape the mind. The MIT Press https://mitpress.mit.edu/books/how-things-shape-mind.

  • Meins, E., Fernyhough, C., Wainwright, R., Clark-Carter, D., Gupta, M. D., Fradley, E., & Tuckey, M. (2003). Pathways to understanding mind: Construct validity and predictive validity of maternal mind-mindedness. Child Development, 74(4), 1194–1211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R., & Kirchhoff, M. (2014). Cognitive transformations and extended expertise. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 46(6), 610–623. https://doi.org/10.1080/00131857.2013.779209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milligan, K., Astington, J. W., & Dack, L. A. (2007). Language and theory of mind: Meta-analysis of the relation between language ability and false-belief understanding. Child Development, 78(2), 622–646.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moll, H., & Tomasello, M. (2007). How 14- and 18-month-olds know what others have experienced. Developmental Psychology, 43(2), 309–317. https://doi.org/10.1037/0012-1649.43.2.309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montgomery, D. E. (2005). The developmental origins of meaning for mental terms. In J. W. Astington & J. A. Baird (Eds.), Why language matters for theory of mind (pp. 106–122). Oxford University Press.

  • Moran, R. (2001). Authority and estrangement: An essay on self-knowledge. Princeton Univ Pr.

  • Moses, L. J., & Flavell, J. H. (1990). Inferring false beliefs from actions and reactions. Child Development, 61(4), 929–945.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, K. (1996). Language in cognitive development: The emergence of the mediated mind (New edizione). Cambridge University Press.

  • Nelson, K. (2009). Narrative and folk psychology. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16(6–8), 69–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, K., & Shaw, L. K. (2002). Developing a socially shared symbolic system. In Language, literacy, and cognitive development (pp. 39–72). Psychology Press.

  • O’Neill, D. K., Astington, J. W., & Flavell, J. H. (1992). Young Children’s understanding of the role that sensory experiences play in knowledge acquisition. Child Development, 63(2), 474–490. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8624.1992.tb01641.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papafragou, A., Cassidy, K. W., & Gleitman, L. (2007). When we think about thinking: The acquisition of belief verbs. Cognition, 105(1), 125–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. The MIT Press.

  • Perner, J. (2010). Who took the cog out of cognitive science? Mentalism in an era of anti-cognitivism. In P. A. Frensch & R. Schwarzer (Eds.), Cognition and neuropsychology international perspectives on psychological science (Vol. 1, pp. 241–261). Psychology Press.

  • Perner, J., & Ruffman, T. (2005). Infants’ insight into the mind: How deep? Science, 308(5719), 214–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., Lang, B., & Kloo, D. (2002). Theory of mind and self-control: More than a common problem of inhibition. Child Development, 73(3), 752–767.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., Sprung, M., Zauner, P., & Haider, H. (2003). Want that is understood well before say that, think that, and false belief: A test of de Villiers’s linguistic determinism on german-speaking children. Child Development, 74(1), 179–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., Huemer, M., & Leahy, B. (2015). Mental files and belief: A cognitive theory of how children represent belief and its intensionality. Cognition, 145, 77–88. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2015.08.006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, C., & Bryant, P. (1990). Young children understand that looking leads to knowing (so long as they are looking into a single barrel). Child Development, 61(4), 973–982. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8624.1990.tb02835.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Premack, D., & Woodruff, G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1(04), 515–526.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rakoczy, H. (2012). Do infants have a theory of mind? British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 30(1), 59–74. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.2044-835X.2011.02061.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rakoczy, H. (2017). In defense of a developmental dogma: Children acquire propositional attitude folk psychology around age 4. Synthese, 194(3), 689–707. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0860-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V. (2008). How infants know minds. Harvard University Press.

  • Rhodes, M., & Wellman, H. (2013). Constructing a new theory from old ideas and new evidence. Cognitive Science, 37(3), 592–604.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, J. F. (2004). Ryleans and outlookers: Wilfrid Sellars on “Mental States.”. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 28(1), 239–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubio-Fernández, P., & Geurts, B. (2013). How to pass the false-belief task before your fourth birthday. Psychological Science, 24(1), 27–33. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797612447819.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruffman, T. (2014). To belief or not belief: Children’s theory of mind. Developmental Review, 34(3), 265–293. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.dr.2014.04.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruffman, T., Slade, L., & Crowe, E. (2002). The relation between children’s and mothers’ mental state language and theory-of-mind understanding. Child Development, 73(3), 734–751.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saxe, R. (2013). The new puzzle of theory of mind development. In M. R. Banaji & S. A. Gelman (Eds.), Navigating the social world: What infants, children, and other species can teach us. Oxford University Press.

  • Schegloff, E. A. (1995). Discourse as an interactional achievement III: The Omnirelevance of action. Research on Language and Social Interaction, 28(3), 185–211. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15327973rlsi2803_2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1, 253–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1969). Language as thought and as communication. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 29(4), 506–527.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shahaeian, A., Peterson, C. C., Slaughter, V., & Wellman, H. M. (2011). Culture and the sequence of steps in theory of mind development. Developmental Psychology, 47(5), 1239–1247. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0023899.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons, M. (2007). Observations on embedding verbs, evidentiality, and presupposition. Lingua, 117(6), 1034–1056. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2006.05.006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taumoepeau, M., & Ruffman, T. (2006). Mother and infant talk about mental states relates to desire language and emotion understanding. Child Development, 77(2), 465–481.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Harvard University Press.

  • Tomasello, M. (2003). Constructing a language. Harvard University Press.

  • Tomasello, M. (2009). The usage-based theory of language acquisition. In E. Bavin (Ed.), The Cambridge Handbook of Child Language (pp. 69–88). Cambridge University Press.

  • Tomasello, M. (2018). How children come to understand false beliefs: A shared intentionality account. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 115(34), 8491–8498.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., & Haberl, K. (2003). Understanding attention: 12- and 18-month-olds know what is new for other persons. Developmental Psychology, 39(5), 906–912. https://doi.org/10.1037/0012-1649.39.5.906.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. (1977). Descriptive analysis of infant communicative behaviour. In H. R. Schaffer, Studies in mother-infant interaction (pp. 227–270). Academic press.

  • Turnbull, W. (2003). Language in action: Psychological models of conversation (1 edition). Routledge.

  • Turnbull, W., & Carpendale, J. I. M. (1999). A social pragmatic model of talk: Implications for research on the development of Children’s social understanding. Human Development, 42(6), 328–355. https://doi.org/10.1159/000022641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turnbull, W., Carpendale, J. I. M., & Racine, T. P. (2008). Relations between mother-child talk and 3- to 5 year-old children’s understanding of belief: Beyond mental state terms to talk about the mind. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 54(3), 367–385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleave, M., & Gauker, C. (2010). Linguistic practice and false-belief tasks. Mind & Language, 25(3), 298–328. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0017.2010.01391.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society: The development of higher psychological processes. Harvard University Press.

  • Wellman, H. M. (1990). The child’s theory of mind. The MIT Press.

  • Wellman, H. M. (2002). Understanding the psychological world: Developing a theory of mind. In U. Goswami, Blackwell Handbook of Childhood Cognitive Development (pp. 167–187). Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Wellman, H. M. (2014). Making minds: How theory of mind develops. In Making minds. Oxford University Press.

  • Wellman, H. M., & Bartsch, K. (1988). Young children’s reasoning about beliefs. Cognition, 30(3), 239–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. M., & Liu, D. (2004). Scaling of theory-of-mind tasks. Child Development, 75, 523–541.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. M., & Peterson, C. C. (2013). Deafness, thought bubbles, and theory-of-mind development. Developmental Psychology, 49(12), 2357–2367. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0032419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. M., Hollander, M., & Schult, C. A. (1996). Young children’s understanding of thought bubbles and of thoughts. Child Development, 67(3), 768–788.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. M., Cross, D., & Watson, J. (2001). Meta-analysis of theory-of-mind development: The truth about false belief. Child Development, 72(3), 655–684.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. M., Fang, F., Liu, D., Zhu, L., & Liu, G. (2006). Scaling of theory-of-mind understandings in Chinese children. Psychological Science, 17(12), 1075–1081. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9280.2006.01830.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. M., Fang, F., & Peterson, C. C. (2011). Sequential progressions in a theory-of-mind scale: Longitudinal perspectives. Child Development, 82(3), 780–792. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8624.2011.01583.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wertsch, J. V. (1979). From social interaction to higher psychological processes: A clarification and application of Vygotsky’s theory. Human Development, 22(1), 1–22. https://doi.org/10.1159/000272425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westra, E. (2017). Pragmatic development and the false belief task. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 8(2), 235–257. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-016-0320-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westra, E., & Carruthers, P. (2017). Pragmatic development explains the theory-of-mind scale. Cognition, 158, 165–176. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2016.10.021.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whiten, A., & Erdal, D. (2012). The human socio-cognitive niche and its evolutionary origins. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 367(1599), 2119–2129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, H., & Mayringer, H. (1998). False belief understanding in young children: Explanations do not develop before predictions. International Journal of Behavioral Development, 22(2), 403–422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition, 13(1), 103–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, H., & Weichbold, V. (1994). Children’s theory of mind: Fodor’s heuristics examined. Cognition, 53(1), 45–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Blackwell.

  • Zawidzki, T. W. (2011). How to interpret infant socio-cognitive competence. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(3), 483–497.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. W. (2013). Mindshaping. A new framework for understanding human social cognition. The MIT Press.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Jedediah Allen, Kristin Andrews, Jeremy Carpendale, Jay Garfield, Hande Ilgaz, Eleonora Mercatelli, Josef Perner, Silvano Zipoli Caiani, and many anonymous reviewers for useful discussion and comments on previous versions of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco Fenici.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fenici, M. How children approach the false belief test: social development, pragmatics, and the assembly of Theory of Mind. Phenom Cogn Sci 21, 181–201 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-020-09709-8

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-020-09709-8

Keywords

Navigation