Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

Expressiveness and definability in circumscription

Abstract

We investigate expressiveness and definability issues with respect to minimal models, particularly in the scope of Circumscription. First, we give a proof of the failure of the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for Circumscription. Then we show that, if the class of P; Z-minimal models of a first-order sentence is Δ-elementary, then it is elementary. That is, whenever the circumscription of a first-order sentence is equivalent to a first-order theory, then it is equivalent to a finitely axiomatizable one. This means that classes of models of circumscribed theories are either elementary or not Δ-elementary. Finally, using the previous result, we prove that, whenever a relation Pi is defined in the class of P; Z-minimal models of a first-order sentence Φ and whenever such class of P; Z-minimal models is Δ-elementary, then there is an explicit definition ψ for Pi such that the class of P; Z-minimal models of Φ is the class of models of Φ ∧ ψ. In order words, the circumscription of P in Φ with Z varied can be replaced by Φ plus this explicit definition ψ for Pi.

Minimal models; Circumscripition; Expressiveness; Definability


Expressiveness and definability in circumscription

Francicleber Martins Ferreira1 1 This author was partially supported by CNPq, FUNCAP, CAPES (DS, PROCAD 2010). ; Ana Teresa Martins2 2 This author was partially supported by CNPq (PQ, Casadinho 2008, Universal 2010) and CAPES (PROCAD 2010).

Departamento de Computação, Universidade Federal do Ceará, Fortaleza, CE, CP 12.166, BRASIL, fran@lia.ufc.br, ana@lia.ufc.br

ABSTRACT

We investigate expressiveness and definability issues with respect to minimal models, particularly in the scope of Circumscription. First, we give a proof of the failure of the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for Circumscription. Then we show that, if the class of P; Z-minimal models of a first-order sentence is Δ-elementary, then it is elementary. That is, whenever the circumscription of a first-order sentence is equivalent to a first-order theory, then it is equivalent to a finitely axiomatizable one. This means that classes of models of circumscribed theories are either elementary or not Δ-elementary. Finally, using the previous result, we prove that, whenever a relation Pi is defined in the class of P; Z-minimal models of a first-order sentence Φ and whenever such class of P; Z-minimal models is Δ-elementary, then there is an explicit definition ψ for Pi such that the class of P; Z-minimal models of Φ is the class of models of Φ ∧ ψ. In order words, the circumscription of P in Φ with Z varied can be replaced by Φ plus this explicit definition ψ for Pi.

Keywords: Minimal models. Circumscripition. Expressiveness. Definability.

1. INTRODUCTION

In practical situations, people reason and act without having complete or sufficient knowledge about the situation that they are dealing with. Sometimes, there is no way or it is too much expensive to obtain all the necessary information in order to be secure about our conclusions. However, in such cases, we may find ourselves in a position in which it is mandatory to take some action or make some inferences. For instance, a pilot which need to abort landing the airplane for some technical problem just discovered will immediately go-around instead of waiting for the confirmation that this action will not lead to a crash with another aircraft. Reasoning under such circumstances is, thus, required. Any system intended to describe or simulate practical reasoning must be able to deal with the lack of information. Actually, even in daily activities we assume beliefs which we take as certain, but for which there is no logical, deductive justification (Hume (1748)). However, although we cannot deduce from earlier facts that to put ours hands on the fire will burn them, no mentally healthy person will do this and think that nothing will go wrong.

The lack of information and the need of drawing conclusions force us to go beyond of which can be deduced from our partial, current knowledge. In real life, we make use of general or uncertain knowledge, such as that "birds generally flies" and that penguins do not, to guide us in the task of making such assumptions. However, due to the character of uncertainty of such sort of assumption, it may be confronted with new, reliable information and be refuted. Hence, besides the ability of handling the lack of information and the use of general and uncertain knowledge, another feature of a system that models practical reasoning is to be able to backtrack and drop some previous conclusions inferred from uncertain assumptions in order to stay consistent with the new information obtained.

In order to formalize practical reasoning under partial knowledge, classical logic is not appropriate. In fact, classical logic is deductive and, as a deductive approach to reasoning, classical logic cannot go beyond and infer more than what is already known. As we argued above, in practical situations one must conclude more than what can be deduced, that is, a logical system for practical reasoning must allow non-deductive inferences. Another feature of classical reasoning is the monotonicity property: the addition of new premises does not invalidate previous inferences. On the contrary, logical systems for practical reasoning must be non-monotonic, since conclusions taken under partial knowledge may be defeated. Hence, classical logic is not suited to properly deal with practical reasoning.

In the 1980s, with the increasing interest in Artificial Intelligence, some non-monotonic logical systems where proposed to formalize practical reasoning, such as Reiter's Default logic Reiter (1980), Doyle and McDermott's Non-Monotonic logic McDermott, Doyle (1980) and McCarthy's Circumscription McCarthy (1980, 1986). Our focus, here, is in the latter approach since we are interested in minimal models, as we explain below.

McCarthy's Predicate Circumscription is one of the most studied logical approaches to non-monotonic reasoning (see Lifschitz (1994) for a good introduction and extensive bibliography). In McCarthy (1980), McCarthy introduces Circumscription to deal with the Qualification Problem. The Qualification Problem is the problem of describing or qualifying the necessary conditions to take an action or safely infer some information in a given situation. As argued in McCarthy (1980), it is practically impossible to deal with the huge amount of constraints or conditions necessary for the success of an action. In practice, people disregard many possible obstacles or assumptions contrary to some conclusion just because they are unknown, there is no evidence for it, or they usually do not happen. Usually, we concentrate on the relevant evidences drawing conclusions even in the absence of information about conditions of success. We also suppose, under the lack of knowledge about the consequences of some action, that things not directly involved in the action will stand as they were before the action was taken. McCarthy argued also that if, on the one hand, we must go beyond what can be deduced from the known information, on the other hand we should avoid unreasonable assumptions. That is the case, for instance, of the winged horse solution for McCarthy's Missionaries and Cannibals puzzle McCarthy (1980). General or default knowledge is used as an heuristics, a guide to reasoning.

The intuitive idea of Predicate Circumscription is to consider that the objects which have some property are only those necessary to satisfy the problem description. In McCarthy (1980), Predicate Circumscription was introduced as a first-order formula schema and, in McCarthy (1986), as a second-order formula, with an additional extension called Formula Circumscription. Here, we will call them first-order Circumscription and second-order Circumscription, respectively. Predicate Circumscription works minimizing the extent of some relation in the problem description. A variant called Parallel Circumscription works minimizing a tuple of relations at the same time. In a model of a circumscribed theory, the circumscribed relations are intended to have extents as minimal as possible and satisfying the theory. Such models are called minimal models.

Minimal models were used in the 1980s to provide semantics for McCarthy's Circumscription McCarthy (1980, 1986). In the 1980s and mid 1990s, the mathematics of minimal models was widely studied in the scope of Circumscription and its extensions (see Lifschitz (1994)). In 1995, Lifschitz extended McCarthy's Circumscription to Nested Abnormality Theories (NATs) Lifschitz (1995). In NATs, circumscriptions can be grouped into blocks and circumscribed again. Recent work has been done on the computational complexity of satisfiability and validity of propositional versions of NATs Cadoli et al (2005). In Ferreira, Martins (2007), the logical expressiveness of NATs, as presented in Lifschitz (1995), was studied and it was proved that the expressive power of of NATs is equivalent to the expressive power of second-order logic, modulo extra relations.

Minimal models are also related with fixed-points. In van Benthem (2005), van Benthem introduced the MIN(FO) logic that allows one to define the minimal relation which satisfies certain syntactically defined sort of formulas: the PIA-Conditions. These minimal relations are the extent of P in the P-minimal models (see Section 2 for the definition of P-minimal model) of the corresponding PIA-Condition, for a syntactically determined relation symbol P in the PIA-Condition. van Benthem (2005) showed that MIN(FO) is equivalent to the Least Fixed Point Logic—LFP (see Dawar, Gurevich (2002) for results on LFP).

In this paper, we will examine expressiveness and definability properties of logics with respect to minimal models, in particular, Circumscription. In Section 2, we will introduce the basic concepts of Minimal Model Theory and Circumscription. In Section 3, we will investigate the expressive power of Circumscription. First, we will give a proof that the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem does not hold for Circumscription. After that, we will prove a theorem relating classes of minimal models and Δ-elementary classes (see Definition 3.6). We will show that, if the class of ;-minimal models of a first-order sentence is Δ-elementary, then it is elementary. That is, whenever a circumscribed theory is equivalent to a first-order theory, then it is equivalent to a finitely axiomatizable one. It follows that classes of minimal models of first-order sentences either are elementary or are not even Δ-elementary. In Section 4, we investigate definability on Circumscription. We will introduce the main concepts of the Theory of Definitions and address a statement made in Doyle (1985) regarding definitions and Circumscription. We will also state and prove a theorem which can be taken as an alternative approach to some problems faced in Doyle (1985). We will show that, whenever the circumscription of a tuple of relations in a finite first-order theory Φ, implicitly defines some circumscribed relation Pi and such circumscription is equivalent to a (possibly countable) first-order theory Γ, then there is a specific explicit definition ψ for Pi in Γ which, together with the initial theory Φ, is equivalent to the theory Γ. We will use the result of Section 3 to show that the theory Γ is finitely axiomatizable. In Section 5, we will draw some conclusions about all we have done in the previous sections.

The basic logic notation used throughout this text follows that in Ebbinghaus et al (1994). For instance, a symbol set S is a set of relation, function and constant symbols. An S-structure is a pair = (A, σ), where A is a set and σ is a map which associates an n-ary relation σ(P) = An to each n-ary relation symbol PS, an n-ary function σ(f) = : An → to each n-ary function symbol fS and an element σ(c) = A to each constant symbol c S. (We use "relation" instead of "relation symbol" when the meaning is clear from the context.) The satisfiability relation ╞ is defined as usually, for instance as in Ebbinghaus et al (1994), for both first-order and second-order sentences. We use Fraktur capital letters, such as , , , ..., to denote structures and the corresponding Roman capital letters A, B, C, ... for their domains. We call ModS ( Γ) the class of S-structures which satisfy (are models of) the S-sentences in the set Γ of S-sentences. Given a class of S-structures , we call () the set of first-order S-sentences satisfied by every S-structure in .

In the next section, we will introduce the main concepts of Minimal Model Theory and Circumscription that will be used in Sections 3 and 4.

2. MINIMAL MODELS AND CIRCUMSCRIPTION

By minimal models we mean those defined over the following relation.

Definition 2.1 [

] Let S ∪{,} be a symbol set such that = P1, ..., Pm and = Z1,...,Zv are tuples of relation symbols. Let and be two structures on the symbol set S ∪{,} (in other words, two S ∪{,}-structures) with the same domain A. We say that and agree on the interpretation of all symbols in S iff, for each s S, we have

We define the relation between structures on the same symbol set S ∪{,} which agree on S and with varied as:

When the tuple has length 0 ( = ), we write for .

It is easy to see that is a preorder, that is, it is reflexive and transitive. Hereafter, we consider = P1, ..., Pm and a tuple of variable whose length is equal to the arity of Pi, 1 < i < m, = Z1, ..., Zv and yj is a tuple of variables whose length is equal to the arity of Zj, 1 < j < v. We also consider S, {} and {} as pairwise disjoint and S' = S ∪{} ∪{}, if not otherwise stated. Also note that we use a semi-colon between the tuple of relations and the tuple of varied relations instead of a comma, which is used between symbols in a tuple or list. If is empty, then the relation is a partial order, that is, an antisymmetric preorder. An example of this case occurs when S' = {}, which means that all relation symbols in the symbol set are minimized.

Definition 2.2 [;-Minimal Models of ] Let be a class of S ∪{,}-structures. A structure is a ;-minimal model of iff is minimal with respect to the restriction of to , that is, there is no such that

When has length 0, we say that is a -minimal model instead of ;-minimal model. Given an S'-sentence Φ, we say that a model is a ;-minimal model of Φ if it is a ;-minimal model of ModS'( Φ).

Definition 2.3 [Minimal Consequence ] Given two sentences Φ and ψ, we say that Φ ;-minimally entails ψ, in symbols Φ ψ, iff each ;-minimal model of Φ is a model of ψ.

McCarthy's Circumscription captures the Closed World Assumption Reiter (1978) by means of minimal models. In McCarthy (1980), McCarthy introduced Circumscription as a first-order formula schema. Let T(,) be a first-order sentence on the symbol set S ∪{,}, where = P1, ..., Pm and : = Z1,...,Zv are tuples of relation symbols. The circumscription schema for in T(,) with varied is the following expression:

where = Φ1, ..., Φm is a tuple of metavariables standing for any S ∪{,}-formulas = Φ1(), ..., Φm() with free variables in , respectively, and such that the length of is equal to the arity of Pi, and is a tuple of metavariables standing for any tuple of S ∪{,}-formulas : = δ1(),..., δv() such that the length of is equal to the arity of Zi. An instance of (1) is obtained by replacing every occurrence of Pi() with Φi(), for any tuple = t1,...,tn of terms in the language, and every occurrence of Zi() with δi(), for any tuple of terms in the language, with the appropriate substitutions of bound variables in the formulas Φ1(), ..., Φm(), δ1(), ..., δv() to avoid undesired biding of the variables in . Such an instance says that, if the relations defined by Φ1(), ..., Φm(), δ1(), ..., δv() satisfy the sentence T(,) and the relation Pi contains the relation defined by Φi(), for each 1 < i < m, then the relation defined by Φi() also contains the relation Pi for 1 < i < m. Hence, the schema (1) says that, every definable relation that satisfies T and is contained in Pi, also contains Pi, with varying among definable relations. We define first-order circumscription as follows.

Definition 2.3 [First-Order Circumscription]Given a sentence T(,), we define the first-order circumscription of in T(,) with varied as the set of sentences

CircFO[T(, ); ; ] := {T(, )} ∪{ θ| θ is an instance of (1)}.

We write CircFO[T(,);] for CircFO[T(,);;].

Any ;-minimal model of T(,) is a model of CircFO[T(, );;]. However, it can be proved that, for some S ∪{,}-sentence T(;), not every model of CircFO[T(;);;] is a ;-minimal model in the sense of Definition 2.2. For instance, consider the sentence

T(P) := ∀xy(E(x,y) → P(x,y)) ∧∀xyz(P(x,y) ∧E(y,z) → P(x,z)).

The first conjunct says that the relation P contains the relation E and second conjunct says that P is closed with respect to E. In other words, P contains the transitive closure of E. It is easy to see that in any P-minimal model of T(P), is exactly the transitive closure of . However, there is no first-order theory which axiomatizes the class class of structures = (A, , ) where is the transitive closure of .

In McCarthy (1986), McCarthy reformulated his Circumscription and captured precisely the minimal models semantics with respect to the relation of Definition 2.1. McCarthy presented Circumscription as a second-order formula.

Definition 2.5 [Second-Order Circumscription]Given a first-order sentence T(,), the second-order circumscription of the relations = P1, ..., Pm in T(,) with varied , represented by CircSO[T(,);;], is defined as the following second-order formula:

where

and := ∧1 < i < m(Xi() → Pi()) and = : = . If there is no varied relation ( = ), we write CircSO[T(,);] instead of CircSO[T(,);; ].

A proof of the following statement can be found in Lifschitz (1994):

Theorem 2.6 The ;-minimal models of T(;) are exactly the models of

CircSO[T(; ); ; ].

It is easy to see from Theorem 2.6 above that CircSO[T(;);; ] ╞ Φ iff T(,) Φ. In the next section, we will give a characterization of the classes of ;-minimal models of first-order sentences. This result will be used in the Section 4.

3. TWO EXPRESSIVENESS THEOREMS

The expressive power of a logic is its capability to express classes of structures or to distinguish between classes of structures. Our aim in this section is to give a characterization of the expressive power of second-order Circumscription. This is achieved by Theorems 3.5 and 3.7 and Corollary 3.8 below. As we will see, the definability results in the next section will appear as applications of the results obtained in this section.

In Schlipf(1987), Schlipf studied decidability questions regarding Circumscription such as to decide whether a first-order formula has a countable minimal model or not. Among other things, Schlipf showed that some formulas which have minimal models do not have countable minimal models Example 2.6 in Schlipf(1987). It means that an analogue to the Downward Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem does not hold for second-order Circumscription.

Theorem 3.1 [Schlipf]There is a first-order formula Φ which has only uncountable minimal models.

This fact is particularly important in our characterization of the expressive power of first- and second-order Circumscription. In order to keep this paper self-contained, we will give a proof, different from that of Schlipf, of the failure of the Downward Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for Circumscription. Schlipf's proof is based on the existence of ω1-like models of Peano Arithmetic. These ω1-like models are models of cardinality ℵ1, but each element in these models has only countable many predecessor (see Schlipf(1987), p.177). Then, Schlipf uses second-order Circumscription in order to avoid countable models.

Our proof is based on another set-theoretical fact, namely that continuous dense linear orderings are uncountable. A dense, linear ordering < of a set A is continuous iff any subset A'A which has a upper bound in A with respect to < , also has a least upper bound with respect to < . We use just two relation symbols. Let < be a binary relation symbol and P a unary relation symbol. Let LO(<) be a first-order sentence saying that < is a strict, dense, linear order without the least element:

and consider the following formulas:

D(P) says that, if there is an upper bound for the elements in P, then there is a least one. We call D(P) the Dedekind property for P. DC(P) says that P is downward closed, that is, if an element x belongs to P, then any other element less than x with respect to < also belongs to P. The intuitive meaning of the other formulas is obvious.

Let

It is easy to see, using Definition 2.5, that

Intuitively, CircSO[T(P);P] says that any downward closed, proper subset P' of P has the Dedekind property, that is, any downward closed proper subset of P which has an upper bound also has a least upper bound. However, by T(P), P itself does not have the Dedekind property.

Lemma 3.2CircSO[T(P);P] is satisfiable.

Proof. Let be the structure of the real numbers with order and be an isomorphic copy of the structure of the rational numbers with order disjoint from (that is, RQ = ). Let ' = (B', ) be the disjoint union of and , that is

Now, let = (B, ) be obtained from ' by defining

That is, any element in R is less than each element in Q with respect to . If we imagine a graphical representation of the ordering where the increasing order is from left to right, the real numbers appears as a continuous ordering on the left and the rationals as a dense ordering on the right. Now, let

= (,)

with = R. It is not too much difficult to check that is a model for CircSO[T(P);P].

We will need the following well known result of Set Theory and the Theory of Order Hrbacek, Jech (1999) in order to prove Theorem 3.5. Recall that a linear order without end-points is an order without the least or the greatest elements.

Theorem 3.3 Any two countable, dense, linearly ordered sets without end-points are order-isomorphic.

The following lemma will lead to the failure of the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for Circumscription.

Lemma 3.4Any model of CircSO[T(P);P] is uncountable.

Proof. In any model = (A , ,) of CircSO[T(P);P], is a dense linear ordering of the domain A, and is a nonempty, downward closed subset of A. As A does not have a least element with respect to (see LO(<)), has infinitely many elements. Since ƪD(P), it follows that does not have a greatest element. Let be any proper subset of with an upper bound in and

= {aA | exists b such that a b or a = b}.

is a downward closed, proper subset of . Moreover, any upper bound for is an upper bound for and vice-versa. Thus and have the same least upper bound, if any. As CircSO[T(P);P] and

, it follows that has a least upper bound in A. But, by definition, , and therefore , has an upper bound in . As is downward closed, the least upper bound of belongs to . Therefore, has a least upper bound in .

We get that any proper subset of with an upper bound in has a least upper bound in . It follows that the substructure = (C, ) obtained by defining C = and as the restriction of to , that is,

= ∩ ( ×),

is a continuous, dense linearly ordered set without endpoints. Suppose, by reduction to the absurd, that is countable. It follows, by Theorem 3.3, that is order-isomorphic to the structure of the rationals with order = (Q, ). But is continuous and is not, which contradicts the fact that and are order-isomorphic. It follows that C = is uncountable and so is .

We immediately get:

Theorem 3.5 The Downward Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for second-order Circumscription does not hold.

We follow our investigation about the expressive power of Circumscription and we will show our second result of this section. We remember the definition of elementary and Δ-elementary classes of models below (see, for instance, Ebbinghaus et al (1994)).

Definition 3.6 [Elementary and Δ-Elementary Classes] Let S be a symbol set anda class of S-structures.is said to be Δ-elementary iff there is a set T of S-sentences such that ModS(T) = . is said to be elementary if there is a single S-sentence Φ such that ModS( Φ) = .

From Theorem 3.5 it follows that there are some classes of minimal models of finite first-order theories which are not Δ-elementary. An example is the sentence T(P) in (3). For suppose that there is a set of first-order sentences Γ whose models are exactly the same models of CircSO[T(P);P]. Since the models of CircSO[T(P);P] are structures in the symbol set {< , P}, Γ is a set of {< , P}-sentences. As first-order sentences are finite, Γ is countable. And since the Downward Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem does hold for first-order logic, Γ has a countable or finite model, which contradicts Theorem 3.5.

Below, we will prove the main theorem of this section. We will show that there is no strictly Δ-elementary class of ;-minimal models of first-order sentences, that is, Δ-elementary but not elementary. This will follow directly from the next theorem.

Theorem 3.7Let Φ(;) be an S' = S ∪{,}-sentence such that the class of ;-minimal models of Φ is Δ-elementary. Then is elementary.

Proof. In this proof, we will first define a first-order sentence and, after that, we will show that the models of ∧ Φ(,) are exactly the ;-minimal models of Φ(,). Let

be the first-order S'-theory of , that is, the set of all first-order sentences satisfied by all models in . As is Δ-elementary, then

ModS'(Ψ) = .

Let be new relation symbols, not occurring in Φ(,), with the same arity of the predicate symbols ,, respectively. Let Φ() be the result of replacing , with [ (P')],[ (Z')] in Φ(,). Consider the set

Ψ ∪{ Φ()}

of sentences. As neither some of occurs in Φ(,), nor some of , occurs in Φ(), for each S ∪{,} ∪ {}-structure

we have that

Consider the set

of sentences. Since the models of Ψ are ;-minimal, by (5) the set of sentences (6) is inconsistent. Let Θ' be a finite subset of Ψ ∪{ Φ()} such that, is inconsistent, and let Θ: = Θ' - Φ(). As first-order logic is compact, such sets always exist. Let

:= ∧ Θ

be a first-order sentence obtained by the conjunction of all (finitely many) sentences in Θ. By definition, any ;-minimal model of Φ(,) is a model of Φ(,) ∧ . Let (,) be a model of Φ(,) ∧ . Suppose (,) is not a ;-minimal model of Φ(,). In this case, there is a model (,) of Φ(,), such that (,) (,) and P'i

Pi for some i, 1 < i < m. It follows that

which contradicts the fact that is inconsistent. Therefore, an S ∪ {,}-structure is a ;-minimal model of Φ(,) iff it is a model of Φ(,) ∧. That is, ModS'( Φ(,) ∧) is exactly the class of models . Hence, the class of ;-minimal models of Φ(,) is elementary.

Corollary 3.8 Let Φ(;) be an S' = S ∪{,}-sentence such that

ModS'(CircSO[ Φ(; ); ; ])

is Δ-elementary. Then ModS'(CircSO[ Φ(;);;]) is elementary.

Theorem 3.5 shows that there are classes of minimal models of first-order sentences which are not Δ-elementary. Moreover, Theorem 3.7 shows that, if the class of minimal models of a first-order sentence is Δ-elementary, then it is in fact elementary. The proof of the following corollary is immediate.

Corollary 3.9 The class of ;-minimal models of a first-order formula is either elementary or it is not Δ-elementary.

A particularly important consequence of Theorem 3.7 is:

Corollary 3.10 If a second-order circumscription is equivalent to a first-order theory, then the set of its conclusions is recursively enumerable.

In the following section, we will examine definability questions regarding first- and second-order Circumscription. We will begin with an explanation of the basic concepts of the Theory of Definitions. After that, we will give a detailed analysis of definability questions motivated by Doyle's work in Doyle (1985). We will apply the expressiveness results of this section to obtain the main results of Section 4.

4. DEFINABILITY AND CIRCUMSCRIPTION

In Padoa (1900), Padoa argue that, in order to show that an expression like

where the relation symbol P does not occur in ψ(), cannot be proved from a theory, say, Γ, it is sufficient to show that there are two models of Γ which differ on the interpretation of P, but agree on the interpretation of the other symbols. An expression like (7) is called an explicit definition. When an S ∪{P}-theory Γ is such that for each two S ∪{P}-models (,P) and (,P') of Γ we always have P = P', we say that Γ implicitly defines P.

The so called Padoa's Method consists of showing that an explicit definition for P such as ∀(P() ↔ ψ()) cannot be a logical consequence of a set of first-order sentences, say Γ, by showing that Γ does not implicitly defines P. This is equivalent to state that, if there is an explicit definition for P in Γ, then Γ implicitly defines P. In Beth (1953), Beth shows the converse. The Beth's Definability Theorem states that, if a set of first-order sentences Γ implicitly defines P in first-order logic, then there is an explicit definition, say ∀(P() ↔ ψ()) in first-order logic for P such that

Γ ╞∀(P() ↔ ψ()).

In Doyle (1985), Doyle investigated some relations between Circumscription and implicit definability in the context of first-order Circumscription. Doyle addressed the question on what are the circumstances in which first-order Circumscription implicitly defines the circumscribed relation. It is intuitive that such circumstances must involve the existence of exactly one minimal interpretation for the circumscribed relation in the domain of a structure, that is, given a symbol set S' = S ∪{P,} and a sentence Φ(P,), for each S-structure , there is at most one A such that = (, , ) is a P;-minimal model of Φ(P,) for some (possibly many) . This semantic condition, stated in another, equivalent form, was called the unique minimal model property by Moinard and Rolland in Moinard, Rolland (1991), who also introduced a variant of the standard Circumscription called Strong Circumscription Moinard, Rolland (1991) and gave some sufficient conditions for the equivalence between standard and Strong Circumscription. Here, we consider another, different point addressed by Doyle in Doyle (1985) relating Circumscription with Definability Theory, which we explain below.

Suppose CircFO[ Φ;P;] implicitly defines P. By Beth's Definability Theorem, there is an explicit definition ∀(P() ↔ ψ()) for P. In Doyle (1985), Doyle states that it is not always the case that the circumscription CircFO[ Φ;P;] of P in Φ can be replaced with Φ plus its explicit definition ∀(P() ↔ ψ()). In other words, it may be the case that, for some Φ,

That is, an explicit definition for the implicitly defined relation P cannot replace the (infinitely many) sentences in CircFO[ Φ;P;]. However, Doyle's example fails to show this. Doyle considered the sentence Φ(Block) of block's world:

Φ(Block) := Block(t1) ∧ ... ∧ Block(tl).

It is clear that for any model of Φ(Block), must be included in , where is the interpretation of the relation symbol Block by . It follows that the Block-minimal models of Φ(Block) are those in which

For each Block-minimal model of Φ(Block), we have that

╞∀x(Block(x) ↔ (x = t1 ∨ ... ∨ x = tl)),

and for ψ(x) := (x = t1 ∨ ... ∨ x = tl), the instance

Φ( ψ()) ∧∀x( ψ(x) → Block(x)) →∀x(Block(x) → ψ(x)

of the circumscription schema for Block in Φ(Block)—see the schema (1)—belongs to CircFO[ Φ(Block);Block]. This means that the Block-minimal models of Φ(Block) are exactly the models of CircFO[ Φ(Block);Block]. It can be easily seen that

CircFO[ Φ(Block);Block] ≡ Φ(Block) ∧∀x(Block(x) ↔ ψ(x)),

contrary to what was expected by Doyle in Doyle (1985, p. 397), where he supposed to be necessary additional axioms to guarantee minimality.

In the following, we will carefully investigate this question for both first- and second-order Circumscription.

There is a wide class of sentences for which (8) fails. First, let us precisely state the concept of well-foundedness for sentences in the context of minimal models.

Definition 4.1 [Well-Founded Sentences]We say that a sentence Φ(,) is ;-well-founded iff for each model of Φ(,) there is a ;-minimal model of Φ(,) such that

. If = we write -well-founded for ;-well-founded.

For -well-founded sentences in circumscriptions without varied relations, (8) does not hold.

Theorem 4.2 Let the S'-sentence Φ(P) be a P-well-founded sentence and the class of P-minimal models of Φ(P). Suppose that is P-defined and that ∀(P() ↔ ψ()) is a first-order explicit definition for P in , which means that Φ(,) (P() ↔ ψ()). Then

= ModS'( Φ(P) ∧∀(P() ↔ ψ()).

Proof. By the hypothesis of the theorem,

Suppose by contradiction that there is a model

ModS'( Φ(P) ∧∀(P() ↔ ψ())

which is not a P-minimal model of Φ(P). As Φ(P) is P-well-founded, there is a P-minimal model of Φ(P) such that < P. By (9),

╞∀(P() ↔ ψ()).

But since

< P, and agree on the interpretation of the symbols in S' - {P}. Since and are models of ∀(P() ↔ ψ()), it follows that and agree on P and, hence, = . Thus

ModS'( Φ(P) ∧∀(P() ↔ ψ()) ⊆ .

Corollary 4.3 Let Φ(P) be a P-well-founded sentence.

1. If CircFO[ Φ(P);P] implicitly defines P and(P() ↔ ψ()) is a first-order explicit definition for P in CircFO[ Φ(P);P], then

CircFO[ Φ(P);P] ≡ Φ(P) ∧∀(P() ↔ ψ()).

2. If CircSO[ Φ(P);P] implicitly defines P, ∀(P() ↔ ψ()) is a first-order explicit definition for P in CircSO[ Φ(P);P], then

CircSO[ Φ(P);P] ≡ Φ(P) ∧∀(P() ↔ ψ()).

Proof. The proof of 2 follows directly from Theorem 4.2. The proof of 1 is analogous, since any P-minimal model of Φ(P) is a model of CircFO[ Φ(P);P].

Although Doyle's example does not satisfy the statement (8), there are sentences Φ for which that statement is true. Indeed, there are well-founded sentences which satisfy the statement (8) for circumscription with varied predicates. We show this in the following example, where we use second-order Circumscription since, in this case, it is equivalent to first-order Circumscription.

Example 4.4 Let P and Z be unary relations. Consider the sentence

Φ(P,Z) := ∀xP(x) → Z(x)).

For each model of Φ(P,Z), there is a P;Z-minimal model ' such that ' < P;Z , namely with = , = B and for the other symbols s in the symbol set. Hence, Φ(P,Z) is P;Z-well-founded. Moreover, any P;Z-minimal model of Φ(P,Z) interprets P as the empty relation. Consider the explicit definition x(P(x) ↔¬Z(x)) for P. It is clear that

CircSO[ Φ(P,Z);P;Z] ╞∀x(P(x) ↔¬Z(x)),

but

CircSO[ Φ(P,Z);P;Z] Φ(P,Z) ∧∀x(P(x) ↔¬Z(x)).

Based on the proof of Theorem 4.2, we can give a restricted version of this theorem for well-founded sentences in parallel circumscriptions with varied relations.

Theorem 4.5 Let the S'-sentence Φ(,) be a ;-well-founded sentence and the class of ;-minimal models of Φ(,). Suppose that is Pi-defined and that ∀(Pi() ↔ ψi()) is a first-order explicit definition for Pi in , for each Pi, that is, Φ(,) (Pi() ↔ ψi()), and such that no symbol in {,} occurs in ψi, for each Pi. Then

Proof. Analogous to the proof of Theorem 4.2.

Corollary 4.6 Let Φ(,) be a ;-well-founded sentence.

1. If CircFO[ Φ(,);;] implicitly defines Pi and(Pi() ↔ ψi()) is a first-order explicit definition for Pi in CircFO[ Φ(,); ;] such that no symbol in ,occurs in ψi(), for each Pi, then

2. If CircSO[ Φ(,);;] implicitly defines Pi, ∀(Pi() ↔ ψ()) is a first-order explicit definition for Pi in CircSO[ Φ(,); ;] such that no symbol in ,occurs in ψi(), for each Pi, then

Proof. Analogous to the proof of Corollary 4.3.

The restriction on the occurrence of varied relations in the explicit definition used in Corollary 4.6 does not work for non-well-founded sentences, since there are non-well-founded sentences for which (8) does hold even under this restriction. Again, in the following example, first- and second-order Circumscription coincide.

Example 4.7 Suppose < be a linear order relation. Let

LE(x) := ∀y(x < y x = y) and

GE(x) := ∀y(y < x y = x)

be first-order formulas saying that x is the least (LE) and the greatest (GE) element of < , respectively, and

S(x,y) := x < y ∧∀z(x < zy < zz = y)

be a first-order formula saying that y is the successor of x with respect to < . Let α(<) be a first-order sentence which says that < is a linear order (a total, transitive and asymmetric binary relation) in which each element, except the greatest, has a successor and each element, except the least, has a predecessor, although α(<) does not determine whether there are such least and greatest elements or not:

Let c be a constant symbol in the underlying symbol set S'. Let β(c) be a first-order formula expressing that, if < has a least element, then c is such least element:

β(c) := ∃x(LE(x)) → LE(c).

Let P be a relation symbol in S'. Let γ(P) be a first-order sentence saying that P is not empty, P has a greatest element with respect to < and P is downward closed, that is, if a belongs to P and b < a, then b belongs to P:

γ(P) := NE(P) ∧∃x(P(x) ∧ (∀y(P(y) → y < xy = x))) ∧ DC(P).

It is clear that < has a least element in any P-minimal model (,P) of

α(<) ∧β(c) ∧γ(P),

otherwise any downward closed proper subsetP' ofPcould be used to construct a model (,P') <P (,P). Conversely, if < has a least element, then α(<) ∧β(c) ∧γ(P) has a P-minimal model in which = {c}. We can see that CircSO[α(<) ∧β(c) ∧γ(P);P] is equivalent to the set Γ of first-order formulas defined as

Γ := {α(<) ∧β(c) ∧γ(P), ∀x(P(x) → LE(x))}.

It can easily be seen that the formulax(P(x) ↔ (x = cx < c)) is an explicit definition for P in Γ, that is

Γ ╞∀x(P(x) ↔ (x = cx < c)).

However, as α(<) ∧β(c) ∧γ(P) has models (not minimal) in which < does not have a least element, we have that

CircSO[α(<) ∧β(c) ∧γ(P);P]

α(<) ∧β(c) ∧γ(P) ∧∀x(P(x) ↔ (x = cx < c)).

So, if, in (8), Φ is the sentence α(<) ∧β(c) ∧γ(P) and ψ is LE(x), then (8) is verified.

It is important to stress the fact that, for a relation implicitly defined in a theory, there are many distinct explicit definitions. If we consider the explicit definition ∀x(P(x) ↔ (x = c)) for P and Γ as in Example 4.7, we have

Γ ╞∀x(P(x) ↔ (x = c)),

and

CircSO[α(<) ∧β(c) ∧γ(P);P] ≡α(<) ∧β(c) ∧γ(P) ∧∀x(P(x) ↔ (x = c)).

That is, if ψ is (x = c) in (8), that statement is not verified.

Note that the problem in Example 4.7 occurs in the cases in which < does not have a least element. In such cases, there is no interpretation for P which gives a minimal model for α(<) ∧β(c) ∧γ(P). It follows that α(<) ∧β(c) ∧γ(P) is not P-well-founded, falling outside the scope of Corollary 4.3 or Corollary 4.6.

In the face of these facts, we can ask: in the cases in which

CircSO[ Φ;P;] implicitly defines P and ModS'(CircSO)[ Φ;P;]) is Δ-elementary, is there an explicit definition ∀(P() ↔ ψ()) for which

holds? We will give a positive answer to this question below.

Theorem 4.8 Let be the class of ;-minimal models of the S'-sentence Φ(,) and such that is Δ-elementary and Pi-defined for some i, 1< i < m. Then there is an explicit definition (Pi() ↔ ψ()) such that

= ModS'( Φ(, ) ∧∀(Pi() ↔ ψ())).

Proof. Let Φ(,) be an S' = S ∪{,} sentence of first-order logic, Pi be an n-ary relation symbol and and tuples of relation symbols. By Theorem 3.7, there is a sentence γ(,) = ∧ Φ(,) such that

= ModS'(γ(, )).

As is Pi-defined, by Beth's Theorem there is an explicit definition ∀(Pi() ↔ ψ()) for which

Let γ': = γ( ψ,) be the S' - {Pi}-sentence obtained from γ(,) by replacing each atom Pi() with ψ() in γ(,), with the appropriated renaming of the bound variable of ψ() in order to avoid undesirable binding of the variables in . Let the S' - {Pi}-structure be a model of γ' and PiAn defined as Pi := {An|╞ ψ()[]}. Then, by (11), (,Pi) ╞γ(,). On the other hand, again by (11), if (,Pi) ╞γ(,) then ╞γ' and Pi := {An|╞ ψ()[]}. It follows that

Let ψ'(): = γ' ∧ ψ(). Let (,Pi) be a model of γ(,), where is an S'-{Pi}-structure. Since γ(,) = ∧ Φ, we have that

By (11), it follows that (,Pi) ╞∀(Pi() ↔ ψ()). Let An be a tuple of elements in A. We have that

and, by (12),

From (14) and (15), we get

By (13) and (16),we have

As (17) holds for any model (,Pi) of γ(,), it follows that

Now, let (,Pi) be a model of Φ(,) ∧∀(Pi() ↔ ψ'()). If Pi = ∅, then (,Pi) is a ;-minimal model of Φ(,). If Pi, then there is in An such that (,Pi) ╞ Pi()[]. But, as (,Pi) ╞∀(Pi() ↔ ψ'()), then (,Pi) ╞ ψ'()[] and hence (,Pi) ╞γ' ∧ ψ()[]. Therefore (,Pi) ╞γ', and, as Pi does not occur in γ',

Since (,Pi) ╞∀(Pi() ↔ ψ'()), we have that Pi = {An|╞ ψ'()[]}. But as ╞γ', it follows that

From (12), (19) and (20), we have

and hence

By (18) and (21) we have = ModS'(γ(,)) = ModS'( Φ(,) ∧∀(Pi() ↔ ψ'())).

From the proof of the Theorem 4.8 above, we have the following:

Corollary 4.9 Let be the class of ;-minimal models of the S'-sentence Φ(,) and such that is Δ-elementary and there is J ⊆ {1, ..., m} such that is Pi-defined for all i ∈ J. Then there are explicit definitions (Pi() ↔ ψi()), i ∈ J, such that = ModS'( Φ(,) ∧ ∧i J(Pi() ↔ ψi())).

Corollary 4.10 If CircSO[ Φ(,);;] implicitly defines Pi, iJ for some J ∈ {1, ..., m} and ModS'(CircSO[ Φ(,);;]) is Δ-elementary, then there are explicit definitions(Pi() ↔ ψ()) such that

5. CONCLUSIONS

We investigated expressiveness and definability results that concerns Circumscription. We dealt with both first- and second-order Circumscription. Within first-order Circumscription, the result of circumscribing a relation P with varied is a set of first-order sentences, namely the set of all first-order instances of the circumscription schema (1), see Section 3. Second-order Circumscription results in a second-order sentence whose models are just the minimal models of the circumscribed sentence. In Section 3, Theorem 3.5, we gave a proof that second-order Circumscription does not have the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem. We showed that second-order Circumscription can express a class of structures which has a dense, continuous, linearly-ordered set without end-points as a substructure. Thus, any model in such class is uncountable. In Theorem 3.7 we showed that, whenever the class of minimal models of a first-order sentence is Δ-elementary, such class is actually elementary. That is, whenever a second-order circumscription is equivalent to a first-order theory, this theory is finitely axiomatizable. As stressed by Corollary 3.8, Theorem 3.5 and Theorem 3.7 divide the classes of minimal models of first-order sentences in elementary and non- Δ-elementary. In a picture, we have:

A straightforward but important consequence is that, when the class of minimal models of a first-order sentence is Δ-elementary, the set of logical consequences of the circumscribed theory is recursively enumerable, as pointed out in Corollary 3.10.

We also investigated definability questions regarding Circumscription. In Moinard, Rolland (1991), Moinard and Rolland dealt with a problem raised by Doyle in Doyle (1985) about the conditions on which Circumscription defines the circumscribed relation. We dealt with another, although related, problem here. We are concerned with a statement made by Doyle also in Doyle (1985). Doyle stated that, in the cases in which a first-order circumscription implicitly defines the circumscribed relation, such circumscription cannot always be replaced by the initial sentence together with an explicit definition for the circumscribed relation. He also argued that, in some cases, extra axioms should be added in order to guarantee minimality Doyle (1985, p. 397). Unfortunately, Doyle's example fails in showing this (see Section 4 above). Indeed, although Doyle's example does not work, he was right about the fact that the circumscription of a relation cannot always be replaced by the initial theory and an explicit definition for the circumscribed relation. Examples 4.4 and 4.7 in Section 4 confirm his statement. However, there is a wide class of first-order sentences for which his statement does not hold, namely the P-well-founded sentences, as showed by Theorem 4.2. We called attention to the fact that an implicitly defined symbol can have many different explicit definitions. We then asked about the existence of a suitable explicit definition ψ which yields the equivalence between the circumscription and the initial theory plus ψ. In Corollary 4.10, we showed that, whenever the first-order logic can express the minimality of a relation in a sentence with varied relations, if the circumscription of a relation implicitly defines the circumscribed relation, then there is an explicit definition for the circumscribed relation which give us the desired equivalence.

Doyle also argues that, in general, minimality statements require infinitely many axioms like the first-order circumscription schema Doyle (1985). But, as proved by Theorem 3.7 and Corollary 3.8, whenever first-order logic can express a second-order Circumscription, it can be made by a single sentence. Indeed, this result is in the core of the definability results showed in this paper.

  • BETH, E.W. "On Padoa's method in the theory of definitions". Indag- tiones Mathematicae, 15, 1953.
  • CADOLI, M., EITER, T. and GOTTLOB, G. "Complexity of propositional nested circumscription and nested abnormality theories". ACM Transactions on Computational Logic, 6(2), p.232-272, 2005.
  • DAWAR, A. and GUREVICH, Y. "Fixed-point logics". Bulletin of Sym- bolic Logic, 8(1), p. 65-88, 2002.
  • DOYLE, J. "Circumscription and Implicit Definability". Journal of Au- tomated Reasoning, 1(4), p. 391-405, 1985.
  • EBBINGHAUS, H.-D. and FLUM, J. Finite Model Theory Springer-Verlag, 1995.
  • EBBINGHAUS, H.-D., FLUM, J. and THOMAS, W. Mathe- matical Logic Springer-Verlag, New York, NY, 1994.
  • FLUM, J. "On the (infinite) model theory of fixed-point logics". In Caicedo and Montenegro, editors, Models, algebras and proofs, number 2003 in Lecture Notes in Pure and Applied Mathematics, p. 67-75. Marcel Dekker, 1999.
  • FERREIRA, F.M. and MARTINS, A.T. "On minimal models". Logic Journal of the IGPL, 15(5-6), p. 503-526, 2007.
  • HRBACEK, K. and JECH, T. Introduction to Set Theory Marcel Dekker, 1999.
  • HUME, D. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding 1748. Oxford University Press, 2007.
  • LIFSCHITZ, V. "Circumscription". In D. M. Gabbay, C. J. Hogger, and J. A. Robinson, editors, Handbook of Logic in Artificial Intelli- gence and Logic Programming-Nonmonotonic Reasoning and Uncer- tain Reasoning, V. 3, p. 297-352. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1994.
  • ______. "Nested abnormality theories". Intelli- Gence, 74(2): p. 351-365, 1995.
  • MCCARTHY, J. "Circumscription - a form of non-monotonic reason- Ing". Artificial Intelligence, 13(1-2), p. 27-39, 1980.
  • ______."Applications of circumscription to formalizing common-sense knowledge". Artificial Intelligence, 28(1), 1986.
  • MCDERMOTT, D. and DOYLE, J. "Non-monotonic logic I". Artificial Intelligence, 13(1-2), p. 41-72, 1980.
  • MOINARD, Y. and ROLLAND, R. "Circumscription and definability". In International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, p. 432-437, 1991.
  • PADOA, A. "Essai d'une théorie algébrique des nombres en tiers, precedé d'une introduction logique a une théorie deductive quel- conque". In Bibliothčque Du Congrčs International de Philosophie, volume 3, p. 118-123, 1900.
  • REITER, R. "On closed world data bases". In H. Gallaire and J. Minker, editors, Logic and Data Bases, p. 55-76, New York, 1978.
  • ______."A logic for default reasoning". Artificial Intelligence, 13(1-2), p.81-132, 1980.
  • SCHLIPF, J. "Decidability and definability with circumscription". An- nals of Pure and Applied Logic, 35(2): p.173-191, 1987.
  • van BENTHEM, J. "Minimal predicates, fixed-points, and definability". Journal of Symbolic Logic, 70(3): p. 696-712, 2005.
  • 1
    This author was partially supported by CNPq, FUNCAP, CAPES (DS, PROCAD 2010).
  • 2
    This author was partially supported by CNPq (PQ, Casadinho 2008, Universal 2010) and CAPES (PROCAD 2010).
  • Publication Dates

    • Publication in this collection
      31 July 2012
    • Date of issue
      June 2011
    UNICAMP - Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Centro de Lógica, Epistemologia e História da Ciência Rua Sérgio Buarque de Holanda, 251, 13083-859 Campinas-SP, Tel: (55 19) 3521 6523, Fax: (55 19) 3289 3269 - Campinas - SP - Brazil
    E-mail: publicacoes@cle.unicamp.br