Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Neural Dynamics of Seeing-In

  • Original Contribution
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Philosophers have suggested that, in order to understand the particular visual state we are in during picture perception, we should focus on experimental results from vision neuroscience—in particular, on the most rigorous account of the functioning of the visual system that we have from vision neuroscience, namely, the ‘Two Visual Systems Model’. According to the initial version of this model, our visual system can be dissociated, from an anatomo-functional point of view, into two streams: a ventral stream subserving visual recognition, and a dorsal stream subserving the visual guidance of action. Following this model, philosophers have suggested that, since the two streams have different functions, they represent different properties of a picture. However, the original view proposed by the ‘Two Visual Systems Model’ about the presence of a strong anatomo-functional dissociation between the two streams has recently been questioned on both philosophical and experimental grounds. Indeed, the analysis of several new pieces of evidence seems to suggest that many visual representations in our visual system, related to different tasks, are the result of a deep functional interaction between the streams. In the light of the renewed status of the ‘Two Visual Systems Model’, also our best philosophical model of picture perception should be renewed, in order to take into account a view of the process of picture perception informed by the new evidence about such interaction. Despite this, no account fulfilling this role has been offered yet. The aim of the present paper is precisely to offer such an account. It does this by suggesting that the peculiar visual state we are in during picture perception is subserved by interstream interaction. This proposal allows us to rely on a rigorous philosophical account of picture perception that is, however, also based on the most recent results from neuroscience. Unless the explanation offered in this paper is endorsed, all the recent evidence from vision neuroscience will remain unexplained under our best empirically informed philosophical theory of picture perception.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. If both streams represent both the surface and the depicted object and if, during seeing-in, the surface and the depicted object are represented by at least one chunk (not necessarily the same one) of our visual brain, then there might be four kinds of seeing-in: (1) dorsal vision represents the surface, whereas ventral vision represents the depicted object; (2) ventral vision represents both the surface and the depicted object (purely ventral, inflected seeing-in); (3) dorsal vision represents the depicted object, while ventral vision represents the surface; (4) dorsal vision represents both the surface and the depicted object (purely dorsal uninflected seeing-in). I do not explore this point here, as it is not relevant for my claim.

  2. The role of dorsal processing in the perception of depicted objects has been initially denied and only recently recognized. But such a role has been confirmed only concerning the action property attribution (§1). The role of dorsal processing in the recognition of shapes is still unexplored in the philosophical literature. For this reason, I will devote more space to this section than I have to the other sub-sections of (§3), in order to properly discuss the evidence concerning this perceptual fact.

  3. It has been suggested that the dorsal stream can be hodologically divided into two sub-cortical pathways: the ventro-dorsal stream and the dorso-dorsal stream (Chinellato and Del Pobil 2016; Gallese 2007; Borghi and Riggio 2015; Milner and Goodale 1995/2006). Here I mainly mention the evidence on the ventro-dorsal stream because it has several characteristics of the pragmatic processing of what was considered the dorsal stream, along with several computational aspects of ventral recognitional processing (Chinellato and Del Pobil 2016: 28; Ferretti 2016c: 187; Gallese 2007; Milner and Goodale 1995/2006: Sect. 8.2.3; Borghi and Riggio 2015). For the role of this sub-stream in picture perception see (Ferretti 2016a). Some have also suggested the presence of three sub-streams within the dorsal one (Kravitz et al. 2011; Haak and Beckmann 2018). I do not offer an analysis concerning this new subdivision here.

  4. Dorsal perception discriminates between images of depicted graspable and non-graspable objects (Rice et al. 2007; Ferretti 2016a, b) and it also performs object categorization, especially concerning manipulable objects (Helbig et al. 2010). To this extent, experiments performing continuous flash suppression on ventral vision, while leaving dorsal processing intact, suggested a facilitating influence on tools categorization, but not on the categorization of objects that are not manipulable (Almeida et al. 2008). It is not by chance that both streams can respond to both normal and depicted objects/tools (Konen and Kastner 2008; Sects. 3.2, 3.3, 4.1).

  5. However, the inferior temporal (IT) cortex remains the crucial area for object discrimination (Di Carlo et al. 2012). Its processing is computationally more accurate in object identification of two-dimensional shapes with respect to that of dorsal-related areas such as the lateral intraparietal cortex (LIP), arguably because the LIP is related to sensorimotor representations (Lehky and Sereno 2007: 316–317; Farivar 2009: 3.1; Chinellato and Del Pobil: 2.3.4). Indeed, dorsal processing is not sufficient for complete volumetric recognition (Westwood et al. 2002; Ferretti 2016a: 4.2, b: 5.6); see footnote 6. However, both streams are differently involved in the representation of depth, shape and volumetric recognition, and stereoscopic information of 2-D and 3-D structures (Chinellato and del Pobil 2016; Briscoe 2009; Theys et al. 2015; Ferretti 2016a, b, c; Farivar 2009).

  6. I am not considering here interstream interaction concerning colour and motion detection (Tchernikov and Fallah 2010; Perry and Fallah 2014). This is, however, another example of dorsal-ventral integration in object recognition.

  7. An important contribution for this task comes from the right inferior parietal lobule (Pammer et al. 2006: 2929). Moreover, dyslexia seems to be caused by an impairment of magnocellular pathways in the dorsal stream, in particular, of the area MT/V5. This evidence is important because we know that the inferior parietal lobule, related to the ventro-dorsal stream, which comprises the AIP, receives direct inputs from the MT/V5 visual pathway (Rizzolatti and Matelli 2003), which in turn receives inputs from V1 (Laycock et al. 2009; for the relation between dorsal vision and reading see also Levy et al. 2010).

  8. This is in line with the evidence that magno-cellular, dorsal-related responses arrive before parvo-cellular, ventral-related responses in the case of visual processing of different kinds of objects (Barrett and Bar 2009; Bar et al. 2006; Bullier 2001; Laycock et al. 2007; Milner and Goodale 1995/2006; Sect. 4.1).

  9. This is also in accordance with the evidence that vision for action and visual recognition are both subject to illusions in the same way (Kopiske et al. 2016; Briscoe 2009; Bruno 2001; Bruno and Franz 2009). I’ll get back to the issue of egocentric representations, pictorial illusions and dorsal-ventral interactions below in (Sects. 3.4, 4.1, 4.2).

  10. I will offer more technical details on this point in (Sect. 4), where I will also explain the difference between this case and that of the visual recognition of real objects, like surfaces, as really offering action possibilities.

  11. For the role of semantic information in motor processing see (Ferretti 2016b: 5.3; Zipoli Caiani and Ferretti 2016). Note that, on the other hand, motor processing can affect object recognition (Kiefer et al. 2011; Helbig et al. 2006, 2010).

  12. Nanay suggested that on the one hand, “there seems to be plenty of evidence for the claim that the malfunctioning of the ventral stream leads to a breakdown in picture perception. Patients with visual agnosia, as we have seen in the case of D.M., are extremely bad at picture perception (see Turnbull et al. 2004; Westwood et al. 2002)” (p. 474). On the other hand, dorsal processing is important for picture perception, as shown by experimental results in which “A patient presenting symptoms of optic ataxia, A.T., who sustained a bilateral parieto-occipital infarct during eclampsia did perceive pictures, but her “evaluation of line length and size of drawn figures was poor” (Jeannerod et al. 1994, p. 370; see also Jeannerod 1997, p. 62). As Nanay suggests concerning this passage, “What we have in this case is a malfunctioning of picture perception as a result of a malfunctioning of the dorsal stream. The malfunctioning of the dorsal stream does not result in the complete breakdown of picture perception (like the malfunctioning of the ventral stream does), but it does lead to misestimating the distances and size of the depicted scenes” (Nanay 2011: 475). Now, we know that dorsal representations respond to depicted objects apparently presented in the peripersonal space of the observer and whose vehicle is also actually located in peripersonal space (Ferretti 2016b). The right posterior parietal lobe, related to the dorsal stream, is crucial in the recognition of the spatial orientation of objects. Lesions to this area disrupt this ability, leading to orientation agnosia (Martinaud et al. 2014; Priftis et al. 2003). But I also suggested that the dorsal stream is also crucial in object recognition (§3.1). This is in line with the fact that “evaluation of line length and size of drawn figures was poor”, as it seems to be a problem in shape recognition. Furthermore, note that several studies have shown that optic ataxia and visual agnosia are much more complex impairments than previously thought, concerning action and object processing, so that one cannot simply reduce each impairment either to space perception or to object perception, or to action processing in general (Rossetti et al. 2003; Briscoe 2009; Briscoe and Schwenkler 2015; Ferretti 2017b).

  13. While we can quasi-egocentrically localize depicted objects and represent their relative depth (§3.1), we can obtain absolute egocentric localization only with normal objects—exception made for pictorial illusions (Sect. 4.3).

  14. Recall that the AIP is involved in visual recognition, whose processing is related to that of the ventral areas mentioned above (Sects. 3.1, 3.2).

  15. This also happens when the object is perceived as present, but we decide not to act.

  16. Most of the time, such an object is real, but it could also be pictorial, as in the case of pictorial illusions able to deceive our visual recognition (Sect. 4.3).

  17. For a brief review of their role in picture perception in tune with the account proposed here see (Ferretti 2017c).

  18. The mainly ventral contribution is related to the perceptual fact that “high-level, categorical representations of the functional and material properties of objects that are not usable directly in motor programming can be used instead for action planning” (Briscoe and Schwenkler 2015: 1437; Wallhagen 2007).

  19. For this reason, the information managed by the ventral stream can be used in the motor programming mainly generated by the dorsal stream, especially in the mainly dorsal interplay. Thus, ventral processing is important for different aspects of the visual guidance of action (Young 2006; Briscoe and Schwenkler 2015; Chinellato and Del Pobil 2016; Gallese 2007; Zipoli Caiani and Ferretti 2016; Ferretti 2016b: Sect. 5, c). This is in line with the fact that both dorsal and ventral vision are involved in–and cooperate during–the encoding of action in different manners (Ibid.).

  20. Which can be followed by motor interaction (computed by the mainly dorsal interplay).

  21. Recall that the minimal ventral contribution in the mainly dorsal interplay only concerns semantic encoding for the dorsal action property attribution, not high-level recognition. But the semantic information coming from ventral processing cannot detect presence. Therefore, this mainly dorsal interplay is not related to any recognition of presence (Sect. 4).

  22. Note that dorsal computations are triggered without the subject wanting or attempting to grasp the object: observation in static conditions directly triggers these dorsal visuomotor responses (Ferretti 2016a: Sect. 4, 2017c). The reader should note that I do not mean here that the motor behavior of the subject in general is the same with both real and depicted objects: we do not attempt to grasp objects in a picture. The idea is that the representational behavior of the dorsal stream and, thus, of the mainly dorsal interplay, is the same with both of them. Accordingly, I am not saying that we (normally) attempt to grasp both depicted and normal objects: of course, we do not even attempt to grasp depicted objects. Finally, note that I am not even saying that a subject would attempt (if requested to do so in an experimental setting) to grasp a depicted and a normal object in the same manner. Evidence suggests, indeed, that attempting to grasp normal (i.e. non-trompe l’oeil) depicted objects is different from attempting to grasp real objects (Freud, Ganel, et al. 2015a: 1381). In accordance with this, there is plenty of evidence that even action planning directed toward depictions is computed differently with respect to face-to-face scenarios (Culham 2018).

  23. Concerning how motor responses decay, see (Borghi and Riggio 2015).

  24. However, when the mainly ventral interplay is deceived, as in the case of pictorial illusions, the results of motor programming may end up being wrongly used for generating covert action (Sect. 4.3). In normal pictorial scenarios, the low-level action property attribution concerning the surface, and realized by the mainly dorsal interplay, is always accompanied by the detection of its presence, subserved by the mainly ventral interplay. Thus, the mainly ventral action planning can always direct the mainly dorsal motor programming toward the surface.

  25. Response selection and action planning are mainly ventrally subserved. Thus, given the dorsal magnocellular advantage, their occurrence is slower than the occurrence of the visuomotor response mainly dorsally subserved. However, the link between the dorsal AIP and the inferotemporal areas related to the ventral stream (Verhoef et al. 2011; Fogassi and Luppino 2005; Sects. 3.2, 3.3) guarantees that ventral semantic information can be used by the dorsal stream to compute an appropriate motor act even before response selection and action planning are performed.

  26. However, the final go/no-go responses related to action release depend on the prefrontal cortex, which manages the computations coming from both streams (Lebedev and Wise 2002; Sereno et al. 2002).

  27. Not only does this theory explain how we ascribe the feeling of presence, and why this is not only ascribed to real objects, but also to some special kinds of depicted objects. Furthermore, it allows us to understand what determines the visual ascription of pictoriality (related to less enhanced visual cues), which can be ascribed not only to objects in a picture, but also to real objects in certain cases, like, for example, to landscapes (Vishwanath 2011: 225, 228; Matthen 2005: 322; Ferretti 2016c: 8).

  28. In line with (Sect. 4.1), when the mainly ventral interplay establishes, thanks to the detection of such special visual features, that the surface is a real and present object we can interact with, the information about visuomotor interaction computed by the mainly dorsal interplay can be used to generate overt action on the surface. This is not possible with depicted objects, with which the motor response is triggered, and then bound to decay.

  29. These are the main visual characteristics at the basis of ‘stereopsis’, i.e. the visual process thanks to which we see a three-dimensional present world (Vishwanath 2014).

  30. What about the case of hyperrealist but not delusive paintings? When perceiving these paintings, one may have a more vivid apprehension of the depicted object than the one we can get in the case of normal paintings. But with these paintings the surface is visible. Thus, this vivid apprehension will not be as strong as the one we can get from real and present objects and, ipso facto, from a real and present object like a surface: the pictorial visual features will never be equal to the enhanced visual features of a real object like the surface. For this reason, absolute depth cannot be ascribed to the depicted object, but only to the surface. Thus, in accordance with vision science, only with the surface can we have the perception of presence, for only with the surface are we able to visually represent the possibility of absolute depth localization, which depends on the ascription of the enhanced visual features reported above, which are displayed only by real objects, like the surface.

  31. In accordance with footnote 28, even if a covert representation of the motor acts is generated by the mainly dorsal interplay in both cases, we can use this to effectively perform overt motor execution only with the surface.

  32. Dorsal representations for the detection of action properties and the construction of motor acts, considered alone (i.e. without any interplay with ventral processing), are taken to be unconscious and not consciously accessible (Brogaard 2011a). However, there is no problem in suggesting that, thanks to interstream interplay, ‘conscious vision can affect action’ (Brogaard 2011a: 1078; Briscoe 2009; Briscoe and Schwenkler 2015) and that a mainly ventral interplay can give rise to a conscious action planning (Chinellato and Del Pobil 2016; Ferretti 2016b, c; Zipoli Caiani and Ferretti 2016).

  33. It is worth noting that also Briscoe (2016, 2018) has recently suggested that absolute egocentric depth representation grounds the feeling of presence towards the surface and not towards the depicted object. However, Briscoe defends a sort of ‘weak onefoldness’. Such an account does not deny, as ‘strong onefoldness’ (as Briscoe calls it), that our visual system attributes properties to the depicted object and to the surface at the same time. It simply wants to stress that pictorial experience is ‘onefold’ “in the sense that its content reflects a single, consistent 3D scene interpretation of the retinal image” (2018: Sect. 4). That said, however, the notion of ‘weak onefoldness’ is also used to support the philosophical idea of a continuity (the ‘continuity hypothesis’) between face-to-face and picture perception, in the sense that perceiving an object face-to-face and perceiving an object in a picture are not experiences of a different psychological kind, but only concerning the degree of representational content, i.e. the degree of attribution of the properties that are respectively ascribed in both of those two perceptual states. Since the goal of this paper is to describe the ‘neural dynamics of seeing-in’ in relation to interstream interaction, I cannot tackle this further deep philosophical point here. A discussion of this point will have to wait for another occasion.

  34. However, when our mainly ventral interplay is deceived, it triggers action planning on the depicted object. At this point, we can actually attempt to grasp the pictorial object. When this happens, the visuomotor resources we use to shape overt motor execution come from the mainly dorsal interplay, as in the case of face-to-face perception.

  35. Experimental results suggest that the mainly ventral interplay can be conscious or unconscious, while the mainly dorsal one is always unconscious and cannot be consciously accessed (Chinellato and Del Pobil 2016; Ferretti 2016b, 2016c; Zipoli Caiani and Ferretti 2016).

  36. Since trompe l’oeils deceive us for a moment, the explanation here concerns the moment in which the deception is at work.

  37. It is crucial to note that I am using ‘conscious vision’ and ‘conscious visual attention’ interchangeably. I bypass the debate on the relations between consciousness and attention, when talking about picture perception. This is not a problem (Nanay 2011, 2017; Voltolini 2013).

  38. In accordance with footnote 35, a mainly ventral unconscious representation for recognition can be subsequently accessed. This is something not possible with a mainly dorsal representation for motor action.

  39. Of course, at the same time, also our mainly dorsal interplay represents the action properties of the depicted object and of the surface. But this is a subpersonal, unconscious, representational response, whose result can be used only with the surface.

  40. The notions of ‘mainly dorsal’ and ‘mainly ventral’ interplay only denote a particular way in which the streams interact in a given situation.

  41. This work was supported by the ‘Fondazione Franco e Marilisa Caligara per l’Alta Formazione Interdisciplinare’. I have several special thanks to offer. First of all, I want to thank Bence Nanay, for spending so much time discussing with me about the relations between picture perception and the functioning of our visual system. The second goes to two anonymous referees, whose crucial and insightful comments allowed me to significantly clarify to the reader some technical aspects of the theory developed here. Special thanks also go to these excellent scholars who have always proven to be ready to enthusiastically discuss with me about several issues concerning the functioning of the visual system: Andrea Borghini, Silvano Zipoli Caiani, Chiara Brozzo, Albert Newen, Anna Maria Borghi, Giorgia Committeri, Neil Van Leuween, Francesco Marchi, Alberto Voltolini. Finally, special thanks go to the students in Philosophy in Urbino, who attended my lessons in ‘Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science’ and offered several points on this topic.

References

  • Aasen, S. (2015). Pictures, presence and visibility. Philosophical Studies, 173(1), 187–203. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0475-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aglioti, S., DeSouza, J. F. X., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). Size-contrast illusions deceive the eye but not the hand. Current Biology, 5, 679–685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Almeida, J., Mahon, B. Z., Nakayama, K., & Caramazza, A. (2008). Unconscious processing dissociates along categorical lines. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 105, 15214–15218.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar, M. (2003). A cortical mechanism for triggering top-down facilitation in visual object recognition. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 15, 600–609.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar, M., Kassam, K. S., Ghuman, A. S., et al. (2006). Top-down facilitation of visual recognition. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 103, 449–454.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. F., & Bar, L. F. (2009). See it with feeling: Affective predictions during object perception. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 364, 1325–1334.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, S. (2009). Fixing my gaze. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bettencourt, K. C., & Xu, Y. (2013). The role of transverse occipital sulcus in scene perception and its relationship to object individuation in inferior intraparietal sulcus. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 25, 1711–1722.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2014). Seeing-as in the light of vision science. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89(1), 560–572.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borghi, A. M., & Riggio, L. (2015). Stable and variable affordances are both automatic and flexible. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 9, 351. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2015.00351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borra, E., Belmalih, A., Calzavara, R., et al. (2007). Cortical connections of the macaque anterior intraparietal (AIP) area. Cerebral Cortex, 18(5), 1094–1111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, R. (2009). Egocentric spatial representation in action and perception. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79, 423–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, R. (2016) Depiction, pictorial experience, and vision science. In C. Hill & B. McLaughlin (Eds.), Philosophical topics, special issue on appearance properties, 44(2).

  • Briscoe, R. (2018). Gombrich and the Duck-Rabbit. In M. Beaney (Ed.), Aspect perception after Wittgenstein: Seeing-as and novelty (pp. 49–88). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, R., & Schwenkler, J. (2015). Conscious vision in action. Cognitive Science, 39(7), 1435–1467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2011a). Conscious vision for action versus unconscious vision for action? Cognitive Science, 35, 1076–1104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2011b). Are there unconscious perceptual processes? Consciousness and Cognition, 20(2), 449–463.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruno, N. (2001). When does action resist visual illusions? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, 385–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruno, N., & Battaglini, P. P. (2008). Integrating perception and action through cognitive neuropsychology (broadly conceived). Cognitive Neuropshycology, 25(7–8), 879–890.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruno, N., & Franz, V. H. (2009). When is grasping affected by the Müller–Lyer illusion? A quantitative review. Neuropsychologia, 47, 1421–1433.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bullier, J. (2001). Integrated model of visual processing. Brain Research. Brain Research Reviews, 36, 96–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bullier, J., Hupè, J. M., James, A. C., et al. (2001). The role of feedback connections in shaping the responses of visual cortical neurons. Progress in Brain Research, 134, 193–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavedon-Taylor, D. (2011). The space of seeing-in. British Journal of Aesthetics, 51(3), 271–278.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti G., & Chinellato, E. (In Press) Can our Robots rely on an emotionally charged vision-for-action? An embodied model for neurorobotics. In J. Vallverdú, & V. C. Müller (Eds.), Blended cognition. The robotic challenge, Berlin: Springer.

  • Chinellato, E., & del Pobil, A. P. (2016). The visual neuroscience of robotic grasping. Achieving sensorimotor skills through dorsal-ventral stream integration. Berlin: Springer International Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2009). Perception, action, and experience: Unraveling the golden braid. Neuropsychologia, 47(6), 1460–1468.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cloutman, L. L. (2013). Interaction between dorsal and ventral processing streams: Where, when and how? Brain and Language, 127(2), 251–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, N., Cross, E., Tunikc, E., et al. (2009). Ventral and dorsal stream contributions to the online control of immediate and delayed grasping: A TMS approach. Neuropsychologia, 47, 1553–1562.

    Google Scholar 

  • Culham, J. C. (2018). Getting a grip on reality: Grasping movements directed to real objects and images rely on dissociable neural representations. Cortex, 98, 34–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Culham, J. C., Cavina-Pratesi, C., & Singhal, A. (2006). The role of parietal cortex in visuomotor control: What have we learned from neuroimaging? Neuropsychologia, 44(13), 2668–2684.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cutting, J. E. (2003). Reconceiving perceptual space. In H. Hecht, R. Schwartz, & M. Atherton (Eds.), Looking into pictures: An interdisciplinary approach to pictorial space (pp. 215–238). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Haan, E. H. F., Jackson, S. T., & Schenk, T. (2018). Where are we now with ‘What’ and ‘How’? Cortex, 98(1), 7. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.rehab.2017.02.002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Carlo, J. J., Zoccolan, D., & Rust, N. C. (2012). How does the brain solve visual object recognition? Neuron, 73, 415–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dijkerman, H. C., McIntosh, R. D., Schindler, I., Nijboer, T. C. W., & Milner, A. D. (2009). Choosing between alternative wrist postures: Action planning needs perception. Neuropsychologia, 47(6), 1476–1482. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2008.12.002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Durand, J. B., Nelissen, K., Joly, O., et al. (2007). Anterior regions of monkey parietal cortex process visual 3D shape. Neuron, 55(3), 493–505.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durand, J. B., Peeters, R., Norman, J. F., et al. (2009). Parietal regions processing visual 3D shape extracted from disparity. Neuroimage, 46, 1114–1126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fang, F., & He, S. (2005). Cortical responses to invisible objects in the human dorsal and ventral pathways. Nature Neuroscience, 8, 1380–1385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farivar, R. (2009). Dorsal–ventral integration in object recognition. Brain Research Reviews, 61(2), 144–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2016a). Pictures, action properties and motor related effects. Synthese, Special Issue: Neuroscience and Its Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1097-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2016b). Through the forest of motor representations. Consciousness and Cognition, 43, 177–196. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2016.05.013.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2016c). Visual feeling of presence. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2017a). Pictures, emotions, and the dorsal/ventral account of picture perception. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-017-0330-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2017b). Two visual systems in molyneux subjects. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9533-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2017c). Are pictures peculiar objects of perception? Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 3(3), 372–393. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2017.28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (Forthcoming). Perceiving surfaces (and what they depict). In B. Glenney & J. F. Silva (Eds.), The senses and the history of philosophy, London: Routledge.

  • Ferretti, G., & Zipoli Caiani, S. (2018). Solving the interface problem without translation: The same format thesis. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fogassi, L., & Luppino, G. (2005). Motor functions of the parietal lobe. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 15(6), 626–631.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley, T. R., Whitwell, R. L., & Goodale, M. A. (2015). The two-visual-systems hypothesis and the perspectival features of visual experience. Consciousness and Cognition, 35(2015), 225–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, E., Ganel, T., & Shelef, I, et al. (2015a). Three-dimensional representations of objects in dorsal cortex are dissociable from those in ventral cortex. Cerebral Cortex, pp. 1–13.

  • Freud, E., Rosenthal, G., Ganel, T., & Avidan, G. (2015b). Sensitivity to object impossibility in the human visual cortex: Evidence from functional connectivity. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 27, 1029–1043.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2007). The ‘‘Conscious” dorsal stream: Embodied simulation and its role in space and action conscious awareness. Psyche, 13(1), 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Georgieva, S., Peeters, R., Kolster, H., et al. (2009). The processing of three-dimensional shape from disparity in the human brain. Journal of Neuroscience, 29, 727–742.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gombrich, E. (1960). Art and illusion. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., & Milner, A. D. (2004). Sight unseen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., & Milner, A. D. (2018). Two visual pathways–where have they taken us and where will they lead in future? Cortex, 98, 283–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grill-Spector, K., Kushnir, T., Edelman, S., et al. (1999). Differential processing of objects under various viewing conditions in the human lateral occipital complex. Neuron, 24, 187–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grill-Spector, K., & Malach, R. (2004). The human visual cortex. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 27, 649–677.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grush, R. (2000). Self, world, and space: The meaning and mechanisms of ego- and allocentric spatial representation. Brain and Mind, 1, 59–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haak, K. V., & Beckmann, C. F. (2018). Objective analysis of the topological organization of the human cortical visual connectome suggests three visual pathways. Cortex, 98, 73–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hecht, H., Schwartz, R., & Atherton, M. (Eds.). (2003). Looking into pictures: An interdisciplinary approach to pictorial space (pp. 215–238). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helbig, H. B., Graf, M., & Kiefer, M. (2006). The role of action representations in visual object recognition. Experimental Brain Research, 174, 221–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helbig, H. B., Steinwender, J., Graf, M., & Kiefer, M. (2010). Action observation can prime visual object recognition. Experimental Brain Research, 200, 251–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (1998). Picture, image and experience. A philosophical inquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (2003). Pictures, phenomenology and cognitive science. Monist, 86, 653–675.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (2010). Inflected pictorial experience: Its treatment and significance. In C. Abell & K. Bantilaki (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives on depiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (2012). Seeing-in and seeming to see. Analysis, 72, 650–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoshi, E., & Tanji, J. (2007). Distinctions between dorsal and ventral premotor areas: Anatomical connectivity and functional properties. Current Opinions in Neurobiology, 17(2), 234–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ikkai, A., Jerde, T. A., & Curtis, C. E. (2011). Perception and action selection dissociate human ventral and dorsal cortex. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 23, 1494–1506.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P., & Jeannerod, M. (2003). Ways of seeing: The scope and limits of visual cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, T., Humphrey, G., Gati, J., et al. (2002). Differential effects of viewpoint on object-driven activation in dorsal and ventral stream. Neuron, 35, 793–801.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (1997). The cognitive neuroscience of action. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (2006). Motor cognition: What actions tell the self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M., Decety, J., & Michel, F. (1994). Impairment of grasping movements following a bilateral posterior parietal lesion. Neuropsychologia, 32, 369–380.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kandel, E. R., Schwartz, J. H., Jessell, T. M., et al. (2013). Principles of neural science. New York: McGraw Hill Medical.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiefer, M., Sim, E. J., Helbig, H., & Graf, M. (2011). Tracking the time course of action priming on object recognition: evidence for fast and slow influences of action on perception. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 23, 1864–1874.

    Google Scholar 

  • Konen, C. S., & Kastner, S. (2008). Two hierarchically organized neural systems for object information in human visual cortex. Nature Neuroscience, 11, 224–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kopiske, K., Bruno, N., Hesse, K., Schenk, T., & Franz, V. H. (2016). The functional subdivision of the visual brain: Is there a real illusion effect on action? A multi-lab replication study. Cortex, 79, 130–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kozuch, B. (2015). Dislocation, not dissociation: The neuroanatomical argument against visual experience driving motor action. Mind and Language, 30(5), 572–602.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kravitz, D. J., Saleem, K. I., Baker, C. I., & Mishkin, M. (2011). A new neural framework for visuospatial processing. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 12, 217–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kravitz, D. J., Saleem, K. S., Baker, C. I., et al. (2013). The ventral visual pathway: An expanded neural framework for the processing of object quality. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17(1), 26–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kulvicki, J. (2006). On images. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laycock, R., Crewther, S. G., & Crewther, D. P. (2007). A role for the “magnocellular advantage” in visual impairments in neurodevelopmental and psychiatric disorders. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 31, 363–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laycock, R., Crewther, D. P., Fitzgerald, P. B., & Crewther, S. G. (2009). TMS disruption of V5/MT+ indicates a role for the dorsal stream in word recognition. Experimental Brain Research, 197, 69–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laycock, R., Cross, A. J., Lourenco, T., & Crewther, S. G. (2011). Dorsal stream involvement in recognition of objects with transient onset but not with ramped onset. Behavioral and Brain Functions, 7, 34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lebedev, M. A., & Wise, S. P. (2002). Insights into seeing and grasping: Distinguishing the neural correlates of perception and action. Behavioral and Cognitive Neuroscience Reviews, 1(2), 108–129. https://doi.org/10.1177/1534582302001002002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehky, S. R., & Sereno, A. B. (2007). Comparison of shape encoding in primate dorsal and ventral visual pathways. Journal of Neurophysiology, 97, 307–319. https://doi.org/10.1152/jn.00168.2006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, T., Walsh, V., & Lavidor, M. (2010). Dorsal stream modulation of visual word recognition in skilled readers. Vision Research, 50(9), 883–888.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lopes, D. M. (1996). Understanding pictures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lopes, D. M. (2005). Sight and sensibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martinaud, O., Mirlink, N., Bioux, S., et al. (2014). Agnosia for mirror stimuli: A new case report with a small parietal lesion. Archives of Clinical Neuropsychology, 29(7), 724–728.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2005). Seeing, doing and knowing: A philosophical theory of sense perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McIntosh, R. D., & Schenk, T. (2009). Two visual streams for perception and action: Current trends. Neuropsychologia, 47(6), 1391–1396.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (2004). Varieties of meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A., & Goodale, M. (1995/2006). The visual brain in action (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (2008). Two visual systems re-viewed. Neuropsychologia, 46, 774–785.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (2010). Cortical visual systems for perception and action. In N. Gangopadhyay, M. Madary, & F. Spencer (Eds.), Perception, action, and consciousness: Sensorimotor dynamics and the two visual systems (pp. 71–95). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mole, C. (2009). Illusions, demonstratives, and the zombie action hypothesis. Mind, 118, 472.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murata, A., Gallese, V., Luppino, G., et al. (2000). Selectivity for the shape, size, and orientation of objects for grasping in neurons of monkey parietal area AIP. Journal of Neurophysiology, 83(5), 2580–2601.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2010). Inflected and uninflected experience of pictures. In C. Abell & K. Bantinaki (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives on depiction (pp. 181–207). Oxford: Oxford U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2011). Perceiving pictures. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 10, 461–480.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2013). Between perception and action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2015). Trompe l’oeil and the dorsal/ventral account of picture perception. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 6, 181–197. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-014-0219-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2017). Threefoldness. Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0860-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelissen, K., Joly, O., Durand, J. B., et al. (2009). The extraction of depth structure from shading and texture in the macaque brain. PLoS ONE, 4(12), e8306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noudoost, B., Chang, M. H., Steinmetz, N. A., & Moore, T. (2010). Top-down control of visual attention. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 20, 183–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orban, G. A. (2011). The extraction of 3D shape in the visual system of human and nonhuman primates. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 34, 361–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pammer, K., Hansen, P., Holliday, I., & Cornelissen, P. (2006). Attentional shifting and the role of the dorsal pathway in visual word recognition. Neuropsychologia, 44(14), 2926–2936.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, C. J., & Fallah, M. (2014). Feature integration and object representations along the dorsal stream visual hierarchy. Frontiers in Computational Neuroscience, 8, 84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peuskens, H., Claeys, K. G., Todd, J. T., et al. (2004). Attention to 3-D shape, 3-D motion, and texture in 3-D structure from motion displays. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 16(4), 665–682.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priftis, K., Rusconi, E., Umilta, C., & Zorzi, M. (2003). Pure agnosia for mirror stimuli after right inferior parietal lesion. Brain, 126(Pt 4), 908–919.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raos, V., Umiltà, M. A., Murata, A., et al. (2006). Functional properties of grasping-related neurons in the ventral premotor area F5 of the macaque monkey. Journal of Neurophysiology, 95, 709–729.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rice, N. J., Valyear, K. F., Goodale, M. A., et al. (2007). Orientation sensitivity to graspable objects: An fMRI adaptation study. Neuroimage, 36, T87–T93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Matelli, M. (2003). Two different streams form the dorsal visual system: Anatomy and functions. Experimental Brain Research, 153, 146–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Sinigaglia, C. (2008). Mirrors in the brain how our minds share actions and emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rossetti, Y., Pisella, L., & McIntosh, R. D. (2017). Rise and fall of the two visual systems theory. Annals of Physical and Rehabilitation Medicine, 60(3), 130–140. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.rehab.2017.02.002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rossetti, Y., Pisella, L., & Vighetto, A. (2003). Optic ataxia revisited: Visually guided action versus immediate visuomotor control. Experimental Brain Research, 153, 171–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sakata, H., Tsutsui, K., & Taira, M. (2003). Representation of the 3D world in art and in the brain. International Congress Series, 1250, 5–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sawamura, H., Georgieva, S., Vogels, R., et al. (2005). Using functional magnetic resonance imaging to assess adaptation and size invariance of shape processing by humans and monkeys. Journal of Neuroscience, 25, 4294–4306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schenk, T., & McIntosh, R. D. (2010). Do we have independent visual streams for perception and action? Cognitive Neuroscience, 1, 52–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sereno, A. B., & Maunsell, J. H. (1998). Shape selectivity in primate lateral intraparietal cortex. Nature, 395(6701), 500–503.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sereno, M. E., Trinath, T., Augath, M., & Logothetis, N. K. (2002). Three-dimensional shape representation in monkey cortex. Neuron, 33(4), 635–652.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, J. (2015). Conscious action/zombie action. Noûs, 50(2), 219–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sim, E.-J., Helbig, H. B., Graf, M., & Kiefer, M. (2015). When action observation facilitates visual perception: Activation in visuo-motor areas contributes to object recognition. Cerebral Cortex, 25, 2907–2918.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singhal, A., Culham, J. C., Chinellato, E., & Goodale, M. A. (2007). Dual-task interference is greater in delayed grasping than in visually guided grasping. Journal of Vision, 7(5), 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singhal, A., Monaco, S., Kaufman, L. D., & Culham, J. C. (2013). Human fMRI reveals that delayed action re-recruits visual perception. PLoS ONE, 8(9), e73629.

    Google Scholar 

  • Srivastava, S., Orban, G. A., De Mazière, P. A., & Janssen, P. (2009). A distinct representation of three-dimensional shape in macaque anterior intraparietal area: Fast, metric, and coarse. Journal of Neuroscience, 29(34), 10613–10626.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taira, M., Nose, I., Inoue, K., & Tsutsui, K. (2001). Cortical areas related to attention to 3D surface. Neuroimage, 14(5), 959–966.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takemura, H., Rokem, A., Winawer, J., et al. (2016). A major human white matter pathway between dorsal and ventral visual cortex. Cerebral Cortex, 26(5), 2205–2214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanaka, K. (1996). Inferotemporal cortex and object vision. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 19(109), 139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tchernikov, I., & Fallah, M. (2010). A color hierarchy for automatic target selection. PLoS ONE, 5, e9338. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0009338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Theys, T., Pani, P., van Loon, J., et al. (2012). Selectivity for three-dimensional shape and grasping-related activity in the macaque ventral premotor cortex. Journal of Neuroscience, 32(35), 12038–12050.

    Google Scholar 

  • Theys, T., Romero, M. C., van Loon, J., & Janssen, P. (2015). Shape representations in the primate dorsal visual stream. Frontiers in Computational Neuroscience. https://doi.org/10.3389/fncom.2015.00043.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsutsui, K., Sakata, H., Naganuma, T., & Taira, M. (2002). Neural correlates for perception of 3D surface orientation from texture gradient. Science, 298, 409–412.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsutsui, K., Taira, M., & Sakata, H. (2005). Neural mechanisms of three-dimensional vision. Neuroscience Research, 51, 221–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turnbull, O. H., Driver, J., & McCarthy, R. A. (2004). 2D but not 3D: Pictorial depth deficits in a case of visual agnosia. Cortex, 40, 723–738.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valyear, K. F., Culham, J. C., Sharif, N., et al. (2006). A double dissociation between sensitivity to changes in object identity and object orientation in the ventral and dorsal visual streams: A human fMRI study. Neuropsychologia, 44, 218–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Polanen, V., & Davare, M. (2015). Interactions between dorsal and ventral streams for controlling skilled grasp. Neuropsychologya, 79, 186–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verhoef, B. E., Michelet, P., Vogels, R., & Janssen, P. (2015). Choice-related activity in the anterior intraparietal area during 3-D structure categorization. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 27, 1104–1115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verhoef, B. E., Vogels, R., & Janssen, P. (2011). Synchronization between the end stages of the dorsal and the ventral visual stream. Journal of Neurophysiology, 105(5), 2030–2042.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vishwanath, D. (2011). Information in surface and depth perception: Reconciling pictures and reality. In L. Albertazzi, G. J. van Tonder, & D. Vishwanath (Eds.), Perception beyond inference. The information content of visual processes (pp. 201–240). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vishwanath, D. (2014). Toward a new theory of stereopsis. Psychological Review, 121(2), 151–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vishwanath, D., & Hibbard, P. (2010). Quality in depth perception: The plastic effect. Journal of Vision. https://doi.org/10.1167/10.7.42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vishwanath, D., & Hibbard, P. (2013). Seeing in 3D with just one eye: Stereopsis in the absence of binocular disparities. Psychological Science, 24, 1673–1685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. (2013). Why, as responsible for figurativity, seeing-in can only be inflected seeing-in. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14(3), 651–667.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallhagen, M. (2007). Consciousness and action: Does cognitive science support (mild) epiphenomenalism? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(3), 539–561.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webster, M. J., Bachevalier, J., & Ungerleider, L. G. (1994). Connections of inferior temporal areas TEO and TE with parietal and frontal cortex in macaque. Cerebral Cortex, 5, 470–483.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westwood, D., Danckert, J., Servos, P., & Goodale, M. (2002). Grasping two-dimensional images and three-dimensional objects in visual-form agnosia. Experimental Brain Research, 144(2), 262–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wokke, M. E., Scholte, H. S., & Lamme, V. A. F. (2014). Opposing dorsal/ventral stream dynamics during figure-ground segregation. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 26(2), 365–379.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. (1980). Seeing-as, seeing-in, and pictorial representation. In Art and its object (2nd ed., pp. 205–226). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Wollheim, R. (1987). Painting as an art. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. (1998). On pictorial representation. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 56, 217–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (2014). Against division: Consciousness, information and the visual streams. Mind and Language, 29(4), 383–406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Xu, Y. (2009). Distinctive neural mechanisms supporting visual object individuation and identification. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 21, 511–518.

    Google Scholar 

  • Xu, Y., & Chun, M. M. (2009). Selecting and perceiving multiple visual objects. Cell Press. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2009.01.008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yeatman, J. D., Weiner, K. S., Pestilli, F., et al. (2014). The vertical occipital fasciculus: A century of controversy resolved by in vivo measurements. Proceedings of National Academy of Sciences, 111, E5214–E5223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, G. (2006). Are different affordances subserved by different neural pathways? Brain and Cognition, 62, 134–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zachariou, V., Klatzky, R., & Behrmann, M. (2014). Ventral and dorsal visual stream contributions to the perception of object shape and object location. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 26(1), 189–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zanon, M., Busan, P., Monti, F., et al. (2010). Cortical connections between dorsal and ventral visual streams in humans: Evidence by TMS/EEG co-registration. Brain Topography, 22(4), 307–317.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zipoli Caiani, S., & Ferretti, G. (2016). Semantic and pragmatic integration in vision for action. Consciousness and Cognition, 48, 40–54. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2016.10.009.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gabriele Ferretti.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ferretti, G. The Neural Dynamics of Seeing-In. Erkenn 84, 1285–1324 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0060-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0060-2

Navigation