Skip to main content
Log in

In defense of pluralist theory

  • Folk Psychology: Pluralistic Approaches
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

A Correction to this article was published on 07 March 2020

This article has been updated

Abstract

In this article I defend pluralist theory against various objections. First, I argue that although traditional theories may also account for multiple ways to achieve social understanding, they still put some emphasis on one particular epistemic strategy (e.g., theory or simulation). Pluralist theory, in contrast, rejects the so-called ‘default assumption’ that there is any primary or default method in social understanding. Second, I illustrate that pluralist theory needs to be distinguished from integration theory. On one hand, integration theory faces the difficulty of trying to combine traditional theories of social understanding that have contradictory background assumptions. On the other hand, pluralist theory goes beyond integrating traditional theories by accounting for a variety of factors that may play a role in social understanding but have been (widely) neglected in such theories, including stereotype activation, social and personal relationships, contextual features, individual moods, perceptions, and so on. Third, I argue that if the default assumption is rejected, pluralist theorists need to provide another positive account of why particular cognitive processes are more likely to come into play in a specific instance of social understanding than others in order to provide a genuine alternative to traditional theories. I discuss three versions of pluralist theory that meet this challenge by pointing to normativity, fluency, and interaction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

Notes

  1. Since pluralist theory is not devoted to any particular view of cognition per se, it is perfectly possible that philosophers who endorse different but not contradictory views of cognition team up to explore the varieties of social understanding from a pluralist viewpoint. For example, Fiebich et al. (2017) agree with respect to pluralism in social cognition but differ in their views of whether cognition is enactive (Hutto and Myin 2017; Gallagher 2017a) or whether to remain neutral with respect to endorsing neither enactivism nor cognitivism, though sympathizing with dynamic embodied views of cognition (e.g., de Bruin and Kaestner 2012) when it comes to social understanding in interactive settings (Fiebich 2015, chapt. 4).

  2. Note that the distinction between Type 1 and Type 2 processes resembles the 2-System approach defended by Fiebich and Coltheart (2015), but it is neither essential for integration theory nor pluralist theory to advocate a 2-System view of cognition.

  3. Anika Fiebich (2015) developed a pluralist approach to social understanding in framework of her doctoral thesis independently from Kristin Andrew’s work and inspired by scientific discussions with Maxoltheart (Fiebich and Coltheart 2015). Unfortunately, she only heard about Andrew’s approach when the book ‘How apes read minds’ appeared in 2012 shortly before submitting her thesis at the Ruhr-University Bochum, Germany, so that a substantial discussion of Andrew’s approach in the thesis (published three years later in roughly its original version according to German law) was not possible anymore.

References

  • Andrews, K. (2008). It’s in your nature. A pluralistic folk psychology. Synthese, 165(1), 13–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, K. (2012). Do apes read minds?. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, K. (2015a). The folk psychological spiral: Explanation, regulation, and language. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53(Spindel Supplement), 50–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, K. (2015b). Pluralistic folk psychology and varieties of self-knowledge: An exploration. Philosophical Explorations, 18(2), 280–294.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, K. (2017). Pluralistic folk psychology in humans and other apes. In J. Kiverstein (Ed.), The routledge handbook o the social mind (pp. 117–138). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Apperly, I. (2008). Beyond simulation-theory and theory–theory: Why social neuroscience should use its own concepts to study “theory of mind”. Cognition, 107, 266–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barlassina, L., & Gordon, R. M. (2017). Folk psychology as mental simulation. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohl, V. (2015a). We read minds to shape relationships. Philosophical Psychology, 28(5), 674–694.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohl, V. (2015b). Continuing debates on direct social perception: Some notes on Gallagher’s analysis of “the new hybrids”. Consciousness and Cognition, 36, 466–471.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohl, V., & van den Bos, W. (2012). Toward an integrative account of social cognition: Marrying theory of mind and interactionism to study the interplay of type 1 and type 2 processes. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 6, 274. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2012.00274

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borg, E. (2007). If mirror neurons are the answer, what was the question? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14, 5–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2014). The semantic problem(s) with research on animal mind-reading. Mind and Language, 29(5), 566–589.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S. (2012). Interacting mindreaders. Philosophical Studies, 165(3), 841–863.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carpendale, J. I. M., & Lewis, C. (2004). Constructing an understanding of mind: The development of children’s social understanding within social interaction. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27, 79–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (1996). Simulation and self-knowledg: A defence of theory–theory. In P. Carruthers & P. K. Smith (Eds.), Theories of theories of mind (pp. 22–28). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2016). Two systems for mindreading? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 7, 141–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cogsdill, E. J., Todorov, A., Spelke, E. S., & Banaji, M. R. (2014). Inferring character from faces: A developmental study. Psychological Science, 25(5), 1132–1139.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Bruin, L., & Kaestner, L. (2012). Dynamic embodied cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11(4), 541–563.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E., & Gallagher, S. (2010). Does social interaction constitute social cognition? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(10), 441–447.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drayson, Z. (2012). The uses and abuses of the personal/subpersonal distinction. Philosophical Perspectives, 26(1), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fabricius, W. V., Boyer, T., Weimer, A. A., & Carroll, K. (2010). True or false: Do five-year-olds understand belief? Developmental Psychology, 46, 1402–1416.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiebich, A. (2014). Mindreading with ease? Fluence and belief-reasoning in 4- to 5-year-olds. Synthese, 191(5), 929–9244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiebich, A. (2015). Varieties of social understanding. Paderborn: Mentis Verlag GmbH.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiebich, A. (2017). Pluralism, social cognition, and interaction in autism. Philosophical Psychology, 30(1–2), 161–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiebich, A., & Coltheart, M. (2015). Various ways to understand other minds: Towards a pluralistic approach to the explanation of social understanding. Mind and Language, 30(3), 235–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiebich, A., Gallagher, S., & Hutto, D. D. (2017). Pluralism, interaction, and the ontogeny of social cognition. In J. Kiverstein (Ed.), The routledge handbook o the social mind (pp. 208–221). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., & di Paolo, E. (2011). The enactive approach: Theoretical sketches from cell to society. Pragmatics & Cognition, 19(1), 1–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind: Theory, simulation, or primary interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5–7), 83–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008). Direct perception in the intersubjective context. Consciousness and Cognition, 17, 535–543.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2015). The new hybrids: Continuing debates on social perception. Consciousness and Cognition, 36, 452–465.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017a). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017b). The significance and meaning of others. In C. Durt, T. Fuchs, & C. Tewes (Eds.), Embodiment, enaction, and culture (pp. 217–227). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Fiebich, A. (2019). Being pluralist about understanding others: Contexts and communicative practices. In A. Avramides & M. Parrott (Eds.), Knowing and understanding other minds (pp. 63–78). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Hutto, D. D. (2008). Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In J. Zlatev, T. Racine, C. Sinha, & E. Itkonen (Eds.), The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity (pp. 17–38). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., & Sinigaglia, C. (2011). What is so special about embodied simulation? Trends in Cognitive Science, 15(11), 512–519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2005). Folk psychology as a model. Philosophers’ Imprint, 5, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2002). Simulation theory and mental concepts. In J. Dokic & J. Proust (Eds.), Simulation and knowledge of action (pp. 1–19). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mind-reading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2012). Theory of mind. In E. Margolis, R. Samuels, & S. P. Stich (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of cognitive science (pp. 402–424). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. (1998). The scientist as child. In A. Gopnik & A. Meltzoff (Eds.), Words, thoughts, and theories (pp. 13–47). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (2012). Reconstructing constructivism: Causal models, Bayesian learning mechanisms and the theory theory. Psychological Bulletin, 138(6), 1085–1108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. M. (1986). Folk psychology as simulation. Mind and Language, 1(2), 158–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, C. (2000). Writing social stories with Carol Grey. Arlington, TX: Future Horizons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heal, J. (2003). Mind, reason and imagination: Selected essays in philosophy of mind and language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heal, J. (2013). Social anti-individualism, co-cognitivism, and second person authority. Mind, 122, 339–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herschbach, M. (2008). Folk psychological and phenomenological accounts of social perception. Philosophical Explorations, 11(3), 223–235.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, E. D. (1965). Truth and method in interpretation. Review of Metaphysics, 18(3), 488–507.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (2008). Understanding simulation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77(3), 755–774.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2008). Folk psychological narratives: The sociocultural basis of understanding reasons. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism. Basic minds meet content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. (2012). Seeing mind in action. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11, 149–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lavelle, J. S. (2012). Theory–theory and the direct perception of mental states. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(2), 213–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (1987). Children’s understanding of the mental world. In R. L. Gregory (Ed.), The Oxford companion to the mind (pp. 139–142). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M., Friedman, O., & German, T. P. (2004). Core mechanisms in ‘theory of mind’. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(12), 528–533.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macrae, C. N., Bodenhausen, G. V., & Milne, A. B. (1995). The dissection of selection in person perception: Inhibitory processes in social stereotyping. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69, 397–407.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maibom, H. L. (2003). The mindreader and the scientist. Mind and Language, 20, 237–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2013). How things shape the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, V. (2007). The regulative dimension of folk psychology. In D. D. Hutto & M. M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Folk psychology re-assessed (pp. 137–156). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michael, H., Christensen, W., & Overgaard, S. (2014). Mindreading as social expertise. Synthese, 191, 817–840.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, R. (2016). Meaning and ostension in great ape gestural communication. Animal Cognition, 19(1), 223–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newen, A. (2015a). Understanding others—The person model theory. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open mind: 26(T) (pp. 1–28). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958570320.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Newen, A. (2015b). A multiplicity view for social cognition: Defending a coherent framework—A reply to Lisa Quadt. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open mind: 26(R) (pp. 1–7). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958571167.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Newen, A., & Schlicht, T. (2009). Understanding other minds. A criticism of Goldman’s simulation theory and an outline of the person model theory. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 79(1), 209–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford Cognitive Science Series. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheimer, D. M. (2008). The secret life of fluency. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12(6), 237–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard, S. (2017). The unobservability thesis. Synthese, 194, 743–760.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quadt, L. (2015). Multiplicity needs coherence—Towards a unifying framework for social understanding—a commentary on Albert Newen. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open mind 26(C) (pp. 1–18). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958571112.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding, S. (2018a). Mindreading beyond belief: A more comprehensive conception of how we understand others. Philosophy Compass, 13(11), e12526.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding, S. (2018b). Do you see what I see? How social differences influence mindreading, Synthese, 195(9), 4009–4030.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stapelton, M., & Ward, D. (2012). Es are good. Cognition as enacted, embodied, embedded, affective and extended. In F. Paglieri (Ed.), Consciousness in interaction: the role of the natural and social context in shaping consciousness (pp. 89–104). Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. B. (1979). Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of primary intersubjectivity. In M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before speech (pp. 321–348). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westra, E. (2018). Character and theory of mind: An integrative approach. Philosophical Studies, 175, 1217–1241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. (2013). Mindshaping: A new framework for understanding human social cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Funding was provided by Università degli Studi di Milano.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anika Fiebich.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fiebich, A. In defense of pluralist theory. Synthese 198, 6815–6834 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02490-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02490-5

Keywords

Navigation