Skip to main content
Log in

A New Imagery Debate: Enactive and Sensorimotor Accounts

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Traditionally, the “Imagery Debate” has opposed two main camps: depictivism and descriptivism. This debate has essentially focused on the nature of the internal representations thought to be involved in imagery, without addressing at all the question of action. More recently, a third, “embodied” view is moving the debate into a new phase. The embodied approach focuses on the interdependence of perception, cognition and action, and in its more radical line this approach promotes the idea that perception is not a process involving internal world-models (representations). The anti-representationalist version of the embodied paradigm covers, among others that we shall not discuss here, two quite different positions, namely the enactive approach and sensorimotor theory. Up to now these two anti-representationalist accounts have generally been confounded. In this paper we will argue that despite some important commonalities, enactive and sensorimotor accounts come with distinctive theoretical traits with regard to their approach to imagery. These become manifest when critically examining the role they assign to sensorimotor engagements with the world. We shall argue that enactive and sensorimotor approaches are different in their understanding of the role of embodied action, and these different notions of embodiment lead to different explanatory accounts of perception and imagery. We propose that, due to existing ambiguities in enactivism, the sensorimotor theory is a better framework for a skill-based approach to imagery.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We skip a discussion of other anti-representationalist approaches, such as Gibsonian ecological psychology, dynamical systems theory and bahaviour-based artificial intelligence, because they go beyond the scope of the present paper.

  2. One more caveat: although one may be under the impression that imagery and imagination refer to the same mental phenomenon, or that imagery is a subtype of imagination, the link between the two is an open issue. Some (for example White 1990) have stressed their differences, basing their argument on the fact that various mental processes, such as memories, hallucinations, dreams, imagistic beliefs, involve imagery without involving imagination, and that whereas in imagery a subject has minimal control, imagination is under voluntary control. Though we acknowledge the relevance of the topic, it lies beyond the scope of the present paper to discuss the link and differences between the notions of mental imagery and imagination (we refer to Kind 2001 for a thoughtful investigation).

  3. It should be noted that the present-day version of the theory includes reference to oculomotor activity (saccades, fixations and eye scanpaths) as being necessary and functional to the build-up of a depictive image (Mast and Kosslyn 2002), and accommodates a conceptual framework where mental imagery is regarded as a simulation of perceptual behavior (Moulton and Kosslyn 2009).

  4. Alva Noë in his 2004 single-authored book adopts an « enactive » approach and specifies that perception is enactive in that it is constituted by sensorimotor knowledge, namely, practical grasp of the way sensory stimulation changes as a function of movement. What he calls « enactive » approach here is no more and no less than the sensorimotor contingency theory. He borrows the term from Varela et al. (1991), but rightly acknowledges that he may not use it in exactly the same way (see p. 233).

  5. Boundary extension is an instance of false memory, whereby people report having seen parts of a scene that fall outside a picture’s boundaries. For example, when asked to draw from memory a previously displayed picture, people report not only what was actually contained in it, but tend to include details as if the picture had been taken from farther away, thus including more parts of a given object. These ‘errors’ in boundary judgment actually display a very good prediction of how the world really is, and the rapidity and spontaneity with which they occur suggest that sensory information processing embodies spatial expectations resulting from viewpoint shifts.

  6. The idea that the phenomenology of seeing is much less rich than is usually thought is supported by such phenomena as change blindness (Simons and Levin 1997) and inattentional blindness (Mack and Rock 1998).

References

  • Altmann, G.T.M. 2004. Language-mediated eye movements in the absence of a visual world: The “blank screen paradigm”. Cognition 93(2): B79–B87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W. 1999. Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22(4): 577–660.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W. 2008. Grounded cognition. Annual Review of Psychology 59(1): 617–645.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W., W. Kyle Simmons, A.K. Barbey, and C.D. Wilson. 2003. Grounding conceptual knowledge in modality-specific systems. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7(2): 84–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, S.A., and L.W. Stark. 1997. Spontaneous eye movements during visual imagery reflect the content of the visual scene. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 9(1): 27–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. 2009. Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Clark, A. 1997. Being there: putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 2008. Supersizing the mind: embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., and J. Toribio. 1994. Doing without representing. Synthese 101(3): 401–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foglia, L., and R. Grush. 2011. The limitations of a purely enactive (Non-representational) account of imagery. Journal of Consciousness Studies 18(5–6): 35–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fourtassi, M., Hajjioui, A., Urquizar, C., Rossetti, Y., Rode, G., and Pisella, L. 2013. Iterative fragmentation of cognitive maps in a visual imagery task. (F. P. de Lange, Ed.) PLoS ONE 8(7).

  • Gallagher, S. 2005. How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ganis, G., W.L. Thompson, and S.M. Kosslyn. 2004. Brain areas underlying visual mental imagery and visual perception: An fMRI study. Brain Research. Cognitive Brain Research 20(2): 226–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grush, R. 1998. Perception, imagery, and the sensorimotor loop. In A consciousness reader, Eds. Esken, F. and Heckman F.-D. Schoeningh Verlag.

  • Grush, R. 2004. The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery, and perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27(3): 377–396.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hebb, D.O. 1968. Concerning imagery. Psychological Review 75(6): 466–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hesslow, G. 2002. Conscious thought as simulation of behaviour and perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6(6): 242–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hesslow, G. 2012. The current status of the simulation theory of cognition. Brain Research 1428: 71–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hickerson, R. 2007. Perception as knowing how to act: Alva Noë’s action in perception. Philosophical Psychology 20(4): 505–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holšánová, J., B. Hedberg, and N. Nilsson. 1999. Visual and verbal focus patterns when describing pictures. In Current Oculomotor research, ed. W. Becker, H. Deubel, and T. Mergner, 303–304. New York: Springer US.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey, K., and G. Underwood. 2008. Fixation sequences in imagery and in recognition during the processing of pictures of real-world scenes. Journal of Eye Movement Research 2(3): 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D.D., and E. Myin. 2012. Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Intraub, H., and Richardson, M. 1989. Wide-angle memories of close-up scenes. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition 15: 179–187.

  • Johansson, R., and M. Johansson. 2014. Look here, eye movements play a functional role in memory retrieval. Psychological Science 25(1): 236–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, R., Holšánová, J., and Holmqvist, K. 2005. What do eye movements reveal about mental imagery? Evidence from visual and verbal elicitations. Proceedings of the 27th Cognitive Science conference.

  • Johansson, R., J. Holšánová, and K. Holmqvist. 2006. Pictures and spoken descriptions elicit similar Eye movements during mental imagery, both in light and in complete darkness. Cognitive Science 30(6): 1053–1079.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, R., Holšánová, J., and Holmqvist, K. 2010. Eye movements during mental imagery are not reenactments of perception. In Proceedings of the 32nd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, Eds. Ohlsson S. and Catrambone R. Cognitive Science Society.

  • Johansson, R., Holšánová, J., and Holmqvist, K. 2011. The dispersion of eye movements during visual imagery is related to individual differences in spatial imagery ability. In Proceedings of the 33rd Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, 1200–1205. Austin: Cognitive Science Society.

  • Johansson, R., J. Holšánová, R. Dewhurst, and K. Holmqvist. 2012. Eye movements during scene recollection have a functional role, but they are not reinstatements of those produced during encoding. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 38(5): 1289–1314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A. 2001. Putting the image back in imagination. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62(1): 85–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S.M. 1980. Image and mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S. M. 1994. Image and brain. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Kosslyn, S.M. 2005. Mental images and the brain. Cognitive Neuropsychology 22(3): 333–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S.M., N.M. Alpert, W.L. Thompson, V. Maljkovic, S.B. Weise, C.F. Chabris, S.E. Hamilton, et al. 1993. Visual mental imagery activates topographically organized visual cortex: PET investigations. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 5(3): 263–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S.M., W.L. Thompson, I.J. Kim, and N.M. Alpert. 1995. Topographical representations of mental images in primary visual cortex. Nature 378(6556): 496–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S.M., W.L. Thompson, and N.M. Alpert. 1997. Neural systems shared by visual imagery and visual perception: a positron emission tomography study. NeuroImage 6(4): 320–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S.M., A. Pascual-Leone, O. Felician, S. Camposano, J.P. Keenan, W.L. Thompson, G. Ganis, et al. 1999. The role of area 17 in visual imagery: Convergent evidence from PET and rTMS. Science (New York, N.Y.) 284(5411): 167–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S.M., W.L. Thompson, and G. Ganis. 2006. The case for mental imagery, vol. vi. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laeng, B., and D. Teodorescu. 2002. Eye scanpaths during visual imagery reenact those of perception of the same visual scene. Cognitive Science 26(2): 207–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laeng, B., I.M. Bloem, S. D’Ascenzo, and L. Tommasi. 2014. Scrutinizing visual images: The role of gaze in mental imagery and memory. Cognition 131(2): 263–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loughlin, V. 2014. Sensorimotor knowledge and the radical alternative. In Contemporary Sensorimotor Theory, Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, Eds. Bishop J.M. and Martin A.O., 105–116. Springer International Publishing.

  • Mack, A., and I. Rock. 1998. Inattentional blindness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mast, F.W., and S.M. Kosslyn. 2002. Eye movements during visual mental imagery. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6(7): 271–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H.R., and Varela, F.J. 1992. The tree of knowledge: the biological roots of human understanding. Cognition.

  • Moulton, S.T., and S.M. Kosslyn. 2009. Imagining predictions: mental imagery as mental emulation. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Series B, Biological Sciences 364(1521): 1273–1280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U. 1967. Cognitive psychology. East Norwalk: Appleton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. 2004. Action in perception. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. 2006. Experience without the head. In Perceptual experience, ed. T. Gendler and J. Hawthorne, 411–433. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. 2010. Vision Without Representation. In N. Gangopadhyay, M. Madary, & F. Spicer (Eds.), Perception, Action, and Consciousness: Sensorimotor Dynamics and Two Visual Systems, 245–256. Oup Oxford.

  • Noë, A. 2012. Varieties of presence. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Noton, D., and L. Stark. 1971a. Scanpaths in eye movements during pattern perception. Science (New York, N.Y.) 171(3968): 308–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noton, D., and L. Stark. 1971b. Scanpaths in saccadic eye movements while viewing and recognizing patterns. Vision Research 11(9): 929–942.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J.K. 2011. Why red doesn’t sound like a bell: understanding the feel of consciousness, 1st ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J. K., and N. Block. 2012. Discussion of J. Kevin O’Regan’s “Why Red Doesn’t Sound Like a Bell: Understanding the Feel of Consciousness.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(1): 89–108.

  • O’Regan, J.K., and A. Noë. 2001. A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24(05): 939–973.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z.W. 1981. The imagery debate: Analog media vs. Tacit knowledge. Psychological Review 88: 16–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z.W. 2002. Mental imagery: In search of a theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25(2): 157–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z.W. 2003. Seeing and visualizing: It’s not what you think. Cambridge: A Bradford Book.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. 2009. The concept of mind: 60th anniversary edition. London: Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. 2010. Embodied cognition. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, D.J., and D.T. Levin. 1997. Change blindness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 1(1): 241–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spivey, M.J., and J.J. Geng. 2001. Oculomotor mechanisms activated by imagery and memory: eye movements to absent objects. Psychological Research 65(4): 235–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spivey, M.J., M.J. Tyler, D.C. Richardson, and E.E. Young. 2000. Eye movements during comprehension of spoken scene descriptions. Proceedings of the 22nd annual conference of the cognitive science society, 487–492. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, N.J.T. 1999. Are theories of imagery theories of imagination? An active perception approach to conscious mental content. Cognitive Science 23(2): 207–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, N.J.T. 2003. New support for the perceptual activity theory of mental imagery. Resource document : http://www.imagery-imagination.com/newsupa.htm

  • Thomas, N.J.T. 2009. Visual imagery and consciousness. In Encyclopedia of Consciousness, Ed. W. P. Banks.

  • Thomas, N.J.T. 2010. Imagery and the coherence of imagination. Journal of Philosophical Research 22: 95–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, N. J. T. 2014). Mental imagery. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Ed. E.N. Zalta. Resource document : http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/mental-imagery/

  • Thompson, E. 2007. Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E., and F.J. Varela. 2001. Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 5(10): 418–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., E. Thompson, and E. Rosch. 1991. The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, A.R. 1990. The language of imagination. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors acknowledge the support of Advanced grant ERC FEEL number 323674. ​The Authors also wish to thank two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lucia Foglia.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Foglia, L., O’Regan, J.K. A New Imagery Debate: Enactive and Sensorimotor Accounts. Rev.Phil.Psych. 7, 181–196 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0269-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0269-9

Keywords

Navigation