Skip to main content
Log in

Disagreement or denialism? “Invasive species denialism” and ethical disagreement in science

  • S.I.: Disagreement in Science
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recently, invasion biologists have argued that some of the skepticism expressed in the scientific and lay literatures about the risks of invasive species and other aspects of the consensus within invasion biology is a kind of science denialism. This paper presents an argument that, while some claims made by skeptics of invasion biology share important features with paradigm cases of science denialism, others express legitimate ethical concerns that, even if one disagrees, should not be dismissed as denialist. Further, this case illustrates a more general point about ethical disagreement within sciences like invasion biology that constitutively pursue non-epistemic goals and values. While philosophers of science have argued that epistemic disagreement within science can be productive as heterogeneous epistemic communities “hedge their bets,” the case of invasion biology shows how non-epistemic or ethical disagreement within sciences, while carrying significant risks, can also be epistemically and non-epistemically valuable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this paper I use “value-laden” to mean “non-epistemically value-laden.” While I tend to agree with the philosophers of science who argue that the distinction between epistemic values related to knowledge and its production, and non-epistemic values, i.e. ethical, political, aesthetic, and other values, is difficult to strictly maintain (Longino 1996), I use the distinction here in the way identified by Douglas (2000), namely to “serve to remind us which goals the values primarily serve within a particular context.” (560)

  2. The literature on disagreement in analytic epistemology usually distinguishes disagreement about belief from disagreement about action, focusing on the former (Frances and Matheson 2018). Here the distinction between epistemic and non-epistemic disagreement is put in terms of belief disagreement, recognizing that both are clearly relevant to action disagreement.

  3. Sometimes native species that are weeds are pests are colloquially labeled ‘invasive,’ but the scientific literature generally does not follow this usage.

  4. An analysis of the source and recipient ecosystems of over 13,000 plants that have been introduced showed that “patterns of naturalization have largely followed historical colonial links between continents (van Kleunen et al. 2015).” (Buckley and Catford 2016, p. 5)

  5. In her exploration of “bullshit at the interface of science and policy,” Douglas (2006) discusses some of these tactics, particularly cherry-picking, or the “bullshit of the isolated fact,” where denialists rely on the complexities of scientific evidence to present individual facts that mislead non-experts about the consensus but are not strictly false; and the “bullshit of universal standards,” where denialists claim that the consensus does not meet a (non-existent) “universal” standard of proof for scientific claims.

  6. Ecologist critics Davis and Chew (2017) go further, claiming that “[c]onstructing an ostensible category of ‘denialists’ reflects invasion biology’s traditional reliance on inflammatory exaggeration to impose and enforce a dichotomous doctrine,” (229) and invasion biologists claiming denialism may be “trying to shore up their dwindling authority over an obsolescent endeavor.” (230)

  7. Heneghan is responding to environmental journalist Fred Pearce’s (2015) recent book The New Wild, which argues on the basis of possible benefits of introduced species that rather than harming nature, these species “may be nature’s salvation.” His evidence includes the fact that many invasive plants, e.g. knotweed (Fallopia japonica), which is considered a destructive invasive plant by Britain’s Environment Agency and an invasive plant in several US states, thrive in areas disturbed by human activity, especially urban settings. Indeed, it is known to invade urban, but also rural and riparian, sites, forming dense colonies that exclude other vegetation (Simberloff 2015). Even if one believed that quickly invading disturbed sites (or the plant’s edibility) are possible benefits, these should be placed in a broader context of other impacts, including damage to infrastructure and crowding out other plants.

  8. These concerns have arisen in popular culture; for example, the relationship between cultural perceptions of so-called “Africanized bees” (invasive hybrids of European and African honeybee species that have spread in the southeastern US and killed over 1000 humans) and anti-black racism in the United States is briefly explored in Michael Moore’s 2002 film Bowling for Columbine. The fact that these aggressive bees were labeled “Africanized,” as opposed to some other possible label (e.g. “invasive hybrid honeybees”), is obviously concerning for opponents of anti-black racism in the US.

  9. Jensen wrote, “The gardens that I created myself shall…be in harmony with their landscape environment and the racial characteristics of its inhabitants. They shall express the spirit of America and therefore shall be free of foreign character as far as possible. The Latin and the Oriental crept and creeps more and more over our land, coming from the South, which is settled by Latin people, and also from other centers of mixed masses of immigrants. The Germanic character of our cities and settlements was overgrown…Latin spirit has spoiled a lot and still spoils things every day.” (Quoted by Gould 1998, p. 4)

  10. For example, Davis and Chew (2017): “Perhaps they take others improving on their science as a personal affront, and feel compelled to respond with name-calling.” (230)

References

  • Alberti, M., Marzluff, J., Shulenberger, E., Bradley, G., Ryan, C., & Zumbrunnen, C. (2003). Integrating humans into ecology: Opportunities and challenges for studying urban ecosystems. BioScience, 53, 1169–1179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, H. G., & Stebbins, G. L. (Eds.). (1965). The genetics of colonizing species. In Proceedings of the international union of biological sciences. New York: Academic Press.

  • Bellard, C., Cassey, P., & Blackburn, T. M. (2016). Alien species as a driver of recent extinctions. Biological Letters, 12, 20150623.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biddle, J. B., & Leuschner, A. (2015). Climate skepticism and the manufacture of doubt: Can dissent in science be epistemically detrimental? European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 5(3), 261–278.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, T. M., Essl, F., Evans, T., Hulme, P. E., Jeschke, J. M., et al. (2014). A unified classification of alien species based on the magnitude of their environmental impacts. PLoS Biology, 12(5), e1001850.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44(4), 542–573.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J., & Sax, D. (2004). An essay on some topics concerning invasive species. Austral Ecology, 29, 530–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckley, Y. M., & Catford, J. (2016). Does the biogeographic origin of species matter? Ecological effects of native and non-native species and the use of origin to guide management. Journal of Ecology, 104, 4–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chew, M. K. (2011). Anekeitaxonomy: Botany, place, and belonging. In D. Rotherham & R. A. Lambert (Eds.), Invasive and introduced plants and animals: Human perceptions, attitudes, and approaches to management. Washington, DC: Earthscan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chew, M. K. (2015). Ecologists, environmentalists, experts, and the invasion of the ‘second greatest threat’. International Review of Environmental History, 1, 17–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chew, M. K., & Hamilton, A. (2011). The rise and fall of biotic nativeness: A historical perspective. In D. M. Richardson (Ed.), Fifty years of invasion ecology: The legacy of Charles Elton. New York, NJ, Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, H. (2006). Invasion biology: Critique of a pseudoscience by David Theodoropoulos. Western North American Naturalist, 66(4), 537–539.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clavero, M., & Garcia-Berthou, E. (2005). Invasive species are a leading cause of animal extinctions. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 20(3), 110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coates, P. (2006). American perceptions of immigrant and invasive species. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colautti, R. I., & Richardson, D. M. (2009). Subjectivity and flexibility in invasion terminology: Too much of a good thing? Biological Invasions, 11(6), 1225–1229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cronon, W. (1995). The trouble with wilderness; or, getting back to the wrong nature. In W. Cronon (Ed.), Uncommon ground: Rethinking the human place in nature (pp. 69–90). New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowley, S. L., Hinchliffe, S., Redpath, S. M., & McDonald, R. A. (2017). Disagreement about invasive species does not equate to denialism: A response to Russell and Blackburn. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 32(4), 228–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, M. A. (2006). Invasion biology 1958–2005: The pursuit of science and conservation. In M. W. Cadotte, S. M. McMahon, & T. Fukami (Eds.), Conceptual ecology and invasion biology (pp. 35–64). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, M. A. (2009). Invasion biology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, M. A., & Chew, M. K. (2017). ‘The denialists are coming!’ Well, not exactly: A response to Russell and Blackburn. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 32(4), 229–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, M. A., et al. (2011). Don’t judge species on their origins. Nature, 474, 153–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Cruz, H., & De Smedt, J. (2013). The value of epistemic disagreement in scientific practice. The case of Homo floresiensis. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 44, 169–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Melo-Martín, I., & Intemann, K. (2018). The fight against doubt: How to bridge the gap between scientists and the public. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dellsén, F. (2018). When expert disagreement supports the consensus. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 96(1), 142–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diethelm, P., & McKee, M. (2009). Denialism: What is it and how should scientists respond? European Journal of Public Health, 19(1), 2–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2000). Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 67(4), 559–579.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2006). Bullshit at the interface of science and policy: Global warming, toxic substances, and other pesky problems. In H. Reisch (Ed.), Bullshit and philosophy (pp. 213–226). Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2016). Values in science. In P. Humphreys (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowie, M. (2003). Conservation refugees. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. C. (2009). The ethical significance of language in the environmental sciences: Case studies from pollution research. Ethics, Place, and Environment, 12(2), 157–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. C. (2011). Is a little pollution good for you? Incorporating societal values in environmental research. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. C., & McKaughan, D. J. (2014). Nonepistemic values and the multiple goals of science. Philosophy of Science, 81, 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. C., & Richards, T. (Eds.). (2017). Exploring inductive risk: Case studies of values in science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elton, C. C. (1958). The ecology of invasions by animals and plants. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frances, B., & Matheson, J. (2018). Disagreement. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2018 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/disagreement/.

  • Frank, D. M. (2017). Ethics of the scientist qua policy advisor: Inductive risk, uncertainty, and catastrophe in climate economics. Synthese, S.I.: Evidence Amalgamation in the Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1617-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1998). An evolutionary perspective on strengths, fallacies, and confusions in the concept of native plants. Arnoldia, 58(1), 3–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gröning, G., & Wolschke-Bulmahn, J. (1992). Some notes on the mania for native plants in Germany. Landscape Journal, 11, 116–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guha, R. (1989). Radical American environmentalism and wilderness preservation: A third world critique. Environmental Ethics, 11(1), 71–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guiaşu, R. C., & Tindale, C. W. (2018). Logical fallacies and invasion biology. Biology and Philosophy, 33, 34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurevitch, J., & Padilla, D. K. (2004). Are invasive species a major cause of extinction? Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 19, 470–474.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heneghan, L. (2015). Is there a need for ‘The New Wild’? The new ecological quarrels. Los Angeles Review of Books. https://lareviewofbooks.org/article/is-there-need-for-the-new-wild-the-new-ecological-quarrels/. Accessed October 1, 2018.

  • Hobbs, R. J., Higgs, E., & Harris, J. A. (2009). Novel ecosystems: Implications for conservation and restoration. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 24(11), 599–605.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubbell, S. P. (2001). The unified neutral theory of biodiversity and biogeography. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inkpen, S. A. (2017). Are humans disturbing conditions in ecology? Biology and Philosophy, 32, 51–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kareiva, P., & Mariver, M. (2012). What is conservation science? BioScience, 62(11), 962–969.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingma, E. (2007). What is it to be healthy? Analysis, 67(294), 128–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1990). The division of cognitive labor. Journal of Philosophy, 87, 5–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larson, B. M. H. (2005). The war of the roses: Demilitarizing invasion biology. Frontiers in Ecology and the Environment, 3(9), 495–500.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lodge, D., & Shrader-Frechette, K. (2003). Nonindigenous species: Ecological explanation, environmental ethics, and public policy. Conservation Biology, 17(1), 31–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Long, G. (2011). Disagreement and responses to climate change. Environmental Values, 20(4), 503–525.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1996). Cognitive and non-cognitive values in science: Rethinking the dichtomy. In L. H. Nelson & J. Nelson (Eds.), Feminism, science, and the philosophy of science (pp. 39–58). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacDougall, A. S., & Turkington, R. (2005). Are invasive species the drivers or passengers of change in degraded ecosystems? Ecology, 86(1), 42–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murcia, C., Aronson, J., Kattan, G. H., Moreno-Mateos, D., Dixon, K., & Simberloff, D. (2014). A critique of the ‘novel ecosystem’ concept. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 29(10), 548–553.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Invasive Species Council (NISC), Beck, G., Zimmerman, K., Schardt, J. D., Stone, J., Lukens, R. R., Reichard, S., et al. (2006). Invasive species defined in a policy context: Recommendations from the federal invasive species advisory committee. Invasive Plant Science and Management, 1(4), 414–421.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, N., & Conway, E. M. (2010). Merchants of doubt: How a handful of scientists obscured the truth on issues from tobacco smoke to global warming. New York: Bloomsbury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, F. (2015). The new wild: Why invasive species will be nature’s salvation. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Purdy, J. (2015). Environmentalism’s racist history. The New Yorker, August 13. https://www.newyorker.com/news/news-desk/environmentalisms-racist-history. Accessed October 3, 2018.

  • Raffles, H. (2011). Mother nature’s melting pot. New York Times, April 2, 2011.

  • Rawls, J. (1996). Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricciardi, A., Blackburn, T. M., Clarton, J. T., Dick, J. T. A., Hulme, P. E., Iacarella, J. C., et al. (2017). Invasion science: A horizon scan of emerging challenges and opportunities. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 34, 464–474.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricciardi, A., & Ryan, R. (2018a). The exponential growth of invasive species denialism. Biological Invasions, 20, 549–553.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricciardi, A., & Ryan, R. (2018b). Invasive species denialism revisited: Response to Sagoff. Biological Invasions, 20(10), 2731–2738.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, J. C., & Blackburn, T. M. (2017). The rise of invasive species denialism. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 32(1), 3–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sagoff, M. (1999). What’s wrong with exotic species? Philosophy & Public Policy Quarterly, 19(4), 16–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sagoff, M. (2005). Do non-native species threaten the natural environment? Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 18(3), 215–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sagoff, M. (2009a). Environmental harm: Political not biological. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 22, 81–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sagoff, M. (2009b). Who is the invader? Alien species, property rights, and the police power. Social Philosophy and Policy, 26(2), 26–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sagoff, M. (2018). What is invasion biology? Ecological Economics, 154, 22–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shamoo, A., & Resnik, D. (2015). Responsible conduct of research (3rd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, K. (2001). Non-indigenous species and ecological explanation. Biology and Philosophy, 16, 507–519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D. (2003). Confronting introduced species: A form of xenophobia? Biological Invasions, 5, 179–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D. (2004). Invasion biology. Critique of a pseudoscience. D.I. Theodoropoulos, Avvar Books, 2003. Ecological Economics, 48(3), 360–362.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D. (2005a). Non-native species do threaten the natural environment! Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 18, 595–607.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D. (2005b). The politics of assessing risk for biological invasions: The USA as a case study. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 20(5), 216–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D. (2012). Nature, natives, nativism, and management: Worldviews underlying controversies in invasion biology. Environmental Ethics, 34, 5–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D. (2013). Invasive species: What everyone needs to know. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D. (2014). Biological invasions: What’s worth fighting and what can be won? Ecological Engineering, 65, 112–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D. (2015). Nature’s nature and the place of non-native species. Current Biology, 25, R588–R591.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D., Martin, J., Genovesi, P., Maris, V., Wardle, D. A., Aronson, J., et al. (2013). Impacts of biological invasions: What’s what and the way forward. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 28(1), 58–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D., Souza, L., Nunez, M. A., Noelia Barrios-Garcia, M., & Bunn, W. (2012). The natives are restless, but not often and mostly when disturbed. Ecology, 93(3), 598–607.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D., et al. (2011). Non-natives: 141 scientists object. Nature, 475, 36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soulé, M. (1985). What is conservation biology? BioScience, 35, 737–744.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steele, K. (2012). The scientist qua policy advisor makes value judgment. Philosophy of Science, 79, 893–904.

    Google Scholar 

  • Subramaniam, B. (2001). The aliens have landed! Reflections on the rhetoric of biological invasions. Meridians, 2(1), 26–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takacs, D. (1996). The idea of biodiversity: Philosophies of paradise. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Theodoropoulos, D. I. (2003). Invasion biology: Critique of a pseudoscience. Blythe, CA: Avvar Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, K. (2014). Where do camels belong? The story and science of invasive species. London: Profile Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Driesche, R., Simberloff, D., Blossey, B., Causton, C., Hoddle, M., Marks, C., et al. (Eds.). (2016). Integrating biological control into conservation practice. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Kleunen, M., Dawson, W., Essl, F., Pergl, J., Winter, M., Weber, E., et al. (2015). Global exchange and accumulation of non-native plants. Nature, 525, 100–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warren, R. J., II, King, J. R., Tarsa, C., Haas, B., & Henderson, J. (2017). A systematic review of context bias in invasion biology. PLoS ONE, 12(8), e0182502.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webb, D. A. (1985). What are the criteria for presuming native status? Watsonia, 15, 231–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M., & Muldoon, R. (2009). Epistemic landscapes and the division of cognitive labor. Philosophy of Science, 76(2), 225–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilcove, D. S., Rothstein, D., Dubow, J., Phillips, A., & Losos, E. (1988). Quantifying threats to imperiled species in the United States. BioScience, 48, 607–615.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, A. M., & Larson, B. M. H. (2011). Clarifying debates in invasion biology: A survey of invasion biologists. Environmental Research, 111, 893–898.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Special thanks to ecologists Dan Simberloff and Christy Leppanen for the opportunity to participate in research on invasive species, for many lively conversations, and comments on the manuscript. Thanks also to Dale Jamieson, Jennifer Jacquet, members of the Department of Philosophy at the University of Tennessee, and two anonymous referees for constructive comments and criticisms.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David M. Frank.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Frank, D.M. Disagreement or denialism? “Invasive species denialism” and ethical disagreement in science. Synthese 198 (Suppl 25), 6085–6113 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02259-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02259-w

Keywords

Navigation