Academia.eduAcademia.edu
WHY IT IS ETHICAL TO EAT MEAT Danny Frederick http://independent.academia.edu/DannyFrederick The ethics of meat-eating may concern the activity itself, the plight of animals, or the wider environment. The activity itself seems ethical. Meat is nutritious and many people enjoy eating it. Admittedly, some dour types seem to think that it is wrong for people to enjoy themselves. But they are surely mistaken. Ethics is about living well. Enjoying one’s life, and enjoying one’s food, is an important part of living well. Does meat-eating violate our duties to (non-human) animals? If the animals we eat had a right to life, then it would be wrong to kill them for their meat, just as it is wrong to kill an innocent human. However, rights are the sorts of things that can be claimed, exercised, waived and traded. Such activities are beyond the capacities of animals. Further, rights involve reciprocity: if I have rights which others have a duty to respect, then I have a duty to respect the rights of others. But animals cannot understand rights and duties. To hold them to account for behaviour which infringes the rights of others would be, not only absurd, but cruel. The absence of animal rights means that there are no duties that we owe to them. But there are still duties we have with regard to them in virtue of their sentient and purposive nature. Eating meat has some adverse consequences for animals: annually, billions of animals are slaughtered, often when they are young because the quality of their meat deteriorates with age. But there are other consequences too. Animals in the wild often struggle to find food and are in constant fear of predators. If they are not ripped apart by a carnivore they are often killed more slowly by parasites or bacteria. Top predators often suffer a lingering and painful death when old age, disease or injury renders them unable to get food. Animals on farms are spared such suffering. On the better farms, animals live comfortably among their natural companions, are well-fed, protected from predators, cared for when disease afflicts them and, ultimately, killed humanely. Further, the vast majority of animals that are slaughtered for food would not have existed at all if they had not been bred for their meat. So, even if they are killed young, they have had a life that they would not otherwise have had. With respect to the animals, therefore, meat-eating is not unethical on the grounds either of rights or of consequences. Of course, there are abuses in farming, as in any human activity. But that does not show that eating meat, or the farming on which it depends, is inherently wrong. It shows only that that we have a duty to rectify abuses. Parental child abuse, for example, does not show that raising children is unethical. From a global viewpoint, there are concerns about the sustainability of meat-eating. Feeding farm animals consumes substantial resources, including water (which is becoming increasingly scarce). As world population grows, so does the demand for food; and as people get richer, they tend to eat more meat. If these trends continue, some predict environmental disaster. But if this is so, it does not show that eating meat is unethical as such. At most, it shows that meat-eating is ethically problematic in the context of growth in population and in wealth. Indeed, it shows only that widespread and frequent meat-eating is problematic in that context. But any normally ethical activity can become problematic in a particular context. For example, raising children would become problematic, and might have to be limited, in an unsustainable population explosion. Eating meat from non-abusive farms is therefore ethical, even if resource scarcity sets ethical limits to its prevalence or frequency.