Skip to main content
Log in

What Experience Cannot Teach Us About Time

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Does the A-theory have an intuitive advantage over the B-theory? Many A-theorists have claimed so, arguing that their theory has a much better explanation for the fact that we all experience the passage of time: we experience time as passing because time really does pass. In this paper I expose and reject the argument behind the A-theorist’s claim. I argue that all parties have conceded far too easily that there is an experience that needs explaining in the first place. For what exactly is an experience of temporal passage? One natural thought is that we experience passage in virtue of experiencing change, or in virtue of experiencing change as ‘dynamic’. Another is that we experience passage in virtue of experiencing events as (successively) present. None of these experiences, I argue, amounts to an experience of passage. Although there might still be other ways to experience passage, A-theorists would have to provide us with a plausible candidate experience. If there is such an experience at all, it won’t be one that qualifies as what we intuitively take to be an experience of passage. The ‘intuitive advantage’, it seems, has dissolved in any case.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Among others, there is the classic argument that change requires temporal passage, inspired by McTaggart’s view (1908, 1927) (although McTaggart ultimately rejects temporal passage). Some may argue that temporal passage is reflected in the tensed structure of language. A further argument is found in Prior’s paper ‘Thank Goodness That’s Over’ (1959), where he argues that we need the passage of time to make sense of our emotional attitudes towards events.

  2. Not all dynamic theories would be entirely happy with this characterisation but it suffices to give a first intuitive grasp of the phenomenon I am concerned with.

  3. For defence of the A-theory and tense realism see among others: Bigelow (1996), Broad (1938), Markosian (2004), Smith (1993), Schlesinger (1991), Zimmerman (2005), Crisp (2005, 2007), Prior (1958, 1967, 1968a, b), Tallant (2009, 2010, forthcoming), Zeilicovici (1981). For the distinction between tense realism and A-theory see (Percival 2002).

  4. B-theorists include Le Poidevin (1996, 1998), Le Poidevin and Mellor 1987), Mellor (1981, 1998), Oaklander (1991, 1993, 2002, 2004), Quine (1960), Reichenbach (1947), Russell (1914, 1940, 1948), Smart (1949, 1955), Smith (1993), Williams (1951). Not all B-theorists think of themselves as static theorists. Oaklander (2012) and Maudlin (2002) defend a B-theoretic account of temporal passage according to which time is inherently dynamic just by virtue of the fact that it features a sequence of different events (Oaklander) and/or has a privileged direction (Maudlin). This is not the sense of passage the dynamic theorist has in mind.

  5. To my mind, the only philosophers who have denied that we experience temporal passage (although for different reasons than me) are Prosser (2012, 2007) and Deng. Dainton comes close to arguing that we do not experience passage in (Dainton 2011).

  6. I will sometimes use ‘experience’ as a shorthand for ‘visual perceptual experience’.

  7. Le Poidevin’s argument actually refers to a bundle of arguments. I have taken his label to identify what I take to be the most important one.

  8. The objection can also be understood in a more general way. The doubt then seems to be whether we can, in principle, ever know whether a certain explanation is the best explanation for some explanandum. But although we might strictly speaking never be in the position to know whether an explanation is really the best explanation, it does not mean that it could not actually be the best explanation. My thanks to Fiona Macpherson who brought my attention to this point.

  9. Philosophers who have argued along these lines include Le Poidevin (1991), Oaklander (1993), Mellor (1998), and Paul (2010).

  10. Le Poidevin does not defend the view—he is merely describing an intuitive pre-philosophical assumption that most of us share.

  11. By ‘ordinary change’ I mean all changes that objects can undergo apart from the change that constitutes temporal passage. When I just say ‘change’ I refer to ordinary change, unless otherwise indicated. I am not implying that all ordinary changes can be perceived. Mere Cambridge changes are presumably not perceivable and that they are included under the label ‘ordinary change’ might sound strange. However, the term ‘ordinary change’ is mainly chosen to separate the change that uniquely constitutes temporal passage from all other changes.

  12. Strictly speaking it is not true that we only perceive what is momentarily present. In fact, all we ever perceive is the past, due to the time lag in perceptual experience. The point is, however, that we only ever perceive what was present, but we do not perceive more than what was present at the time when the light was emitted from the object we are currently perceiving. Our awareness, it seems, is restricted to what happens at a time, and cannot ‘take in’ what occurs over time. It is natural to assume that when a perceptual stimulus takes n seconds to reach us at a time t, then we are perceptually aware of what happens at time t-n, but not of anything that happened before or after t-n. For ease of reading I shall stick with the less precise formulation that we are only ever perceptually aware of what is present.

  13. Philosophers who have denied that we can, strictly speaking, have perceptual experiences of change include Mabbott (1951, 1955), Dennett (1991), Mellor (1998), Le Poidevin (2007), Kelly (2005), and Plumer (1985).

  14. Specious present theories of various types have been among others defended by James (1890), Broad (1938), Foster (1982), Dainton (2000) and Tye (2003). For a good overview of the temporal perception debate, see Dainton (2008).

  15. The term ‘connected’ has been suggested to me by Craig French.

  16. I am much indebted to Thomas Brouwer and Craig French for discussion on this point.

  17. All qualitatively distinct events are also numerically distinct, although the converse does not necessarily hold.

  18. Standardly, change is taken to occur over time, but some people think that changes are instantaneous (Priest 2006). However, even if change was instantaneous, it could not occur in a world without duration. If there is nothing that changes, nothing that is different now from how it was before, there cannot be change. Moreover, even if change was instantaneous, we would not experience it as instantaneous. When a traffic light changes from red to green, for example, we do not experience that the light is simultaneously red and green, we experience that the light is first red and then green, that is, we experience the change as occurring over time. In experience, a’s change from F to G always takes time, whether or not there is a moment of change. Note however that this does not imply that our experiences would be illusory if Priest was correct.

  19. Although change looks like succession in experience, not all successions look like change. To experience succession as change, at least the properties or the objects constitutive of the successive events must differ. A mere numerical change of events cannot be experienced as change, which is presumably why it is standardly thought that we could not be aware of time without being aware of (at least mental) change.

  20. See also Shoemaker for this point (1969). Shoemaker thinks that the fact that we measure time by observing change makes it plausible that there cannot be time without change, for to hold otherwise is to be sceptic about the possibility of measuring time at all. Whether or not there could be time without change shall not be my concern here.

  21. I come back to this in §5.

  22. See for example Dretske (1995), Tye (2000) and Byrne (2001).

  23. See for example Block (1990).

  24. Laurie Paul was discussing (and ultimately rejecting) a similar view in her talk ‘Experience and the Direction of Time’ at the Workshop ‘Temporal Experience’ for the Network of Sensory Research in Toronto 2013.

  25. Le Poidevin mentions this view (Le Poidevin 2007, p. 77), but it is also discussed among others by Mellor (1981, 1998), Callender (2008) and Prosser (2007).

  26. A similar example is found in Mellor (1998), Le Poidevin (2007) and Hestevold (1990).

  27. Skow refers to Hestevold (1990).

  28. A similar point could be made about future events. If we were able to see the future, we would still represent it as present. Mellor has an example of this sort involving a magic crystal ball. Whatever future scene is presented to you in the magic ball, it still looks present to you. But we could not conclude from this that it is present (Mellor 1998, p. 16).

  29. Le Poidevin makes a similar point (2007, p. 78).

  30. See also Hestevold (1990, p. 542), Le Poidevin (2007), (Paul 2010) on the same point.

  31. Fiona Macpherson brought this point to my attention.

  32. Fine writes for example: ‘Even if presentness is allowed to shed its light upon the world there is nothing in [this] metaphysics to prevent that light from being ‘frozen’ on a particular moment of time. (Fine 2005: 287).

  33. I insert the ‘all things considered even’ clause because one might think that if there are other things than the occurrence or lack of passage which differ between a static and a dynamic world, than these might also be factors in explaining the experience. In that case, the fact that time passes would not necessarily be the best explanation for the experience that time passes. Analogously with A-presentness. Many thanks to Alexander Skiles for making this point.

  34. Note, though, that (BestEx) is not a sufficient condition for an experience to be best explained by time’s passage, for an illusion or hallucination of temporal passage could not be accurate in a static world either. The AfE/AfP defender also needs to say that an explanation that takes experiences to be veridical is generally a better explanation than one that resorts to illusions and hallucinations.

  35. Strictly speaking, these experiences would be illusory, due to the time lag in experience. According to Butterfield though, we can almost always ignore the temporal delay. If the process of observation is reliable, and the object is not (much) more than 1,000 m away, we can learn about the observed object’s state at the time when we judge it, not only at a previous time. This is not only due to the fact that the time lag is very short (Butterfield suggests ‘half a second’) but also because solid objects change very infrequently. (1984, p. 163).

  36. Note that the analogous move is not open to the B-theorist in the case of the original argument AfE: That time does not pass cannot be the best explanation for one’s experience as of events undergoing A-change for if time did not pass, there could not be A-change.

  37. Hoerl (2009), Oaklander (1991) and Russell (1915) are among those which have explicitly denied that perceptual experiences should be described as having tensed content. Oaklander has since changed his mind about this, as evident in his article in this very volume.

  38. I attempt to show as much in (Frischhut 2012).

  39. This paper has developed from my thesis, which has been financed by the Swiss National Science Foundation. I am indebted to many people who helped me to improve it. Among these are Fiona Macpherson, Fabrice Correia, Jonathan Lowe, Robin Le Poidevin, Barry Dainton, Kevin Mulligan and the eidos group in Geneva. I am especially grateful for fruitful discussions with Jan Almäng, Thomas Brouwer, Clare Mac Cumhaill, Natalja Deng, Craig French, Ghislain Guigon, Graham Peebles and Alex Skiles.

References

  • Bigelow J (1996) Presentism and properties. Philos Perspect 10:35–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Block Ned (1990) Inverted earth. Philos Perspect 4:53–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broad CD (1938) An examination of McTaggart’s philosophy, vol II. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield J (1984) Seeing the present. Mind 93(370):161–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne Alex (2001) Intentionalism defended. Philos Rev 110(2):199–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callender Craig (2008) The common now. Philos Issues 18(1):339–361

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp Thomas M (2005) Presentism and “cross-time” relations. Am Philos Q 42(1):5–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp TM (2007) Presentism and the grounding objection. Noûs 41(1):90–109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton BF (2000) Stream of consciousness: unity and continuity in conscious experience. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dainton Barry (2008) The experience of time and change. Philos Compass 3(4):619–638

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton B (2010) Temporal consciousness. In: Zalta EN The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

  • Dainton B (2011) Time, passage and immediate experience. In: Callender C (ed) Oxford handbook of philosophy of time. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Deng N forthcoming. Our experience of passage on the B-Theory. Erkenntnis:1–14

  • Dennett DC (1991) Consciousness explained. Penguin, Harmondsworth

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1995) Naturalizing the mind. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine K (2005) Modality and tense. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foster J (1982) The case for idealism. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Frischhut Akiko (2012) The experience of temporal passage. University of Geneva/University of Glasgow, Geneva

    Google Scholar 

  • Hestevold HS (1990) Passage and the presence of experience. Philos Phenomenol Res 50(3):537–552

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoerl Christoph (2009) Time and tense in perceptual experience. Philos Impr 9(12):1–18

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1890) The principles of psychology. Dover, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly SD (2005) The puzzle of temporal experience. In: Brook A (ed) Cognition and the brain: the philosophy and neuroscience movement. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Poidevin R (1991) Change, cause and contradiction. Macmillan, Basingstoke

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Poidevin R (1996) The new theory of time. Int Philos Q 36(1):111–112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Poidevin R (1998) Questions of time and tense. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Poidevin R (2007) The images of time: an essay on temporal representation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Le Poidevin, R (2011) The experience and perception of time. In Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy

  • Le Poidevin R, Mellor DH (1987) Time, change, and the `indexical fallacy’. Mind 96(384):534–538

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mabbott JD (1951) Our direct experience of time. Mind 60(April):153–167

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mabbott JD (1955) The specious present. Mind 64(July):376–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markosian N (2004) A defence of presentism. In: Zimmerman D (ed) Oxford studies in metaphysics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin T (2002) Remarks on the passing of time. Proc Aristot Soc 102(3):237–252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin T (2007) The metaphysics within physics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McTaggart JME (1908) The unreality of time. Mind 17(68):457–474

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McTaggart JME (1927) The nature of existence. Vol. II. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor DH (1981) Real time. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor DH (1998) Real time II. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oaklander LN (1991) A defence of the new tenseless theory of time. Philos Q 41(162):26–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oaklander LN (1993) On the experience of tenseless time. J Philos Res 18:159–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oaklander LN (2002) Presentism, ontology and temporal experience. R Inst Philos Suppl 50:73–90

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oaklander LN (2004) Absolute becoming and the myth of passage. Philo 7(1):36–46

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oaklander LN (2012) A, B- and R-theories of time: a debate. In: Barton A (ed) The future of the philosophy of time. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul LA (2010) Temporal experience. J Philos 107(7):333–359

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke C (1992) A study of concepts. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Percival P (2002) A presentist’s refutation of Mellor’s McTaggart. R Inst Philos Suppl 50:91–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plumer G (1985) The myth of the specious present. Mind 94(January):19–35

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price H (1997) Time’s arrow and archimedes’ point: new directions for the physics of time. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Priest G (2006) In contradiction: a study of the transconsistent. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prior AN (1958) Time after time. Mind 67(266):244–246

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior AN (1959) Thank goodness that’s over. Philosophy 34(128):12–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior AN (1967) Past present and future. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prior AN (1968a) Changes in events and changes in things. In: Papers on time and tense. Clarendon Press, Oxford

  • Prior AN (1968b) Now. Noûs 2(2):101–119

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prosser S (2007) Could we experience the passage of time? Ratio 20(1):75–90

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prosser S (2012) Why Does Time Seem to Pass? Philos Phenomenol Res 85(1):92–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WV (1960) Word and object. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach H (1947) Elements of symbolic logic. Dover, Macmillan Co

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1914) Our knowledge of the external world: as a field for scientific method in philosophy. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1915) On the experience of time. Monist 25(2):212–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1940) An inquiry into meaning and truth. W.W. Norton & Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1948) Human knowledge: its scope and limits. George Allen & Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlesinger GN (1991) E pur si muove. Philos Q 41(165):427–441

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schuster MM (1986) Is the flow of time subjective? Rev Metaphys 39(4):695–714

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S (1969) Time without change. J Philos 66(12):363–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel Susanna (2010) Do visual experiences have contents. In: Nanay B (ed) Perceiving the world. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Skow B (2011) Experience and the passage of time. Philos Perspect 25(1):359–387

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart JJC (1949) The river of time. Mind 58(232):483–494

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart JJC (1955) Spatialising time. Mind 64(254):239–241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith Q (1993) Language and time. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tallant J (2009) Presentism and truth-making. Erkenntnis 71(3):407–416

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tallant J (2010) Time for presence? Philosophia 38(2):271–280

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tallant J forthcoming. A sketch of a presentist theory of passage. Erkenntnis

  • Tye M (2000) Consciousness, color, and content, vol 113. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye M (2003) Consciousness and persons: unity and identity. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams DC (1951) The myth of passage. J Philos 48(15):457–472

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zeilicovici D (1981) Temporal becoming minus the moving-now. Noûs 23(4):505–524

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman DW (2005) The A-theory of time, the B-theory of time, and ‘taking tense seriously’. Dialectica 59(4):401–457

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Akiko M. Frischhut.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Frischhut, A.M. What Experience Cannot Teach Us About Time. Topoi 34, 143–155 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-013-9211-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-013-9211-x

Keywords

Navigation