Skip to main content
Log in

Hume and the enactive approach to mind

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

An important part of David Hume’s work is his attempt to put the natural sciences on a firmer foundation by introducing the scientific method into the study of human nature. This investigation resulted in a novel understanding of the mind, which in turn informed Hume’s critical evaluation of the scope and limits of the scientific method as such. However, while these latter reflections continue to influence today’s philosophy of science, his theory of mind is nowadays mainly of interest in terms of philosophical scholarship. This paper aims to show that, even though Hume’s recognition in the cognitive sciences has so far been limited, there is an opportunity to reevaluate his work in the context of more recent scientific developments. In particular, it is argued that we can gain a better understanding of his overall philosophy by tracing the ongoing establishment of the enactive approach. In return, this novel interpretation of Hume’s ‘science of man’ is used as the basis for a consideration of the current and future status of the cognitive sciences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This paper will draw mainly on Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature: Being an attempt to introduce the experimental method of reasoning into moral subjects (1739–1740a), An Abstract of ... A Treatise of Human Nature (1739–1740b), An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (1748), and his posthumously published Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (1779). Quotations taken from these works will be abbreviated by T, Abs, EHU, and DNR, respectively.

  2. Note that Hume’s critical opposition toward rationalism has arguably also received an experimental foundation in recent artificial intelligence research because in that field “the rationalist tradition had finally been put to an empirical test, and it had failed” (Dreyfus and Dreyfus 1988).

  3. According to some anatomists of Hume’s time, ‘animal spirits’ were a kind of nerve fluid inside nerve-tubes, which was the material source of nervous transmissions in animals and humans (EHU, p. 235).

  4. Hume often does not make a proper distinction between the physical or causal impact on the senses (sub-personal level) and the sense impressions present to the mind (personal level). Moreover, it is also questionable whether such atomic sense impressions can even be given in our experience (cf. Sellars 1956). Nevertheless, at least in the case of our experience of an external world, he explicitly offers a personal level explanation that takes as its starting point “only a single existence, which I shall call indifferently object or perception, [...], understanding by both of them what any common man means by a hat, or shoe, or stone, or any other impression, convey’d to him by his senses” (T. 1.4.2.31).

  5. Subsequently the label ‘enactive’ has also been associated with the sensorimotor account of perception of O’Regan and Noë (2001), especially due to Noë (2004). Here we will be specifically concerned with the broader enactive paradigm that began with Varela et al. (1991). See Torrance (2005) and Thompson (2007, pp. 243–266) for a discussion of the relationship between these two approaches.

  6. There is one notable difference in that Hume does not attempt to explain the origin of valence: “Nature has implanted in the human mind a perception of good or evil, or in other words, of pain and pleasure, as the chief spring and moving principle of all its actions” (T. 1.3.10.2). The enactive approach, on the other hand, often attempts to ground valence in the precarious situation of the self-constituting identity (e.g. Weber and Varela 2002). This additional move should not be misunderstood as a scientific explanation or logical argument; it is more of a structural match based on existential characteristics (cf. Jonas 1966).

  7. Note that this distinction between natural and mind science does not hold with respect to quantum mechanics, which is essentially participatory and structurally similar to the study of mind (cf. Bitbol 2002).

  8. Hume reports that the limitations of human reason have made him ready to reject all belief and reasoning: “Where am I, or what? [...] What beings surround me? [...] I am confounded with all these questions, and begin to fancy myself [...] inviron’d with the deepest darkness, and utterly depriv’d of the use of every member and faculty” (T. 1.4.7.8). It is worth noting the specific manner in which he finds back into the natural attitude: “I dine, I play a game of back-gammon, I converse, and am merry with my friends” (T. 1.4.7.9). Here we have a first rudimentary phenomenological description of how the category of the real is grounded in intersubjectivity, a theme more fully developed by the later Husserl (cf. Zahavi 1996).

References

  • Ashby, W. R. (1947). The nervous system as physical machine: With special reference to the origin of adaptive behavior. Mind, 56(221), 44–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. (1980). Hume. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D. (2000). Dynamical approaches to cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(3), 91–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D. (2003). The dynamics of active categorical perception in an evolved model agent. Adaptive Behavior, 11(4), 209–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biro, J. (1993). Hume’s new science of the mind. In D. F. Norton (Ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Hume (pp. 33–63). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol, M. (2002). Science as if situation mattered. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 181–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boden, M. A. (2008). Autonomy: What is it? BioSystems, 91(2), 305–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47(1–3), 139–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckle, S. (2001). Hume’s enlightenment tract: The unity and purpose of ‘an enquiry concerning human understanding. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chrisley, R., & Ziemke, T. (2002). Embodiment. In L. Nadel, et al. (Ed.), Encyclopaedia of cognitive science (pp. 1102–1108). London, UK: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cliff, D. (1991). Computational neuroethology: A provisional manifesto. In J.-A. Meyer, & S. W. Wilson (Eds.), From animals to animats: Proc. of the 1st Int. Conf. on Simulation of Adaptive Behavior (pp. 29–39). Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collier, M. (1999). Filling the gaps: Hume and connectionism on the continued existence of unperceived objects. Hume Studies, 25(1–2), 155–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collier, M. (2005). Hume and cognitive science: The current status of the controversy over abstract ideas. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(2), 197–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2008). Enaction, sense-making and emotion. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT, in press.

  • Copley, S., & Edgar, A. (1998). Introduction. In S. Copley, & A. Edgar (Eds.), David Hume: Selected essays (pp. vii–xxii). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York, NY: Putnam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davie, G. (1977). Edmund Husserl and ‘the as yet, in its most important respect, unrecognized greatness of Hume. In G. P. Morice (Ed.), David Hume: Bicentenary papers (pp. 69–76). Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. A. (2007). Participatory sense-making: An enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 485–507.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. (1953). Empirisme et subjectivité: Essai sure la Nature Humaine selon Hume, trans. by: C. V. Boundas, Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature. New York, NY: Columbia University Press, (1991).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1978). Brainstorms: Philosophical essays on mind and psychology. Montgomery, VT: Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1984). Cognitive wheels: The frame problem of AI. In C. Hookway (Ed.), Minds, machines, and evolution: Philosophical studies (pp. 129–151). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Depraz, N., Varela, F. J., & Vermersch, P. (2003). On becoming aware: A pragmatics of experiencing. The Netherlands, Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2003). Organismically-inspired robotics: homeostatic adaptation and teleology beyond the closed sensorimotor loop. In K. Murase, & T. Asakura (Eds.), Dynamical systems approach to embodiment and sociality (pp. 19–42). Adelaide, Australia: Advanced Knowledge International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2008). Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social interaction, and play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT, in press.

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2007). Why Heideggerian AI failed and how fixing it would require making it more Heideggerian. Philosophical Psychology, 20(2), 247–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L., & Dreyfus, S. E. (1988). Making a mind versus modelling the brain: artificial intelligence back at a branch-point. Daedalus, 117(1), 15–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (2003). Hume variations. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, D. (1981). Hume’s self-doubts about personal identity. The Philosophical Review, 90(3), 337–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, D. (1997). Cognition and commitment in Hume’s philosophy. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harnish, R. M. (2002). Minds, brains, computers: An historical introduction to the foundations of cognitive science. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, I. (2008). Misrepresentations. In S. Bullock, J. Noble, R. Watson, & M. Bedau (Eds.), Artificial life XI: Proc. of the 11th Int. Conf. on the simulation and synthesis of living systems (pp. 227–233). Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739–1740a). In D. F. Norton, & M. J. Norton (Eds.), A treatise of human nature. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739–1740b). An abstract of … A treatise of human nature. In D. F. Norton, & M. J. Norton (Eds.), David Hume: A treatise of human nature. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1741). Of the delicacy of taste and passion. In S. Copley, & A. Edgar (Eds.), David Hume: Selected essays (pp. 10–13). New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1748). In T. L. Beauchamp (Ed.), An enquiry concerning human understanding. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1757). Of the standard of taste. In S. Copley, & A. Edgar (Eds.), David Hume: Selected essays (pp. 133–154). New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1779). Dialogues concerning natural religion. In J. C. A. Gaskin (Ed.), David Hume: Principal writings on religion including dialogues concerning natural religion and the natural history of religion. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1929). Formale und transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft. In P. Janssen (Ed.), Husserliana XVII. The Hague, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  • Izquierdo, E., & Harvey, I. (2007). The dynamics of associative learning in an evolved situated agent. In F. Almeida e Costa, et al. (Ed.), ECAL 2007: Proc. of the 9th Euro. Conf. on Artificial Life (pp. 365–374). Berlin, Germany: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Izquierdo-Torres, E., & Di Paolo, E. A. (2005). Is an embodied system ever purely reactive? In M. Capcarrere, et al. (Ed.), ECAL 2005: Proc. of the 8th Euro. Conf. on Artificial Life (pp. 252–261). Germany, Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life: Toward a philosophical biology. Evanston,Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemp Smith, N. (1905). The naturalism of Hume (I.). Mind, 14(54), 149–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kemp Smith, N. (1935). Introduction. In N. K. Smith (Ed.), Hume’s dialogues concerning natural religion (pp. 1–153). London, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Dordrecht, Holland: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, J., & Hayes, P. J. (1969). Some philosophical problems from the standpoint of artificial intelligence. In B. Meltzer, & D. Michie (Eds.), Machine intelligence 4 (pp. 463–502). Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McClelland, J. L., Rumelhart, D. E., & the PDP Research Group (1986). Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition. Vol. 2: Psychological and biological models. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGann, M. (2007). Enactive theorists do it on purpose: Toward an enactive account of goals and goal-directedness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 463–483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, D. (2000). Introduction to phenomenology. London, UK: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1976). Computer science as empirical inquiry: Symbols and search. Communications of the Association for Computing Machinery, 19(3), 113–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939–1031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1984). Computation and cognition: Toward a foundation for cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (1993). Hume and the philosophy of science. In D. F. Norton (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Hume (pp. 64–89). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roy, J.-M., Petitot, J., Pachoud, B., & Varela, F. J. (1999). Beyond the gap: An introduction to naturalizing phenomenology. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, B. Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds.), Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 1–80). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schliesser, E. (2007). Hume’s Newtonianism and Anti-Newtonianism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Summer 2007 Edition, URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2007/entries/hume-newton/.

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In H. Feigl, & M. Scriven (Eds.), The foundations of science and the concepts of psychology and psychoanalysis (pp. 253–329). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. C. (2007). The objectivity of tastes and tasting. In B. C. Smith (Ed.), Questions of taste: The philosophy of wine (pp. 41–77). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolensky, P. (1988). On the proper treatment of connectionism. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J., Di Paolo, E. A., & Gapenne, O. (2008). Introduction. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT, in press.

  • Stroud, B. (1977). Hume. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2004). Life and mind: From autopoiesis to neurophenomenology. A tribute to Francisco Varela. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3(4), 381–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torrance, S. (2005). In search of the enactive: Introduction to special issue on enactive experience. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 357–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Gelder, T. (1998). The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21(5), 615–665.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Gelder, T., & Port, R. F. (1995). It’s about time: An overview of the dynamical approach to cognition. In R. F. Port, & T. van Gelder (Eds.), Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition (pp. 1–43). Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1992). Un Know-How per l’Etica, trans. as: Ethical know-how: Action, wisdom, and cognition. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3(4), 330–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1997). Patterns of life: Intertwining identity and cognition. Brain and Cognition, 34(1), 72–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1999). The specious present: A neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, B. Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds.), Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 266–314). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., & Depraz, N. (2005). At the source of time: Valence and the constitutional dynamics of affect. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 12(8–10), 61–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., & Shear, J. (1999). First-person methodologies: What, Why, How? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6(2–3), 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waxman, W. (1994). Hume’s theory of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world: The next step. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (1996). Husserl und die transzendentale Intersubjektivität: Eine Antwort auf die sprachpragmatische Kritik, trans. by: E. A. Behnke, Husserl and Transcendental Intersubjectivity: A response to the linguistic-pragmatic critique. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to Mike Beaton, Ezequiel Di Paolo, Joel Parthemore, Tom Ziemke, Charles Wolfe and two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper. Much of this paper was written during a stay in 2007 at the University of Skövde funded by the euCognition network (www.eucognition.org), as part of the European Cognitive Systems initiative.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tom Froese.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Froese, T. Hume and the enactive approach to mind. Phenom Cogn Sci 8, 95–133 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-008-9111-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-008-9111-5

Keywords

Navigation