Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Schelling as a Thinker of Immanence: contra Heidegger and Jaspers

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Among the different interpretations of the philosophy of Schelling, there is no doubt that the ones developed by Martin Heidegger and Karl Jaspers played a prominent role within the most recent Schelling scholarship. Both Heidegger and Jaspers focused on Schelling’s discourse on freedom, pointing out the fundamental incompatibility of its key elements, i.e. ‘ground’ and ‘existence’, as well as the fallacious conception of Seynsfuge that emerges from it. Moreover, Heidegger argues that Schelling’s ontology ultimately falls back into traditional metaphysical subjectivism, ignoring the question of Being as such and in fact paving the way to nihilism. Similarly, Jaspers criticizes Schelling’s arbitrary account of the relation between freedom and existential being and his misleading conception of transcendence. However, I argue against Jaspers that Schelling’s discourse on freedom must be read as a philosophy of immanence, which aims at maintaining the concreteness of the concepts and at avoiding any form of transcendence. Consequently, I also argue against Heidegger that not only does Schelling’s discourse successfully show the compatibility of ground and existence, but that Schelling’s understanding of the ‘subject’ does not comply with Heidegger’s notion of ‘metaphysical subjectivism’ and is immune to Heidegger’s criticism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I am referring to F. W. J. Schelling, Philosophische Untersuchungen über das Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit und die damit zusammenhängenden Gegenstände, in SW I.7, 331–416. All the English citations from this work are taken from Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom. Translated and with an introduction by J. Love and J. Schmidt. Albany: SUNY Press, 2010.

  2. This point is largely accepted within the recent scholarship. See Olson 1994 and Heidegger et al. 2003.

  3. On this, see Vater 1975, Sikka 1994, Figal 2010, and Hühn 2014.

  4. The first draft of The Ages of the World (Die Weltalter) dates back to 1811, while the second one was written in 1813, and then, Schelling definitively abandoned the project in 1815.

  5. Incidentally, Heidegger also criticizes Jaspers’s ontology, claiming that Jaspers “rejects the possibility of ontology in general because he also understands by ontology only what it has previously been taken for and which has remained a mechanical manipulation of rigidified concepts” (Heidegger 1985: 64), in turn failing to properly address the fundamental question of Being as such.

  6. That is to say, Schelling maintains that in Being there is an incomprehensible ground and an ‘invisible remainder’; however, such incomprehensibility does not lead Schelling to the conclusion that Being is transcendent and that its ‘invisible remainder’ is a sheer metaphysical occurrence. On the contrary, “the understanding is born in the genuine sense from that which is without understanding. Without this preceding darkness creatures have no reality; darkness is their necessary inheritance” (Schelling 2010: 29; Schelling 1860: I.7, 360). In other words, just as there can be no light without a preceding darkness to be overwhelmed, Being can only occur and be grasped as that immanent life which arises from the tension between ground and existence. According to Schelling, denying this point means to turn Being itself into a sheer arbitrary and transcendent idea, namely, into an ungrounded concept.

References

  • Alderwick, C. (2015). Atemporal essence and existential freedom in Schelling. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 23(1), 115–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Figal, G. (2010). Schelling zwischen Hölderlin und Nietzsche – Heidegger liest Schellings Freiheitsschrift. In L. Hühn & J. Jantzen (Eds.), Heideggers Schelling-seminar (1927/28). Die Protokolle von Martin Heideggers seminar zu Schellings ´Freiheitsschrift´ (1927/28) und die Akten des Internationalen Schelling-tags 2006 (pp. 45–58). Stuttgart: Bad Cannstatt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1954). Das absolute und die geschichte: von der Zweispältigkeit in Schellings Denken. In Dissertation, philosophy. Bonn: Friedrich-Wilhelms-Universität.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin (1985). Schelling’s treatise on the essence of human freedom. Trans. J. Stambaugh. Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2012). In R. Rojcewicz (Ed.), The beginning of Western philosophy: interpretation of Anaximander and Parmenides. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M., Saner, H., Biemel, W., & Jaspers, K. (2003). The Heidegger-Jaspers correspondence (1920–1963). Amherst: Humanity Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hühn, L. (2014). A philosophical dialogue between Heidegger and Schelling. Comparative and Continental Philosophy, 6(1), 16–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, K. (1955). Schelling: Größe und Verhängnis. Munich: Piper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, Karl (1959). Truth and symbol. Translated and with an introduction by J. T. Wilde, W. Kluback and W. Kimmel. Albany: NCUP.

  • Jaspers, Karl (1971). Philosophy. Volume 3. Trans. E. B. Ashton. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

  • Jaspers, K. (1993). The great philosophers. In M. Ermarth & L. Ehrlich (Eds.), Volume III: Xenophanes, Democritus, Empedocles, Bruno, Epicurus, Boehme, Schelling, Leibniz, Aristotle, Hegel. New York: Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, S. J. (2010). Schelling on the unconscious. Research in Phenomenology, 40(1), 72–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nassar, D. (2012). Spinoza in Schelling’s early conception of intellectual intuition. In E. Forster & Y. Melamed (Eds.), Spinoza and German idealism (pp. 136–155). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Norman, J. 1997. Ages of the world: text and context of the translation. Translator’s note in Slavoj ŽiŽek and F. W. J. Schelling, The abyss of freedom / Ages of the world. Translated and with an introduction by J. Norman (pp. 107–12). Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

  • Olson, A. M. (Ed.). (1994). Heidegger & Jaspers. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, F. W. J. (1860). Sämmtliche Werke. Ed. K. F. A. Schelling. Stuttgart: Cotta.

  • Schelling, F. W. J. (1980). Of the I as the principle of philosophy. In F. Marti (Ed.), The unconditional in human knowledge: four early essays 1794–6 (pp. 63–128). Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, F. W. J. (2000). The ages of the world. Translated and with an introduction by J. M. Wirth. Albany: SUNY Press.

  • Schelling, F. W. J. (2010). Philosophical investigations into the essence of human freedom. Translated and with an introduction by J. Love and J. Schmidt. Albany: SUNY Press.

  • Schelling, F. W. J. (2012). Presentation of my system of philosophy. In M. Vater & D. Wood (Eds.), J. G. Fichte and F. W. J. Schelling, The philosophical rupture between Fichte and Schelling: selected texts and correspondence (1800-1802) (pp. 141–205). Albany: SUNY Press.

  • Sikka, S. (1994). Heidegger’s appropriation of Schelling. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 32, 421–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tilliette, X. (1959). Actualité de Schelling. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, 3, 356–369.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vallega-Neu, D. (2003). Heidegger’s contributions to philosophy: an introduction. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vater, M. (1975). Heidegger and Schelling: the finitude of being. Idealistic Studies, 5(1), 20–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vater, M. (2012). Schelling’s philosophy of identity and Spinoza’s Ethica more geometrico. In E. Forster & Y. Melamed (Eds.), Spinoza and German idealism (pp. 156–174). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Whistler, D. (2013). Schelling’s theory of symbolic language: forming the system of identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniele Fulvi.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fulvi, D. Schelling as a Thinker of Immanence: contra Heidegger and Jaspers. SOPHIA 60, 869–887 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-020-00784-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-020-00784-7

Keywords

Navigation