Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T17:12:31.231Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

History, Philosophy, and the Central Metaphor

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 September 2008

Peter Galison
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Department of Physics, and Program in the History of ScienceStanford University

Abstract

Behind the dispute over the relative priority of theory and experiment lie conflicting philosophical images of the nature of scientific inquiry. One crucial image arose in the 1920s, when the logical positivists agitated for a “unity of science” that would ground all meaningful scientific activity on an observational foundation. Their goals and rhetoric dovetailed with the larger movements of architectural, literary, and philosophical modernism. Historians of science followed the positivists by tracking experimental science as the basis for scientific progress. After World War II, historians and philosophers of science created an antipositivist movement, inverting the positivist idea that observation had epistemic (and historical) priority. But this counter-movement retained the modernist aspiration to unity, now chaining observation to theory. Once again historians of science, following their philosophical colleagues, illustrated the new modernism with historical instances of observation dominated by theory.

Either reductionist scheme, by privileging one activity over the other, dictates an overly constrictive periodization. We need a wider class of periodization models (“central metaphors”) that will allow instrumentation, experimentation, and theory a partial autonomy without granting any one the sole legitimate narrative standpoint. Such a heterogeneous representation of historical traditions may, surprisingly, make better sense of the perceived coherence of activity across theoretical transitions than the monolithic modernist representation of science it displaces.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Black, M., 1934 Introduction to Carnap 1934.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolph, 1934 The Unity of Science trans, and ed Black, M.. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner and Co.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolph, 1955Logical Foundations of the Unity of Science,” in Neurath, Morris, and Carnap 1955.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolph, 1963Intellectual Autobiography,” in Schilpp 1963.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolph, 1981 “Protocol Statements and the Formal Mode of Speech,” in Essential Readings in Logical Positivism, ed. Hanfling, O. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Cohen, Robert S. and Marie, Neurath eds., 1983 Otto Neurath Philosophical Papers, 1913–1946 Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Conant, James general., ed.,Nash, Leonard K associate ed., [1957] 1970 Harvard Case Histories in Experimental Science. Cambridge Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Conrads, U. ed., 1964 Programs and Manifestoes on Twentieth-Century Architecture, Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Elkana, Yehuda, 1981 “A Programmatic Attempt at an Anthropology of Knowledge,” in Sciences and Cultures ed. Mendelsohn, E. and Elkana, Y. 176 Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul, 1981 Realism, Rationalism, and Scientific Method. Philosophical Papers vol. I Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galison, Peter, 1987 How Experiments End. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Galison, Peter and Alexi, Assmus, forthcoming (1988) “Artificial Clouds, Real Particles,” in Gooding, Pinch and Schaffer 1988.Google Scholar
Gooding, David, Trevor, Pinch and Simon, Schaffer, eds., forthcoming (1988). The Uses of Experiment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian, 1983. Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl G., 1966 Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs N.J: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Holton, Gerald R., 1973 Thematic Origins of Scientific Thought Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lakatos, Imre, 1970Methodology of Scientific Research Programs,” in Lakatos and Musgrave 1970.Google Scholar
Lakatos, Imre and Musgrave, A. eds., 1970 Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Le, Corbusier, 1925 “Collection de l'esprit Nouveau,” reprinted in Conrads 1964.Google Scholar
Lissitsky, Eleazar Markovich, 1929 Reprinted in Conrads 1964.Google Scholar
Lyotard, Jean-Francois, 1984 The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Morris, Charles, 1955Scientific Empiricism,” in Neurath, Morris and Carnap 1955.Google Scholar
Neurath, Otto, 1955Unified Science as Encyclopedic Integration,” in Neurath, Morris, and Carnap 1955.Google Scholar
Neurath, Otto, 1983Physicalism,” in Cohen and Neurath 1983.Google Scholar
Neurath, O. Morris, C. and Carnap, R. eds., 1955 International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, 2 vols Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl, 1968 Logic of Scientific Discovery New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O., 1953 “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” in From A Logical Point of View. Cambridge Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand, 1914 Our Knowledge of the External World Chicago and London: Open Court.Google Scholar
Schilpp, Paul A., ed., 1963 The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. La Salle 111.: Open Court.Google Scholar
Schlick, Moritz, 1974 General Theory of Knowledge. New York and Vienna: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar