Skip to main content
Log in

A Quantum Theory of Consciousness

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The relationship between quantum collapse and consciousness is reconsidered under the assumption that quantum collapse is an objective dynamical process. We argue that the conscious observer can have a distinct role from the physical measuring device during the process of quantum collapse owing to the intrinsic nature of consciousness; the conscious observer can know whether he is in a definite state or a quantum superposition of definite states, while the physical measuring device cannot “know”. As a result, the consciousness observer can distinguish the definite states and their quantum superposition, while the physical measuring device without consciousness cannot do. This provides a possible quantum physical method to distinguish man and machine. The new result also implies that consciousness has causal efficacies in the physical world when considering the existence of quantum collapse. Accordingly consciousness is not reducible or emergent, but a new fundamental property of matter. This may establish a quantum basis for panpsychism, and make it be a promising solution to the hard problem of consciousness. Furthermore, it is suggested that a unified theory of matter and consciousness includes two parts: one is the psychophysical principle or corresponding principle between conscious content and matter state, and the other is the complete quantum evolution of matter state, which includes the definite nonlinear evolution element introduced by consciousness and relating to conscious content. Lastly, some experimental schemes are presented to test the proposed quantum theory of consciousness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Even though this is possible for a conscious being, it is impossible for a physical measuring device according to the existing physical theories. As thus, the conscious being also has a distinct effect from the physical measuring device, i.e., that he can know the random collapse result beforehand.

  2. Gao (2004a) gave a more detailed demonstration of this conclusion.

  3. We note that the calculation here is still very crude. We omit the influence of other factors (e.g. thermal noise) on the energy difference between the two conscious perception states, which is assumed to be small enough at least in some controllable situations.

  4. The subjects should be unfamiliar with each other before the experiment. This can be tested by the phase incoherence of their brain waves.

References

  • Adler, S. L., & Brun, T. A. (2001). Generalized stochastic Schrödinger equations for state vector collapse. Journal of Physics A, 34, 4797–4809.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. S. (1987). Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford: University of Oxford Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F. (1994). The astonishing hypothesis. New York: Scribner’s.

    Google Scholar 

  • Czachor, M. (1995). Nonlinear Schrödinger equation and two-level atoms. Preprint quant-ph/9501007.

  • DeWitt, B. S., & Graham, N. (Eds.), (1973). The many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, D. (1985). Quantum theory as a universal physical theory. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 24, 1–41.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Diosi, L. (1989). Models for universal reduction of macroscopic quantum fluctuations. Physics Review A, 40, 1165–1174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duane, T. D., & Behrendt, T. (1965). Extrasensory electroencephalographic induction between two identical twins. Science, 150, 367.

  • Edelman, G. M., & Tononi, G. (2000). A universe of consciousness: How matter becomes imagination. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everett, H. (1957). Relative state formulation of quantum mechanics. Review of Modern Physics 29, 454–462.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Fivel, D. I. (1997). Dynamical reduction theory of Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen correlations and a possible origin of CP violations. Physics Review A, 56, 146–156.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2000). Quantum motion and superluminal communication. Beijing: Chinese Broadcasting & Television Publishing House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2001). From quantum motion to classical motion-seeking the lost reality. Physics Essays, 14(1), 37–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2003a). A possible quantum basis of panpsychism. NeuroQuantology, 1(1), 4–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2003b). Quantum. Beijing: Tsinghua University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2004a). Quantum collapse, consciousness and superluminal communication. Foundation of Physics Letters, 17(2), 167–182.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2004b). A possible connection between quantum and self-consciousness. Axiomathes: An International Journal in Ontology and Cognitive Systems, 14(4), 295–305.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2006a). What quantum mechanics really describes: Discontinuous motion of particles. Galilean Electrodynamics, 17(1), 3–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2006b). A model of wavefunction collapse in discrete space-time. International Jouranl of Theoretical Physics, 45(10), 1943–1957.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2006c). Quantum motion: Unveiling the mysterious quantum world. Bury St Edmunds: Arima Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi, G. C., Rimini, A., & Weber, T. (1986). Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic systems. Physics Review D, 34, 470–491.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi, G. C., Pearle, P., & Rimini, A. (1990). A Continuous-spontaneous-reduction model involving gravity. Physics Review D, 42, 1057–1064.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Hameroff, S. R., & Penrose, R. (1996). Conscious events as orchestrated space-time selections. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3(1), 36–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughston, L. P. (1996). Geometry of stochastic state vector reduction. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A, 452, 953–979.

    MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Jahn, R. G., Dunne, B. J., Nelson, R. D., Dobyns, Y. H., & Bradish, G. J. (1997). Correlations of random binary sequences with pre-stated operator intention: A review of a 12-year program. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 11(3), 345–367.

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (1993). Neurophysiology of consciousness: Selected papers and new essays. Boston: Birkhauser.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1999). The mysterious flame: Conscious minds in a material world. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearle, P. (1989). Combining stochastic dynamical state-vector reduction with spontaneous localization. Physics Review A, 39, 2277–2289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1996). On gravity’s role in quantum state reduction. General Relativity and Gravitation, 28, 581–600.

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Percival, I. C. (1994). Primary state diffusion. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A, 447, 189–209.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Radin, D. I. (1997). The conscious universe: The scientific truth of psychic phenomena. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radin, D. I., & Nelson, R. D. (1989). Evidence for consciousness-related anomalies in random physical systems. Foundations of Physics, 19(12), 1499–1514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (1999). Theories of consciousness. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. (2001). Panpsychism, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

  • Stapp, H. (1996). Mind, matter, and quantum mechanics. New York: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2006). Realistic monism: Why physicalism entails panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13(4).

  • Strawson, G., et al. (2006). Consciousness and its place in nature: Does physicalism entail panpsychism? Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Targ, R., & Puthoff, H. (1974). Information transmission under conditions of sensory shielding. Nature, 252, 602–607.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tegmark, M. (2000). Importance of quantum decoherence in brain processes. Physics Review E, 61, 4194–4206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J. (1955). Mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Wackermann, J., Seiter, C., Keibel, H., & Walach H. (2003). Correlations between brain electrical activities of two spatially separated human subjects. Neuroscience Letters, 336, 60–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. P. (1967). Symmetries and reflections. Bloomington and London: Indiana University Press, pp.171–184.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am very grateful to the referee whose comments helped to improve the clarity and understandability of the exposition.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shan Gao.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gao, S. A Quantum Theory of Consciousness. Minds & Machines 18, 39–52 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-007-9084-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-007-9084-0

Keywords

Navigation