Skip to main content
Log in

Beneficence and procreation

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Consider a duty of beneficence towards a particular individual, S, and call a reason that is grounded in that duty a “beneficence reason towards S.” Call a person who will be brought into existence by an act of procreation the “resultant person.” Is there ever a beneficence reason towards the resultant person for an agent to procreate? In this paper, I argue for such a reason by appealing to two main premises. First, we owe a pro tanto duty of beneficence to future persons; and second, some of us can benefit some of those persons by procreating. In support of the first premise I reject the presentist account of time in favor of the view that future persons are just as real as presently existing persons. I then argue that future persons are like us in all the morally relevant ways, and since we owe duties of beneficence to each other, we also owe duties of beneficence to future persons. In support of the second premise I offer an account of benefiting according to which an individual can be benefited by an action even if it makes her no better off than she would have been, had the action not been performed. This account of benefiting solves what I call the “non-identity benefit problem.” Finally, I argue that having a life worth living is a benefit, and some of us can cause some persons that benefit by causing them to exist.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Philosophers who either argue for or merely assume such a view in the course of arguing for something else include Bennett (1978), Warren (1978), Roberts (2011), and Benatar (2006).

  2. Recall my earlier definition of a beneficence reason towards an individual. More generally, I define a reason towards an individual as a reason that is grounded in a duty towards that individual.

  3. Although not everyone uses the same terminology, there is generally a contrast drawn between “direct duties towards” (or just “duties towards”) individuals and “indirect duties towards” or “duties regarding” individuals. Duties of the former kind ought to be carried out for the individual’s own sake, whereas duties of the latter kind might be owed to someone other than the beneficiary of the duty, as when I promise you that I will take your dog to the vet and thereby owe a duty regarding your dog to you. See Wellman (1999) for an overview, Regan (1983) for a discussion of direct duties towards nonhuman animals, and Kant (1989) and Korsgaard (2004) for discussions of what it means to have duties regarding (and not towards) nonhuman animals.

  4. I am using the word “concrete individual” to refer to individuals that are located in time. Examples of concrete individuals are particular persons, particular actions, and particular tables and chairs. The contrasting term is “abstract entity,” which is often taken to refer to things like humanity in general, justice, the color blue, or the number three.

  5. Some proponents of eternalism include Mellor (1998), Smart (1963), and Sider (2001). Notice that eternalism is not the same view as determinism. I take determinism to be the view that all propositions about the future are determined by propositions about the past together with the laws of nature. Eternalism also holds that propositions about the future are determinate—and thus, are determined by something—but eternalists need not hold that propositions about the past and the laws of nature are what determine all propositions about the future. They might instead hold, for example, that propositions about the future are determined by facts about the future.

  6. One might also worry that, because the identities of future persons are contingent upon the choices that present people make, there are no facts about who will exist before those choices are made. However, the principle behind this objection is false: the fact that B is contingent upon A does not mean that B is indeterminate. My own existence was contingent on the actions of my parents, but my identity is determinate. More generally, if eternalism is true, then there are facts about what the outcomes of our choices will be even before we make those choices. I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising the objection that prompted this clarification.

  7. Presentism is defended by Prior (1968), Bigelow (1996), Bourne (2006), and Markosian (2013). Some proponents of growing block theory include Broad (1923), Tooley (2000), and Forrest (2004).

  8. Markosian (2013) also denies the truth of future-tense claims on the condition that the laws of nature are sufficiently indeterministic. However, he argues that if the laws are sufficiently deterministic, then true claims about the future can be grounded by relations between such laws and presently existing objects. For a critique of this kind of approach, see Sider (2001).

  9. Many presentists are focused primarily on the task of explaining how claims about the past can be true or false. Nevertheless, if such presentists were amenable to the idea that some claims about the future were also true, then they would presumably endorse a semantics for future-tense claims similar to their preferred semantics for past-tense claims. For an overview and a critique of the various strategies that presentists have employed to try to vindicate the truth of general claims about the past, see Baron (2013).

  10. I am assuming that the parents of the future preschoolers don't interact with the people who work at the chemical company. The parents will carry out their daily activities—including procreating at particular times—regardless of whether the company does or does not bury the waste beneath the school. This feature of the case helps us to avoid what is known as the “non-identity problem,” which I will discuss in the next section of the paper.

  11. Certainly, the chemical company also owes a duty to the parents of the preschoolers not to harm their children. However, this is not the only duty that is breached; there is a duty to the preschoolers, themselves, not to cause them painful and debilitating organ damage.

  12. Earl (2011) speculates that presentists or growing block theorists might take “future generations” to be “a collection of people potentially existing now,” “a collection of ontologically possibly existing people,” “a collection of imaginary people,” “a ‘useful fiction’,” or “a set, considered as an abstract entity, of ‘placeholders’ or ‘offices’ that are not filled by any presently existing people, but will be filled by some people at a future time” (pp. 63–63). He argues, correctly in my view, that if “future generations” refers to any of the above, then we have no moral duties to them.

  13. Here my argument is similar to Earl’s (2011) argument for the claim that any dynamic theory of time is incompatible with our having obligations to future generations. However, Earl takes this incompatibility to show that we do not have obligations to future generations, whereas I take the incompatibility to show that presentism and growing block theory are false.

  14. In saying this, I reject Kamm’s (1999) view that proximity in space affects the strength of our obligations to help strangers.

  15. I owe this point to Ruth Weintraub (2003), who argues that “When does X cause Y?” is nonsensical, as are “When does X precede Y?” and “When does X last longer than Y?” (p. 181).

  16. The term, “non-identity problem” was coined by Parfit (1984), but the fundamental tensions that constitute the problem were identified, somewhat independently, by Parfit (1976), Adams (1972), and Schwartz (1978).

  17. Proponents of the counterfactually worse-off condition on harming include Feinberg (1984), Boonin (2008), Heyd (2009), Schwartz (1978), and Thomson (2011). Those who reject the counterfactually worse-off condition on harming include Hanser (2008, 2009), Harman (2004; 2009), Klocksiem (2012), Shiffrin (1999), and Woollard (2012). I also argue against the counterfactually worse-off condition in Gardner (2013; forthcoming).

  18. This case is modeled upon one that Woollard (2012) appeals to in her own argument against the counterfactually worse-off condition on harming.

  19. This account of benefiting can also be modified to produce the following account of harming: (H1) A state of affairs, A, is a harm for an individual, S, just in case if it were true that both S existed and A did not obtain, then S would be better off in some respect; and (H2) An event, E, harms an individual, S, just in case E causes a state of affairs that is a harm for S. I argue for something like this account of harming in Gardner (2013, forthcoming).

  20. The accounts of causation defended by Lewis (2000) and Hitchcock (2001) do not make a metaphysical distinction between causes and mere conditions. Accounts that do draw such a distinction include those defended by Broadbent (2007a, b, 2008), Schaffer (2005), and Menzies (2004).

  21. For a defense of possibilism, see Lewis (1986). For defenses of actualism, see Plantinga (1974) and Adams (1981).

  22. For an argument that we ought to respect the interests of merely possible people, see Hare (2007).

References

  • Adams, R. M. (1972). Must God create the best? Philosophical Review, 81, 317–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, R. M. (1981). Actualism and thisness. Synthese, 49, 3–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron, S. (2013). Tensed supervenience: A no-go for presentism. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 51, 383–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benatar, D. (2006). Better never to have been: The harm of coming into existence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. (1978). On maximising happiness. In R. I. Sikora & B. Barry (Eds.), Obligations to future generations (pp. 61–73). Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, J. (1996). Presentism and properties. Philosophical Perspectives, 10, 35–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boonin, D. (2008). How to solve the non-identity problem. Public Affairs Quarterly, 22(2), 129–159.

  • Bourne, C. (2006). A future for presentism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C. D. (1923). Scientific thought. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broadbent, A. (2007a). A reverse counterfactual analysis of causation. (Doctoral dissertation) University of Cambridge.

  • Broadbent, A. (2007b). Reversing the counterfactual analysis of causation. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 15, 169–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broadbent, A. (2008). The difference between cause and condition. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 108, 355–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earl, D. (2011). Ontology and the paradox of future generations. Public Reason, 3(1), 60–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1984). The moral limits of the criminal law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (2004). The real but dead past: A reply to Braddon-Mitchell. Analysis, 64, 358–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, M. (2013). Our duties to future generations. (Doctoral dissertation) University of Wisconsin-Madison.

  • Gardner, M. (forthcoming). A harm-based solution to the non-identity problem. Ergo.

  • Hanser, M. (2008). The metaphysics of harm. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77, 421–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanser, M. (2009). Harming and procreating. In M. Roberts & D. Wasserman (Eds.), Harming future persons: Ethics, genetics and the nonidentity problem (pp. 179–199). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, C. (2007). Voices from another world: Must we respect the interests of people who do not, and will never, exist? Ethics, 117, 498–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, E. (2004). Can we harm and benefit in creating? Philosophical Perspectives, 18, 89–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, E. (2009). Harming as causing harm. In M. Roberts & D. Wasserman (Eds.), Harming future persons: Ethics, genetics and the nonidentity problem (pp. 137–154). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heyd, D. (2009). The intractability of the nonidentity problem. In M. Roberts & D. Wasserman (Eds.), Harming future persons: Ethics, genetics and the nonidentity problem (pp. 3–25). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (2001). The intransitivity of causation revealed in equations and graphs. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 273–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. (1999). Famine ethics: The problem of distance in morality and Singer’s ethical theory. In D. Jamieson (Ed.), Singer and his critics (pp. 161–208). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1989). Duties in regard to animals. In: T. Regan and P. Singer (Eds.) Animal rights and human obligations. pp 23–24.

  • Klocksiem, J. (2012). A defense of the counterfactual comparative account of harm. American Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 285–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (2004). Fellow creatures: Kantian ethics and our duties to animals. In G. Peterson (Ed.), The tanner lectures on human values (Vol. 25/26). Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2000). Causation as influence. Journal of Philosophy, 97, 182–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markosian, N. (2013). The truth about the past and the future. In F. Correia & A. Iacona (Eds.), Around the tree: semantic and metaphysical issues concerning branching time and the open future. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (1998). Real Time II. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P. (2004). Difference-making in context. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1976). On doing the best for our children. In M. Bayles (Ed.), Ethics and population (pp. 100–115). Cambridge, MA: Schenkman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1974). The nature of necessity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. (1968). Papers on time and tense. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regan, T. (1983). The case for animal rights. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, M. A. (2011). The asymmetry: A solution. Theoria, 77, 333–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2005). Contrastive causation. Philosophical Review, 114, 327–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, T. (1978). Obligations to posterity. In R. I. Sikora & B. Barry (Eds.), Obligations to future generations (pp. 3–13). Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin, S. (1999). Wrongful life, procreative responsibility, and the significance of harm. Legal Theory, 5, 117–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001). Four dimensionalism: An ontology of persistence and time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1963). Philosophy and scientific realism. New York: The Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (2011). More on the metaphysics of harm. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82, 436–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (2000). Time, tense, and causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, M. A. (1978). Do potential people have moral rights? In R. I. Sikora & B. Barry (Eds.), Obligations to future generations (pp. 14–30). Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weintraub, R. (2003). The time of a killing. Analysis, 63, 178–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, C. (1999). Relative moral duties. American Philosophical Quarterly, 36, 209–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woollard, F. (2012). Have we solved the non-identity problem? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 15, 677–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank audiences at the 2011 Russell VII conference, the 2012 meeting of the South Carolina Society for Philosophy, the University of Wisconsin-Madison, and Oklahoma State University for helpful feedback. I owe special thanks to participants in my metaphysics and ethics seminar at the University of Bayreuth and to Robert Streiffer, Justin Weinberg, Alastair Norcross, Michael Campbell, and an anonymous reviewer.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Molly Gardner.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gardner, M. Beneficence and procreation. Philos Stud 173, 321–336 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0494-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0494-1

Keywords

Navigation