Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x24gv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-09T14:15:49.941Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Lying with Uninformative Speech Acts

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 May 2023

Grzegorz Gaszczyk*
Affiliation:
Faculty of Philosophy, University of Groningen, Oude Boteringestraat 52, 9712 GL Groningen, The Netherlands
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

I propose an analysis of lying with uninformative speech acts. The orthodox view states that lying is restricted to assertions. However, the growing case for non-assertoric lies made by presuppositions or conventional implicatures challenges this orthodoxy. So far, the only presuppositions to have been considered as lies were informative presuppositions. In fact, uninformative lies were not discussed in the philosophical literature. However, limiting the possibility of lying to informative speech acts is too restrictive. Firstly, I show that standard, uninformative presuppositions can also be lies. Secondly, I extend this picture into uninformative lies made by declarative statements. To implement my proposal, I do not need a new definition of lying. Recently popular commitment-based definitions of lying are able to properly handle uninformative lies.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Canadian Journal of Philosophy

1. Introduction

Traditional definitions of lying maintain that one lies only if one says something one believes to be false with an intention to deceive.Footnote 1 Recently, there is an influential trend to modify this definition in two ways. Firstly, lies are not just any sayings; rather, the contemporary orthodoxy states that lying is restricted to asserting. Secondly, the intention to deceive is considered unnecessary. Thus, we are left with the following simple definition: lying is insincerely asserting.Footnote 2 From these considerations we can extract the almost universally held assumption that underlies theorising about lying.

ASSERTION-ONLY: Only assertions can be lies.

Moreover, based on the analysis of recent literature, we can add the second assumption that is rarely expressed directly, but is intuitively plausible:Footnote 3

INFORMATIVENESS: Lies are informative speech acts.

It is easy to see why lies should be informative. A standard way to lie to someone is by introducing a new piece of information. This way of thinking is grounded in theories of assertion that take assertions to be essentially informative speech acts (e.g., Searle [1969]; Stalnaker [1974, 1978]; García-Carpintero [2004, 2020]; cf. Pagin [Reference Pagin, Brown and Cappelen2011]). Since lies are assertions, they should also satisfy this basic condition. Consider a simple analogy: just as it is generally regarded as improper to ask a question when one already knows the answer, it is also improper to assert information that is already commonly known. For instance, it would be highly confusing to assert to my friend “I have a sister” or “It’s raining” to someone standing outside in the rain. In these cases, the hearers could challenge the appropriateness of my assertions by responding something like “Why do you say that? I already know that!” It is even harder to imagine how one could lie with such obviously true statements.Footnote 4

INFORMATIVENESS is also satisfied by views that extend the possibility of lying beyond assertions. Recently, the case has been made for the possibility of lying with conventional implicatures and presuppositions.Footnote 5 Crucially, conventional implicatures are, just like standard assertions, first and foremost informative speech acts. The content of presuppositions, on the other hand, is standardly taken for granted and so presuppositions are uninformative acts. However, they can sometimes be used to convey a new piece of information. Crucially, all cases of presuppositional lies recorded in the literature are based on informative presuppositions. In fact, so far, all analysed cases of lies were informative.

My main goal is to argue against INFORMATIVENESS. By focusing on presuppositions, I show that standard, uninformative cases of presuppositions are suitable vehicles for lying. I then propose how this argument generalises to other uninformative speech acts. As a result, lying in general is not restricted to informative speech acts. The plan is as follows. I start with a short introduction to a default kind of lies, i.e., those made with assertions. I discuss the idea of informativeness of assertions and how it relates to lies. I also discuss the criteria of lying that I will use throughout the paper. Secondly, I review available arguments for lying with informative presuppositions. I show that presuppositions are suitable for lying. Thus, I argue against ASSERTION-ONLY. Thirdly, I make a case for lying with uninformative presuppositions. I show that such presuppositions can generate the same intuitions as informative ones. This goes against INFORMATIVENESS. In the final part, I extend my argument to uninformative lies made by declarative statements. Thus, I show that the phenomenon of uninformative lies is widespread and should not be neglected. Finally, I conclude by pointing at the consequences of my view.

2. Lying with assertions

Consider the following case of lying (Stokke Reference Stokke2016, 85):

Paul’s party

Dennis is going to Paul’s party tonight. He has a long day of work ahead of him before that, but he is very excited and can’t wait to get there. Dennis’s annoying friend Rebecca comes up to him and starts talking about the party. Dennis is fairly sure that Rebecca won’t go unless she thinks he’s going, too. Rebecca asks Dennis: “Are you going to Paul’s party?”

Version A:

(1) Dennis: No, I’m not going to Paul’s party.

Version B:

(2) Dennis: I have to work.

Rebecca comes to believe that Dennis is not going to Paul’s party.

(1) is considered to be a lie, while (2) is merely misleading. One of the main criteria of a proper definition of lying is its ability to distinguish lying from misleading statements. As an example, take Stokke’s (Reference Stokke2018) definition of lying, which is based on a Stalnakerian (Reference Stalnaker, Munitz and Unger1974, Reference Stalnaker and Cole1978) theory of assertion:

Stokke’s definition of lying

A lies to B if and only if there is a proposition p such that

(L1) A says that p to B, and

(L2) A proposes to make it common ground that p, and

(L3) A believes that p is false.

Stokke’s definition satisfies both the aforementioned assumptions. Conditions (L1) and (L2) specify what it means to make an assertion and (L3) provides an insincerity condition. Thus, Stokke argues that lies are just insincere assertions. All examples of lies that Stokke provides are informative and, more importantly, INFORMATIVENESS follows from his definition. By his definition, (1) is a lie because Dennis says that he will not go to Paul’s party and does not believe it, while (2) is not a lie because Dennis only implies that he will not go. Thus, Stokke’s definition delivers the correct verdict.

Since INFORMATIVENESS is a crucial assumption behind Stokke’s definition, let me expand on the idea that assertions are essentially informative speech acts.Footnote 6 First of all, consider that many accounts of assertion propose a similar condition for a proper assertion, i.e., a proper assertion that p is such that p is not already common knowledge (for Searle [1969, 66], this is one of the “preparatory conditions” for asserting; for Stalnaker [1978, 88–89 in 1999], this is the first “principle” about assertion; and for Farkas [2022, 326], this is one of the “default contextual assumptions characterising canonical assertions”). These theories maintain that it is infelicitous to assert a proposition that already belongs to the common ground.

Here are three further observations that corroborate the informativeness of assertions. Firstly, as mentioned in the introduction, there are unique conversational patterns that point to the informativeness of assertions, i.e., one can be criticised for asserting something that is commonly known (García-Carpintero Reference García-Carpintero and Bianchi2004). For instance, if after saying (1), Dennis would come to Rebecca and just repeat (1), she could rightly criticise him by saying “I already know that,” or “I know. You already told me that!” This shows that there is something improper and defective in uninformative assertions.

Secondly, there is an intriguing analogy between assertions and inquiries, i.e., inquiries can be seen as a reverse of assertions. Just as assertions are a default way of using a declarative mood, inquiries are a default way of using an interrogative mood. Further, just as assertions are essentially informative speech acts, inquiries are information-seeking speech acts—when asking a question, we expect to be informed. Finally, just as it is improper to assert information that is already commonly known, it is also improper to inquire when one already knows the answer. In short, while assertions are non-inquisitive and informative, inquiries are non-informative and inquisitive (Moyer and Syrett Reference Moyer and Syrett2021; Farkas Reference Farkas2022).Footnote 7

Finally, consider the relationship between assertions and uninformative speech acts. It is improper to reassert the same content; however, such content can be reintroduced by means of uninformative speech acts, like reminding, or other types of content, like presuppositions.Footnote 8 Thus, it is improper for Dennis to reassert (1), but he can state the same content by reminding Rebecca that he will not come or by presupposing it. I will discuss such cases in detail in the subsequent sections.Footnote 9

There are certain widely recognised criteria or tests for lying. Following them allows us to separate lying from misleading without relying on a certain definition of lying. For the present purposes, I will be using two. The first one is the so-called “deniability criterion.”Footnote 10 It states that lies cannot be sincerely and consistently denied, only misleading statements can. In other words, whenever one does not lie but is merely misleading, one retains a plausible way to deny the accusation of lying. Thus, after saying (2), Dennis can respond something like this (Viebahn Reference Viebahn2020, 733):

(3) I didn’t lie. I didn’t claim that I wasn’t going to go to Paul’s party. I merely claimed that I had to work, which I did.

Viebahn acknowledges that (3) may seem pedantic, but it is consistent with Dennis’s earlier statement. By contrast, Dennis is lying in (1) because he cannot consistently deny the content of (1). Consider that saying (4) does not work:

(4) #I didn’t lie. I didn’t claim that I’m not going to Paul’s party.

The second criterion is based on the observation of how assertions and lies are reported (see Holton Reference Holton2019). It is not strictly speaking a test of lying (like the deniability criterion), but it helps make our intuitions about lying clearer. A proper way for reporting assertions is with a that-clause, but this does not work for lies. Consider the following:

(5) Dennis said that he will not go to Paul’s party.

(6) #Dennis lied that he will not go to Paul’s party.

(5) sounds natural and correctly represents the state of affairs. (6), however, sounds bad. The natural way of reporting lies is with about-clauses:

(7) Dennis lied about not going to Paul’s party.

(8) #Dennis lied about having to work.

(7) correctly reflects what is going on in this case: by saying (1), Dennis lies to Rebecca about the fact that he is not going to the party. (8), on the other hand, is an infelicitous report since Dennis indeed had a lot of work. Thus, reporting (2) by an about-clause in (8) is a way of framing our intuitions and allows us to see that (2) is not a lie.

3. Lying with presuppositions

Let us focus on presuppositions. A presupposition is a piece of information that is taken for granted and commonly accepted. For instance, (9)–(10) presuppose the same thing, namely, that John owns a Mercedes. The difference between these cases is that the presupposition is carried by different triggers (i.e., factive verb and definite description, respectively):

(9) I know that John owns a Mercedes.

(10) John’s Mercedes is new and shiny.Footnote 11

Presuppositions can be informative. Thus, I can introduce the information that John owns a Mercedes to my audience by presupposing this fact. If my audience notices that I presuppose a new piece of information, they can accept and accommodate it. Such a process is called presupposition accommodation.Footnote 12 Crucially, all cases of presuppositional lies discussed in literature are based on this process (see Meibauer Reference Meibauer2014; Viebahn Reference Viebahn2020; Viebahn et al. Reference Viebahn, Wiegmann, Engelmann and Willemsen2021). Take the following example (Viebahn Reference Viebahn2020, 735):

Mercedes I

Harry wants Rosa to think that his friend John is wealthy. In fact, John is not wealthy and does not own a car, as Harry knows very well. Harry asks Rosa:

(11) Did you know that John owns a Mercedes?

Rosa comes to believe that John owns a Mercedes.

(11) is a clear case of a presuppositional lie. In this example, Harry on purpose presupposes something he believes to be false. The criteria of lying deliver clear results here. Harry cannot sincerely and consistently deny presupposing that John owns a Mercedes. Saying something like (12) does not work (Viebahn Reference Viebahn2020, 735):

(12) #I didn’t lie. I didn’t claim that John owns a Mercedes.

Some might disagree with Viebahn’s judgment here and feel that (12) may not be quite as bad as (4). This is why it is good to consult also the second criterion. Harry’s presupposition can be naturally reported in the following way:

(13) Harry lied about John owning a Mercedes.

Thus, we have at least prima facie reasons for accepting the possibility of lying with presuppositions.

Viebahn (Reference Viebahn2020, 735–36), commenting on this case, makes three further points. Firstly, there seems to be no relevant difference between Harry’s presupposition made in (11) and asserting the same information, as in (14):

(14) John owns a Mercedes. Did you know that?

Secondly, ordinary speakers strongly agree that Harry lies in (11). In an experimental study (Viebahn et al. Reference Viebahn, Wiegmann, Engelmann and Willemsen2021), stories like this received lie ratings of around 90 percent (Mercedes I included). The results remained on this level even when participants could classify these cases as not being lies, but merely misleading. Finally, even though presuppositional content is always carried by a certain speech act, it is important that (11) is a question. So, we cannot say that the lie is asserted. The content of questions is a set of propositions (see, e.g., Cross and Roelofsen Reference Cross, Roelofsen and Zalta2020) and it is not suitable for lying. Thus, the only content in (11) that can be evaluated as a lie is presupposed.Footnote 13

The presupposition in (11) is triggered by a factive verb. Before considering in detail how we can lie with presuppositions, consider one more case with a different trigger (Viebahn Reference Viebahn2020, 738):

Baby I

Gertrude and Mick are colleagues of Jack, whose wife has recently given birth to a baby boy. Gertrude has seen the baby and knows it is a boy. She knows that Mick hasn’t seen the baby and wants to trick him into thinking that John’s baby is a girl. Gertrude says to Mick:

(15) Jack’s baby is lovely. Have you seen her yet?

Mick comes to believe that Jack’s baby is a girl.

(15) triggers the presupposition (by employing a gendered pronoun) that Jack’s baby is a girl. Just as in the case of (11), this presupposition passes both criteria of lying. On the one hand, Gertrude cannot sincerely deny the presupposition made in (15). (16) sounds unnatural:

(16) #I didn’t lie. I didn’t claim that Jack’s baby is a girl.

Just as (12), (16) seems to contradict the original statement made in (15) and hence sounds improper. On the other hand, Gertrude’s lie can be properly reported:

(17) Gertrude lied about the gender of Jack’s baby.

These two cases seem to provide an argument against ASSERTION-ONLY but are consistent with INFORMATIVENESS. In the rest of this section, I want to consider the question of why presuppositions are suitable for lying.

There are many ways of capturing the content of presuppositions. One take is to treat presuppositions as speaker commitments. It means that by presupposing p, one commits to the truth of the presupposed content and cannot deny it without contradicting oneself. For example, if Harry asks Rosa “Did you know that John owns a Mercedes?”, he cannot later deny that John owns a Mercedes without contradicting himself. Interestingly, the degree of speaker commitment is similar in presupposed and asserted contents (Mazzarella et al. Reference Mazzarella, Reinecke, Noveck and Mercier2018; Reins and Wiegmann Reference Reins and Wiegmann2021). However, while assertions contribute to at-issue content because they are a primary contribution in a context, presuppositions standardly contribute to non-at-issue content because their content is backgrounded (Simons et al. Reference Simons, Tonhauser, Beaver and Roberts2010). Because of that, presuppositions are subsidiary speaker commitments (Peters Reference Peters2016). The situation slightly complicates when we consider informative presuppositions. They can have the same effects on the conversational background as assertions (see, e.g., Gauker Reference Gauker2008), however, they are distinct from assertions since only the latter are directly communicated (Kissine and Pantazi Reference Kissine and Pantazi2020).Footnote 14

Can a definition of lying capture presuppositional lies? Stokke’s definition does not classify (11) and (15) as lies, for in neither case one says something one believes to be false. Stokke (Reference Stokke2017) explicitly argues that presuppositions cannot be lies for a simple reason: lies must be said, presuppositions are not, so they cannot be lies.Footnote 15 This is very problematic since both cases pass the criteria of lying and Stokke himself follows the deniability criterion. Furthermore, as I just indicated, at least in some contexts, presuppositions can be as committal as assertions. In both cases, the speaker commits to the communicated content. For this reason, some have proposed defining lying in terms of commitment.Footnote 16 Viebahn (Reference Viebahn2020, 743) recently proposed a commitment-based definition of lying that aims to capture presuppositional lies:

A commitment-based definition of lying

A lies to B if and only if there is a proposition p such that:

(L1) A performs a communicative act C addressed to B with the content p;

(L2) by performing C, A commits herself to p; and

(L3) A believes that p is false.

Viebahn (Reference Viebahn2020) explicates the notion of commitment by appealing to pretheoretical intuitions that are captured, among others, by the deniability criterion, i.e., if one commits to certain content, then one cannot consistently deny it without contradicting oneself. In his (2021, 307), he relies even more strongly on this criterion since the notion of commitment in lying is defined in terms of it. In the next section, I will discuss Viebahn’s view on presuppositional lies, but now, even without going into details, it can be seen that his definition is able to explain all cases discussed so far. Just as Dennis lies in (1), it is equally so for Harry in (11), and Gertrude in (15). They are lying because each of them commits to p and believes that p is false. All of these cases meet INFORMATIVENESS. In the next sections, I will expand the realm of possibilities of lying into uninformative cases.

4. Lying with uninformative presuppositions

Take the following extension of the Mercedes case:

Mercedes II

Harry wants Rosa to think that his friend John is wealthy. In fact, John is not wealthy and does not own a car, as Harry knows very well. Harry asks Rosa:

(11) Did you know that John owns a Mercedes?

Rosa comes to believe that John owns a Mercedes. Later on that day, Rosa asks Harry about John and Harry says:

(18) John’s Mercedes is new and shiny.

The original story remains intact. What is different is the repetition of the presupposition from (11) in (18). However, this added presupposition is an uninformative one because Rosa already believes that John owns a Mercedes. Stating this presupposition again does not weaken Harry’s commitment, rather it can reinforce this presupposition. To answer the question of whether (18) is a lie, consider the familiar criteria. Just as before, Harry cannot consistently deny claiming that John owns a Mercedes and (18) can be naturally reported as lying about John owning a Mercedes.Footnote 17

The presupposition in (18) is triggered differently than in (11), i.e., by possessive construction. However, this only shows that lying is not restricted to a particular presupposition trigger. Instead of a declarative like (18), Harry could make any other statement that fits the context (for instance, an imperative utterance, “You must see John’s new Mercedes!”).

Uninformative lies can be characterised as lies with content that is already common ground. To emphasise, I am interested in cases of uninformative lies that will not be challenged as inappropriate.Footnote 18 In principle, Harry can reassert to Rosa that John owns a Mercedes, but then he can be rightly criticised for making an uninformative assertion—Rosa could object and respond something like “You already told me that!” However, it is perfectly natural to presuppose this information again and again (as in Mercedes II). In general, when lying, we do not want to be recognised as liars, and when our statement is challenged, as being in some sense inappropriate, we raise suspicion. Thus, an uninformative lie should be performed by means of a speech act that can transfer information that was already stated before. Presuppositions are a natural candidate for such cases because they are standardly treated as delivering already-known information. While one may presuppose information that is already commonly known, one cannot do so with assertions. This follows from an observation that “when it is correct to presuppose p, it is incorrect to assert it” (García-Carpintero Reference García-Carpintero2020, 23).

It is worth noting that an initial lie can be made by uttering various speech acts, granted that they are suitable for lying. The options are not limited to assertions. In the introduction, I mentioned the possibility of lying with conventional implicatures.Footnote 19 Thus, take Mercedes I or II and consider that instead of the first statement (11), Harry can communicate the same information by asserting (19) or conventionally implicating (20):

(19) John owns a Mercedes. Did you know that?

(20) John, who owns a Mercedes, is very handsome.

Once it is communicated that John owns a Mercedes, it is inappropriate to assert or conventionally implicate it again. Thus, (19) and (20) cannot be used as uninformative lies.

Before discussing some implications of lying with uninformative presuppositions, consider one more feature of uninformative lies. This time take the Baby I case with a minor alteration:

Baby II

Gertrude, Lily, and Mick are colleagues of Jack, whose wife has recently given birth to a baby boy. Gertrude and Lily have seen the baby and know it is a boy. They know that Mick hasn’t seen the baby and want to trick him into thinking that Jack’s baby is a girl. Gertrude says to Mick:

(15) Jack’s baby is lovely. Have you seen her yet?

Mick comes to believe that Jack’s baby is a girl. During the conversation, Mick inquires about Jack’s baby and Lily says

(21) She is very playful.

In this version, the uninformative lie is made by a different person than the initial lie. Everything else stays the same, i.e., in both cases, one presupposes something one believes to be false. Crucially, (21) carries an uninformative presupposition. Just as (15), it passes our criteria of lying. Lily cannot consistently deny claiming that Jack’s baby is a girl and we can naturally report her lie as lying about the gender of Jack’s baby.Footnote 20 Moreover, when the same lie is not only repeated (like in Mercedes II) but is also made by various speakers it is reinforced even further, and thus it can be more compelling to the hearer to accept the presupposition. This shows that uninformative lies can be made in complex contexts and performed by multiple agents.

Let us return to the definition of lying. We saw that Viebahn’s (Reference Viebahn2020) view captures informative presuppositions. What about uninformative ones? His definition seems to not make a difference between them. For him, lying about p is basically committing to p while believing that p is false. It is instructive to discuss his views on presuppositional lies both in his (2020) and (2021) papers. Viebahn repeatedly distances himself from the possibility of accepting lying with uninformative content. His argument rests on the idea that in uninformative cases, one does not commit to p and thus one is not lying. We can extract two parts of his argument. The first one states that presuppositional lies are assertions and the second that uninformative presuppositions cannot be lies. Let us consider them in turn.

For Viebahn, all analysed cases of “presuppositional lies are assertions” (Reference Viebahn2020, 744). He observes that “the commitment in lying can plausibly be seen as the commitment in asserting” (Reference Viebahn2020, 743), and he directly states that “[l]ying involves the committal speech act of asserting” (Reference Viebahn2021, 307). He says that because he wants to marry two ideas, i.e., that we can lie with presuppositions and that lying is restricted to assertions. Thus, he tries to keep both ASSERTION-ONLY and INFORMATIVENESS. His reasoning can be summarised in the following way: the traditional definitions of lying maintain that all lies are assertions, the newly presented cases involving presuppositions are lies too, thus, we must accept that presuppositional lies are assertions.

Consider the implications of Viebahn’s view to the debates on assertion and presupposition. If Viebahn is right that the presented cases of presuppositions are assertions, then the classical definitions of assertion and presupposition are wrong. Many definitions of assertions have the so-called explicitness condition built-in, according to which, an assertion is a speech act that is explicitly presented (see, e.g., Alston Reference Alston2000). This condition aims precisely at distinguishing between assertoric content that is at-issue and non-assertoric content that is not-at-issue; presuppositions or conventional implicatures belong to the latter. We have an analogical situation with definitions of presupposition where one of their main aims is to separate what is asserted from what is presupposed.

Viebahn’s critique of all these views rests on the view that all lies are assertions. However, the fact that we can lie with presuppositions can simply be interpreted as working against the standard definition of lying, and so against ASSERTION-ONLY. In fact, this was already pointed out by Meibauer (Reference Meibauer2014). Moreover, Viebahn assumes the primacy of the definition of lying over the analogical definitions of assertion and presupposition. I do not see why. Take the explicitness condition in a definition of assertion. Viebahn (Reference Viebahn2020, 744–45) criticises such a condition since it disqualifies presuppositions from assertions. However, this is precisely the point of such a condition. The same can be said about defining presuppositions. There is widespread agreement among philosophers and linguists that asserting and presupposing are distinct ways of expressing content.Footnote 21 Viebahn needs more to undermine this distinction than just referring to the traditional definition of lying. Thus, I do not see good reasons to accept Viebahn’s view that presuppositional lies are assertions.

What about Viebahn’s view that there is a difference in commitment between informative and uninformative cases? This is what he says:

… there are different ways of committing oneself to a proposition: one can commit to p by saying p, but (in at least some situations) one can also do so by presupposing p, e.g. if p was not previously accepted in the conversation… . it seems plausible that speakers are not always committed to what they presuppose. For example, if a speaker goes along with a presupposition that is already part of the common ground, then she may not be committing herself to it. (Reference Viebahn2020, 743)

In both parts of this quotation, Viebahn seems to say that one commits to presuppositions if they are informative, but it is possible to not commit to presuppositions when they are uninformative. In fact, the latter is repeated throughout the article. Here I want to focus on Mercedes II and Baby II, which are cases of lying with uninformative presuppositions. In the last quoted statement, Viebahn entertains a case like Baby II, where Lily goes along with the presupposition that is already part of the common ground. By this view, such cases are not necessarily committal. But if they are not committal, they cannot be lies. However, from the context, it is clear that Lily is lying. In Mercedes II, it does not really make sense to say that Harry commits to what he presupposes only the first time.

In his (2021, 300), Viebahn adds one more condition to his definition of lying, i.e., an intention to communicate p to the hearer. This condition, Viebahn suggests, can be fleshed out in a Stalnakerian framework where a communicative intention p is an intention to propose p as an update to the common ground. I already mentioned, when discussing Stokke’s definition, that the common ground view treats assertions as informative speech acts, and hence accepts INFORMATIVENESS. This reasoning can be seen in the following condition that Viebahn formulates: “… agents do not intend to communicate p … if they presuppose p while taking p to be common ground” (Reference Viebahn2021, 301). Consider again the second presuppositions in Mercedes II and Baby II; Harry and Lily satisfy Viebahn’s condition, i.e., they presuppose something that they know is already a part of the common ground, which excludes the possibility of lying. However, intuitively they do lie. This condition is important because it is formulated in a more direct way than in (Reference Viebahn2020). In both cases, the result is the same. Viebahn’s view precludes the possibility of lying with uninformative content.

The upshot is that presuppositional lies are not reducible to assertions, and thus we must drop ASSERTION-ONLY. Moreover, restricting lies to informative presuppositions, as Viebahn proposes, is untenable. Uninformative presuppositions are just as good vehicles for lying as informative ones.Footnote 22 Notice that Viebahn’s commitment-based definition of lying, or similar definitions of lying formulated in commitment terms,Footnote 23 can account for the presented cases. All that must be done is dropping the requirement of informativeness. In the next section, I expand the picture of uninformative lies to lies made by declarative statements, i.e., to such speech acts as reminding or guaranteeing.

5. Lying with uninformative speech acts

We can lie with all speech acts that entail the illocutionary force of assertion (see, e.g., Marsili Reference Marsili2020; Viebahn Reference Viebahn2021). This should extend the possibility of lying to speech acts whose commitment is at least as strong as in the case of assertions, thus to such speech acts as warning, guaranteeing, or swearing. Although for different reasons, both Marsili (Reference Marsili2020) and Viebahn (Reference Viebahn2021) argue that the aforementioned speech acts are assertions. Thus, when I warn or guarantee you that p I do that by asserting that p. The conclusion is a familiar one, i.e., if lying is restricted to assertions, the above cases are informative speech acts.

I propose to expand this picture by discussing two types of uninformative speech acts. Firstly, there are unique speech acts that are uninformative by design. Secondly, some speech acts can be both informative and uninformative, depending on the context. I will argue that both types of speech acts are suitable for lying.Footnote 24

A paradigmatic case of a uniquely uninformative speech act is the speech act of reminding. Here is a standard case. By reminding you about the dentist appointment, I indicate that this piece of information has already been in the common ground, but I have a reason to believe you might have forgotten about it. Various speech act taxonomies classify reminding either as a special case of assertion or as a distinct speech act type (see, e.g., Searle and Vanderveken Reference Searle and Vanderveken1985; Alston Reference Alston2000). What matters for the present discussion is that reminding does not provide a new piece of information into the common ground (Abbot Reference Abbott2008; cf. Stalnaker Reference Stalnaker2008; Clapp Reference Clapp and Goldberg2020).Footnote 25 Looking from the perspective of informativeness of assertion, it is natural to treat reminding as a distinct speech act type from assertions. This is not a merely taxonomical issue. If assertions are essentially informative speech acts, uninformative assertions are incorrect. Thus, if reminders are assertions, they are in some sense incorrect. However, this is not the case. It is correct and perfectly natural to remind you about your dentist appointment.Footnote 26

Having said that, consider how we can lie by reminding something. We need only a small alteration in the already familiar case:

Mercedes III

Harry wants Rosa to think that his friend John is wealthy. In fact, John is not wealthy and does not own a car, as Harry knows very well. Harry asks Rosa:

(11) Did you know that John owns a Mercedes?

Rosa comes to believe that John owns a Mercedes. Later on that day, Rosa asks Harry about John and Harry says:

(22) Just wanted to remind you that John owns a Mercedes.

If (22) for someone does not sound natural enough, it can be modified accordingly. Rosa can also explicitly ask Harry, “Can you remind me what car John owns?” and thus elicit a reminder as a response. Reminding passes the familiar criteria of lying. Harry cannot consistently deny claiming that John owns a Mercedes and his reminding can be naturally reported as lying about John owning a Mercedes. Crucially, (22) is an uninformative statement.Footnote 27

The second group of speech acts that can be used as uninformative lies contain speech acts that can be both informative and uninformative. I illustrate it with the speech act of guaranteeing. We rarely use speech acts with stronger commitment than assertions. It is broadly accepted that in asserting that p we represent ourselves as knowing that p (e.g., Williamson Reference Williamson1996). This is sufficient for most communicative contexts. However, sometimes context requires holding a stronger position or we want to indicate that our position is stronger than knowledge (say, we want to show that we are certain, or emphasise that we do know what we say). For instance, if I want to learn how to dive and know that you have some experience but do not know how substantial your experience is, you can either assert that you are a certified trainer or guarantee it to reassure me that I am safe with you. In both cases, you convey the same information.

One way to theorise about guaranteeing is to treat it as a speech act that reinforces an assertion (e.g., Turri Reference Turri2013). Thus, I can firstly assert that p, and later on, guarantee that p. Guaranteeing in this sense does not deliver new information, rather it repeats and reinforces the content that was already stated.Footnote 28 Having said that, consider a case of lying by guaranteeing.

Mercedes IV

Harry wants Rosa to think that his friend John is wealthy. In fact, John is not wealthy and does not own a car, as Harry knows very well. Harry asks Rosa:

(11) Did you know that John owns a Mercedes?

Rosa comes to believe that John owns a Mercedes. But remembering that she saw John at a bus stop the other day, she inquiries further about John and his car. Harry responds by saying:

(23) I guarantee you that John owns a Mercedes.

By repeating the same information in (23), Harry commits even stronger to the truth of this proposition than by presupposing it in (11). Notice that, just as in the case of reminding, there are more options to express guaranteeing. One is by saying “I know that p” (Austin Reference Austin1946; cf. Turri Reference Turri2013), as in “I know that John owns a Mercedes.” Finally, (23) passes the tests of lying. Here too Harry cannot consistently deny the content of (23) and his guaranteeing can be reported as lying about John owning a Mercedes.Footnote 29

There are more speech acts that can be used uninformatively. Instead of (23), Harry can utter (24) or (25) which are also clear cases of lying:Footnote 30

(24) I assure you that John owns a Mercedes.

(25) I swear that John owns a Mercedes.

As a final note, consider what Viebahn and Stokke have to say about the analysed cases. Neither of them engages in the discussion of whether lying is possible with uninformative content. Viebahn argues that one does not commit to p if p already is a part of the common ground (Reference Viebahn2020, 743). This equally concerns the content that is presupposed, reminded, or guaranteed. Stokke’s view gives a different verdict to uninformative lies that are made with presuppositions and declarative statements. He explicitly argues against counting presuppositions as lies (Reference Stokke2017, Reference Stokke2018) because presuppositions are not said (in the relevant sense, see section 2). The content of (22)–(25) is said,Footnote 31 thus these statements should be considered lies. However, Stokke follows Stalnaker in defining an assertion as a proposal to update the common ground. The content of (22)–(25) cannot update the common ground since this content already belongs to the common ground.Footnote 32 Thus, Stokke’s view predicts that (22)–(25) should be infelicitous. However, these statements are perfectly appropriate to make. Thus, Stokke’s definition delivers wrong predictions to lies made by uninformative declarative statements.

6. Conclusions

My main aim was to make a case for lying with uninformative speech acts. Firstly, by showing that we can lie with presuppositions, I argued that lying is not restricted to assertions. Secondly, I made a case for the possibility of lying with uninformative presuppositions. This created the space of extending the domain of uninformative lies to other speech acts, for which I have argued in the final section. By arguing for uninformative lies, either made by presuppositions or by declarative statements, I wanted to point at a so far neglected phenomenon of lying with content that is already common ground. This revealed a crucial assumption behind some prominent definitions of lying. As it is widely assumed, lies are insincere assertions. But how an assertion should be understood is not always explicitly presented. I focused on one aspect of assertions, i.e, their informativeness. This discussion shows that more research has to be done into our understanding of the division between informative and uninformative content, and how it influences the concept of lying.

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to two anonymous referees for this journal, and to J. P. Grodniewicz, Emar Maier, and Neri Marsili for very helpful comments and discussion.

Grzegorz Gaszczyk is a PhD candidate at the University of Groningen. His main research interests lie in speech act normativity, theories of assertion, lying, and various forms of insincerity.

Footnotes

1 See, e.g., Isenberg (Reference Isenberg1964); Primoratz (Reference Primoratz1984); Mahon (Reference Mahon2008); Lackey (Reference Lackey2013).

3 This assumption follows from Stokke’s and Viebahn’s definitions of lying; I will discuss these accounts in the next sections. Moreover, it is endorsed even by those rare views that do not fully accept the first assumption; see, e.g., Meibauer (Reference Meibauer2014).

4 Benton (Reference Benton2018) and Marsili (Reference Marsili2022) arguing for a graded notion of belief mix up an example that may seem to be an uninformative lie. Suppose that (i) Mary is certain that p (Bob has a car), (ii) Bob knows that she is certain that p and he tells her that p, (iii) Bob doesn’t have a car. The suggested reading is that Bob’s assertion (and lie) is uninformative because when he asserts that p to Mary, she is already certain that p. I see two interpretations of such cases, neither discussed by Benton and Marsili. The first is that Mary does not know that Bob knows that she is certain that p (this is not common knowledge between them). Here Bob’s assertion is informative since it changes the common ground. The second option is that p was already common ground between them before Bob’s assertion that p. Thus, p is an uninformative assertion. According to informative accounts of assertion, such assertion is improper and can be challenged by Mary. The idea behind proposing an example of an uninformative lie is to show that we can make an uninformative lie that will not be immediately challenged for its inappropriateness. Crucially, as I will show, uttering p again can be achieved not by asserting it but, for instance, by presupposing or reminding.

5 For both, see Meibauer (Reference Meibauer2014) and Viebahn (Reference Viebahn2020, Reference Viebahn2021). Stokke (Reference Stokke2017) and Sorensen (Reference Sorensen2017) restrict this possibility to conventional implicatures; Siegler (Reference Siegler1966) mentions the possibility of lying with presuppositions.

6 I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging me to clarify this point.

7 For a discussion of assertions and inquiries in the context of constitutive norms, see, e.g., Whitcomb (Reference Whitcomb2017), Gaszczyk (Reference GaszczykManuscript, cf. Reference GaszczykForthcoming).

8 As noted in Footnote footnote 4, one can reassert the same content and thus lie by means of it, but such lies are in direct violation of the informativeness of assertion and thus open to criticism.

9 Even though my focus is on informativeness of assertions, the condition of informativeness has been also ascribed to non-assertoric speech acts, for a discussion see, e.g., Searle (Reference Searle1969).

10 See, e.g., Saul (Reference Saul2012); Stokke (Reference Stokke2016, Reference Stokke2018); Viebahn (Reference Viebahn2017, Reference Viebahn2020, Reference Viebahn2021); and van Elswyk (Reference van Elswyk2020). For a discussion of the limitations of this criterion, see, e.g., Peet (Reference Peet2015); García-Carpintero (Reference García-Carpintero2018, Reference García-Carpintero2021).

11 An anonymous reviewer rightly notes that the presuppositions of (9) and (10) are distinct from each other, i.e., the presupposition of the possessive construction in (10) is not specifically about the relation of ownership. For simplicity, here and later on, this difference can be ignored.

12 For more on presuppositions see, e.g., Beaver, Geurts, and Denlinger (Reference Beaver, Geurts and Denlinger2021).

13 There are many real-life examples of presuppositional lies. Consider this tweet of Donald Trump from February 3, 2017, in which he presupposes that there were paid protesters: “Professional anarchists, thugs and paid protesters are proving the point of the millions of people who voted to MAKE AMERICA GREAT AGAIN!” By the proposed criteria, if Trump did not believe that there were paid protesters, he lied.

14 This crucial difference can also be captured in speech act terms. García-Carpintero (Reference García-Carpintero2020) proposes to treat presuppositions as ancillary speech acts that are governed by the common knowledge norm: one’s presupposition p is felicitous only if it is common knowledge that p. Informative presuppositions, in this view, are treated as indirect speech acts.

15 This is a challenge for all says-based definitions of lying, i.e., definitions that define lying in terms of what is said or what is explicitly communicated, apart from Stokke, see, e.g., Carson (Reference Carson2006); Sorensen (Reference Sorensen2007); Fallis (Reference Fallis2009); and Saul (Reference Saul2012).

16 See, e.g., Viebahn (Reference Viebahn2020, Reference Viebahn2021); Marsili (Reference Marsili2020); Reins and Wiegmann (Reference Reins and Wiegmann2021); cf. García-Carpintero (Reference García-Carpintero2021).

17 An anonymous reviewer notices that the intuitions regarding the report of Harry’s lie may vary. Strictly speaking, a natural report of Harry’s lie would be as lying about John’s Mercedes being new and shiny. However, (18) is made in a specific context in which it is preceded by (11), and so when Harry says (18) Rosa already assumes that John owns the Mercedes. Thus, his second lie may be reported as lying about John owning a Mercedes.

18 I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging me to clarify this point.

19 In short, conventional implicatures are considered to be secondary assertions, i.e., assertions that are not-at-issue (Potts Reference Potts2005). However, just as ordinary assertions, they are said. Because of that, they are considered lies even by some proponents of says-based definitions of lying, see, e.g., Stokke (Reference Stokke2017).

20 (21) is analogous to (18). See Footnote footnote 17.

21 For an overview, see, e.g., Pagin and Marsili (Reference Pagin and Marsili2021), and Beaver, Geurts, and Denlinger (Reference Beaver, Geurts and Denlinger2021).

22 The question which presuppositions are committal deserves a separate discussion, but it seems that not all presuppositions are committal, and thus we can presuppose something that we believe to be false without lying. For instance, Stalnaker (Reference Stalnaker1999, 100) gives an example of uninformative presupposition that is false but irrelevant—it is made just to facilitate communication. Noncommittal presuppositions can also be informative, which is shown by Donnellan’s famous Martini case where one presupposes something one believes to be false (by using a definite description “the man drinking the martini”) without lying. There is thus the need to separate committal from noncommittal presuppositions. One way of accounting for such cases is to argue that one lacks commitment in these cases and thus cannot lie. An alternative is to propose that in those cases one lacks an intention to deceive. For a discussion of such cases, see Gaszczyk (Reference Gaszczyk2023, chap. 5).

The other issue that concerns lying with presuppositions is considering how different presupposition triggers influence the strength of the commitment. Presuppositional triggers can be classified along many dimensions, for instance, strong versus weak (Glanzberg Reference Glanzberg, Preyer and Peter2005). Strong triggers (like factive verbs) carry a high level of commitment that can entail, for example, less chance of plausible deniability. On the other hand, weak triggers (such as additive particles, like again), in some contexts, can carry such commitment that could allow for deniability. If presuppositional commitment is gradable in such a way, the open question is whether some weak presuppositions should be considered as lies. There is thus a possibility that not all presuppositions are suitable candidates for lying. I leave this issue for future research. For a gradable notion of commitment in lying, see, e.g., Marsili (Reference Marsili, Cantarini, Abraham and Leiss2014).

24 I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging me to elaborate on this point.

25 I do not claim that reminding or any other uninformative speech act is uninformative in every sense. My focus is on (un)informativeness on the level of content, i.e., whether p is already part of the common ground. Uninformative speech acts play a variety of functions, e.g., they reintroduce a particular topic, or focus our attention on a topic under discussion. Furthermore, repeating the same content can reassure the audience to act on its basis and commit the speaker even stronger to what is communicated.

26 Consider the following reason for treating reminding as a distinct speech act type. One of the widely accepted arguments for individuating speech acts comes from the observations of their conversational patterns. For instance, assertions can be challenged by the “How do you know?” question. Advocates of the knowledge norm of assertion (e.g., Williamson Reference Williamson1996) have a simple explanation for such a challenge: if knowledge is the norm of assertion, then asking for one’s knowledge is appropriate. Furthermore, I said that there are unique conversational patterns associated with informativeness of assertions. If assertions are informative speech acts, we can naturally explain why hearers can criticise us if we say something that is already known. Finally, consider reminding. We can, for instance, ask to be reminded of something (“Can you remind me when my dentist appointment is?”), or criticise someone for not doing so (“You should remind me about my appointment! You know how bad I am with remembering dates!”). These conversational patterns make sense only in contexts when information that is reminded of was previously asserted.

27 Reminding is merely an example of a speech act in which we can repeat information that already belongs to the common ground. Another example of an essentially uninformative speech act is confirming or corroborating. Imagine the context of Baby II, where one person lies and another is repeating the lie. Instead of presupposing the same content (the presupposition in Baby II was triggered by a gendered pronoun), the second speaker can corroborate what was already said (e.g., by saying “Yes, she is lovely”). Thanks to Manuel García-Carpintero for suggesting this example.

29 Another example of guaranteeing is provided by Turri (Reference Turri2010) in the discussion between invariantism and contextualism concerning knowledge ascriptions. Intuitively, in a “low-stakes” context, asserting that p is sufficient (as in the famous DeRose’s bank case, “The bank is open on Saturday mornings”), while in a “high-stakes” context it is not; with rising stakes, we seem to need more than flat-out assertions that p. Turri proposes that what is required in the high-stakes contexts is guaranteeing that p. Importantly, the content of both speech acts remains the same.

30 I discussed cases that can be used as uninformative lies. Although this matter is contextual, some declaratives cannot be used in this way. For instance, if I warned you or agreed with you, it seems inappropriate to warn or agree with you again. For more on lying with explicit performative statements, see Marsili (Reference Marsili2020).

31 At least by many accounts of explicit performatives, for a detailed discussion see, e.g., Marsili (Reference Marsili2021).

32 This is supported by the criterion that Stokke (Reference Stokke2018, 66) proposes, i.e., he suggests that we can test whether a particular proposition has been added to the common ground by asking whether it can be correctly presupposed. For instance, before uttering (22), Harry can correctly presuppose that John owns a Mercedes since this information already belongs to the common ground. Thus, since (22) is uninformative, it should be inappropriate.

References

Abbott, Barbara. 2008. “Presuppositions and Common Ground.” Linguistics and Philosophy 31 (5): 523–38. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-008-9048-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, William P. 2000. Illocutionary Acts and Sentence Meaning. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Austin, J. L. 1946. “Other Minds.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 20 (1): 148–87. https://doi.org/10.1093/aristoteliansupp/20.1.122.Google Scholar
Beaver, David I., Geurts, Bart, and Denlinger, Kristie. 2021. “Presupposition.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring), edited by Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/presupposition/.Google Scholar
Benton, Matthew A. 2018. “Lying, Accuracy and Credence.” Analysis 78 (2): 195–98. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/anx132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carson, Thomas L. 2006. “The Definition of Lying.” Noûs 40 (2): 284306. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0029-4624.2006.00610.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clapp, Lenny. 2020. “Stalnaker on the Essential Effect of Assertion.” In The Oxford Handbook of Assertion, edited by Goldberg, Sanford, 137. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780190675233.013.1.Google Scholar
Cross, Charles, and Roelofsen, Floris. 2020. “Questions.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall), edited by Zalta, Edward N.. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/questions/.Google Scholar
Fallis, Don. 2009. “What Is Lying?The Journal of Philosophy 106 (1): 2956. https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil200910612.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farkas, Donka. 2022. “Non-Intrusive Questions as a Special Type of Non-Canonical Questions.” Journal of Semantics 39 (February): 295337. https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffac001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
García-Carpintero, Manuel. 2004. “Assertion and the Semantics of Force-Makers.” In The Semantics/Pragmatics Distinction, edited by Bianchi, Claudia, 133–66. Stanford: CSLI Lecture Notes, 155.Google Scholar
García-Carpintero, Manuel. 2018. “Sneaky Assertions.” Philosophical Perspectives 32 (1): 188218. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpe.12116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
García-Carpintero, Manuel. 2020. “On the Nature of Presupposition: A Normative Speech Act Account.” Erkenntnis 85 (2): 269–93. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0027-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
García-Carpintero, Manuel. 2021. “Lying vs. Misleading: The Adverbial Account.” Intercultural Pragmatics 18 (3): 391413. https://doi.org/10.1515/ip-2021-2011.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaszczyk, Grzegorz. Forthcoming. “Norms of Speech Acts.” Studia Semiotyczne. Google Scholar
Gaszczyk, Grzegorz 2023. “Normativity and Lying with Non-Assertoric Speech Acts” (PhD diss., University of Groningen).Google Scholar
Gaszczyk, Grzegorz. Manuscript. “Interrogatives, Inquiries, and Exam Questions.”Google Scholar
Gauker, Christopher. 2008. “Against Accommodation: Heim, van Der Sandt, and the Presupposition Projection Problem.” Philosophical Perspectives 22 (1): 171205. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1520-8583.2008.00145.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glanzberg, Michael. 2005. “Presuppositions, Truth-Values, and Expressing Propositions.” In Contextualism in Philosophy: Knowledge, Meaning and Truth, edited by Preyer, Gerhard and Peter, Georg, 349–96. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Holton, Richard. 2019. “Lying About.” The Journal of Philosophy 116 (2): 99105. https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil201911625.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Isenberg, Arnold. 1964. “Deontology and the Ethics of Lying.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 24 (4): 463–80. https://doi.org/10.2307/2104756.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kissine, Mikhail, and Pantazi, Myrto. 2020. “Pragmatic Accommodation.” In The Wiley Blackwell Companion to Semantics, 116. American Cancer Society. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118788516.sem140.Google Scholar
Lackey, J. 2013. “Lies and Deception: An Unhappy Divorce.” Analysis 73 (2): 236–48. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/ant006.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahon, James Edwin. 2008. “Two Definitions of Lying.” International Journal of Applied Philosophy 22 (2): 211–30. https://doi.org/10.5840/ijap200822216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marsili, Neri. 2014. “Lying as a Scalar Phenomenon: Insincerity along the Certainty-Uncertainty Continuum.” In Studies in Language Companion Series, edited by Cantarini, Sibilla, Abraham, Werner, and Leiss, Elisabeth, 165:153–73. Amsterdam, Nether.: John Benjamins. https://doi.org/10.1075/slcs.165.09mar.Google Scholar
Marsili, Neri. 2020. “Lying, Speech Acts, and Commitment.” Synthese 199 (1–2): 3245–69. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02933-4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marsili, Neri. 2021. “Lies, Common Ground and Performative Utterances.” Erkenntnis (March). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00368-4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marsili, Neri. 2022. “Immoral Lies and Partial Beliefs.” Inquiry 61 (1): 117–27. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2019.1667865.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mazzarella, Diana, Reinecke, Robert, Noveck, Ira, and Mercier, Hugo. 2018. “Saying, Presupposing and Implicating: How Pragmatics Modulates Commitment.” Journal of Pragmatics 133 (August): 1527. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2018.05.009.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meibauer, Jörg. 2014. Lying at the Semantics-Pragmatics Interface. Boston: De Gruyter Mouton.10.1515/9781614510840CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moyer, Morgan C., and Syrett, Kristen. 2021. “The Study of Questions.” WIREs Cognitive Science 12 (1). https://doi.org/10.1002/wcs.1531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pagin, Peter. 2011. “Information and Assertoric Force.” In Assertion: New Philosophical Essays, edited by Brown, Jessica and Cappelen, Herman, 97136. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199573004.003.0005.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pagin, Peter, and Marsili, Neri. 2021. “Assertion.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter) edited by Edward N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/assertion/.Google Scholar
Peet, Andrew. 2015. “Testimony, Pragmatics, and Plausible Deniability.” Episteme 12 (1): 2951. https://doi.org/10.1017/epi.2014.31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peters, Stanley. 2016. “Speaker Commitments: Presupposition.” Semantics and Linguistic Theory 26 (December): 1083. https://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v26i0.3951.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Potts, Christopher. 2005. The Logic of Conventional Implicatures. Oxford Studies in Theoretical Linguistics 7. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199273829.001.0001.Google Scholar
Primoratz, Igor. 1984. “Lying and the ‘Methods of Ethics.’International Studies in Philosophy 16 (3): 3557. https://doi.org/10.5840/intstudphil198416353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reins, Louisa M., and Wiegmann, Alex. 2021. “Is Lying Bound to Commitment? Empirically Investigating Deceptive Presuppositions, Implicatures, and Actions.” Cognitive Science 45 (2). https://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12936.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Saul, Jennifer Mather. 2012. Lying, Misleading, and What Is Said: An Exploration in Philosophy of Language and in Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199603688.001.0001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, John R. 1969. Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139173438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, John R., and Vanderveken, Daniel. 1985. Foundations of Illocutionary Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Siegler, Frederick A. 1966. “Lying.” American Philosophical Quarterly 3 (2): 128–36.Google Scholar
Simons, Mandy, Tonhauser, Judith, Beaver, David, and Roberts, Craige. 2010. “What Projects and Why.” Proceedings of SALT 20: 309–27. https://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v20i0.2584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorensen, Roy. 2007. “Bald-Faced Lies! Lying without the Intent to Deceive.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88 (2): 251–64. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0114.2007.00290.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorensen, Roy. 2017. “I—Lucifer’s Logic Lesson: How to Lie with Arguments.” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 91 (1): 105–26. https://doi.org/10.1093/arisup/akw016.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert. 1974. “Pragmatic Presuppositions.” In Semantics and Philosophy, edited by Munitz, Milton K. and Unger, Peter K.. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert. 1978. “Assertion.” In Syntax and Semantics, Vol. 9, edited by Cole, P.. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert. 1999. Context and Content: Essays on Intentionality in Speech and Thought. Oxford Cognitive Science Series. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/0198237073.001.0001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert. 2008. “A Response to Abbott on Presupposition and Common Ground.” Linguistics and Philosophy 31 (5): 539–44. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-008-9047-9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stokke, Andreas. 2016. “Lying and Misleading in Discourse.” Philosophical Review 125 (1): 83134. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-3321731.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stokke, Andreas. 2017. “II—Conventional Implicature, Presupposition, and Lying.” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 91 (1): 127–47. https://doi.org/10.1093/arisup/akx004.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stokke, Andreas. 2018. Lying and Insincerity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/oso/9780198825968.001.0001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, John. 2010. “Epistemic Invariantism and Speech Act Contextualism.” Philosophical Review 119 (1): 7795. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-2009-026.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, John. 2013. “Knowledge Guaranteed.” Noûs 47 (3): 602–12. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0068.2011.00849.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Elswyk, Peter. 2020. “Deceiving without Answering.” Philosophical Studies 177 (5): 1157–73. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01239-7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Viebahn, Emanuel. 2017. “Non-Literal Lies.” Erkenntnis 82 (6): 1367–80. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-017-9880-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Viebahn, Emanuel. 2020. “Lying with Presuppositions.” Noûs 54 (3): 731–51. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Viebahn, Emanuel. 2021. “The Lying-Misleading Distinction: A Commitment-Based Approach.” The Journal of Philosophy 118 (6): 289319. https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil2021118621.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Viebahn, Emanuel, Wiegmann, Alexander, Engelmann, Neele, and Willemsen, Pascale. 2021. “Can a Question Be a Lie? An Empirical Investigation.” Ergo 8. https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.1144.Google Scholar
Whitcomb, Dennis. 2017. “One Kind of Asking.” The Philosophical Quarterly 67 (266): 148–68. https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqw027.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, Timothy. 1996. “Knowing and Asserting.” The Philosophical Review 105 (4): 489523. https://doi.org/10.2307/2998423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar