Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0.001 Render date: 2024-05-25T16:53:24.429Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Organisms-Mechanisms: Stahl, Wolff, and the Case against Reductionist Exclusion

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 September 2008

Alfred Gierer
Affiliation:
Max-Planck-Institut für Entwicklungsbiologie, Tübingen

Abstract

Unlike Aristotelian physics with its Ideological notions, modern physics was developed exclusively in relation to the nonliving domain. This raised the question as to whether mechanics applies to organisms, and if so, to what extent. From the seventeenth century on, mechanistic ideas became prominent in biological and medical theory. Contemporary biology explains essential features of life on the basis of physical laws and processes. This does not prove, however, that the early mechanists were essentially right. In the eighteenth century, following Cartesian notions of mind-body separation and preformation theories of organismic development, they tended to exclude major biological questions rather than answering them. It was those who insisted on the organizational features of organisms, like Stahl and Wolff, who paved the way for solutions to such crucial problems as the psychological basis of human nature and behavior and the generation of form in the course of reproduction. Though they underrated the potentials of a future, extended physics for understanding biology, their case against reductionist exclusion should not be considered outdated even today.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Barrow, J. D., and Tipler, F. J.. 1986. The Anthropic Cosmological Principle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Blumenbach, J. F. [1781] 1971. Über den Bildungstrieb. Edited by vonKaroly, L.. Stuttgart: Fischer. Originally published by Dieterich, Göttingen.Google Scholar
Borelli, G. A. [1681] 1989. On the Movements of Animals. Translated by Maquet, P.Berlin, New York: Springer.Originally published as De motuanimalium.Google Scholar
Gaissinowitsch, A. E. 1956–57. “Notizen von C. F. Wolff oder die Bemerkungen der Opponenten in seiner Dissertation.” Wissenschaftliche Zeitschrift der Friedrich Schiller Universität Jena 6:122–24.Google Scholar
Geyer-Kordesch, J. 1989. “Die Medizin im Spannungsfeld zwischen Aufklärungund Pietismus: Der unbequeme Weg Georg Ernst Stahls und dessen kulturelle Bedeutung.” In Zentren der Aufklarung I: Halle — Aufklärung und Pietismus, edited by Hinske, N., 255–74. Heidelberg: Schneider.Google Scholar
Gierer, A. 1970. “The Physical Basis of Biology and the Psychophysic Problem.” Ratio 1:4054.Google Scholar
Gierer, A. 1983. “Relation between Neurophysiological and Mental States: Possible Limits of Decidability.” Naturwissenschaften 70:282–87.Google Scholar
Goethe, J. W. von. [1817] 1891. Zur Morphologic. Stuttgart/Tübingen: Cotta. Reprinted in Goethes Werke, II. 2nd ed., vol. 6., pp. 18, 19. Weimar.Google Scholar
Griffin, J., and Rees, M.. 1989. Cosmic Coincidences: Dark Matter, Mankind, and Anthropic Cosmology. New York: Bantam Books.Google Scholar
Kant, I. [1790] 1966. Critique of Judgment. Translated by Bernard, J. H.. New York: Haefner. Originally published as Kritik der Urteilskraft.Google Scholar
McLaughlin, P. 1982. “Blumenbach und der Bildungstrieb.” Medizinisches Journal 17:357–72.Google ScholarPubMed
Rather, L. J. 1961. “G. E. Stahl’s Psychological Physiology.” Bulletin of the History of Medicine 35:3749.Google Scholar
Roe, S. A. 1979. “Rationalism and Embryology: Caspar Friedrich Wolff’s Theory of Epigenesis.” Journal of the History of Biology 12:143.Google Scholar
Roe, S. A. 1981. Matter, Life and Generation: Eighteenth-Century Embryology and the Holier-Wolff Debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schelling, F. W. J. 1799. In Schriften von 1799–1801: Erster Entwurfeines Systems der Naturphilosophie. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 80.Google Scholar
Schelling, F. W. J. 1803. Vorlesungen über die Methode des akademischen Studiums. Tubingen: Cotta, 237–59.Google Scholar
Stahl, G. E. [1695] 1961a. Über den Einfluss der Gemiitsbewegungen auf den menschlichen Körper. Translated and edited by Gottlieb, B. J.. Leipzig: Barth. Originally published as Passionibus animi corpus humanum varie alter antibus. Halle.Google Scholar
Stahl, G. E. [1695] 1961 b. Über die Bedeutung des synergischen Prinzips in der Heilkunde. Translated and edited by Gottlieb, B. J.. Leipzig: Barth. Originally published as De synergia naturae in medendo, Halle.Google Scholar
Stahl, G. E. [1697] 1734. Zymotechniafundamental oder Allgemeine Grunderkenntnisse der Gärungskunst. Frankfurt/Leipzig. Originally published as Zymotechnia fundamental seufermentationis theoria generalis, Halle.Google Scholar
Stahl, G. E. 1701. Propempticon inaugurate de differentia rationis et rationcinationis et actionum, quae per et secundum utrumque horum actuum fiunt in negotio vitali et animali. Halle. Source: Library of the Deutsche Akademie fur Naturforschung Leopoldina, Halle.Google Scholar
Stahl, G. E. [1708] 1831. Theoria medico vera. Edited, translated into German, and abridged by Karl, Wilhelm Ideler. Part I. Berlin: Verlag Enslin. Originally published in Halle.Google Scholar
Stahl, G. E. [1714] 1961. Über den Unterschied zwischen Organismus und Mechanismus. Translated and edited by Gottlieb, B. J.. Leipzig: Barth. Originally published as Dissertatio inauguralis medico de medicina medicinae curiosae, Halle.Google Scholar
Trembley, A. 1744. Mémoires pour servir à I’histoire d’un genre de polypes d’eau douce à bras en forme de comes. Leiden: Verbeek.Google Scholar
Wolff, C. F. [1759] 1896. Theoria generationis. Translated into German by Samassa, P.. Leipzig.Google Scholar
Wolff, C. F. 1764. Theorie von der Generation. Berlin: Birnstiel.Google Scholar