Skip to main content
Log in

Semantics and truth relative to a world

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper argues that relativity of truth to a world plays no significant role in empirical semantic theory, even as it is done in the model-theoretic tradition relying on intensional type theory. Some philosophical views of content provide an important notion of truth at a world, but they do not constrain the empirical domain of semantic theory in a way that makes this notion empirically significant. As an application of this conclusion, this paper shows that a potential motivation for relativism based on the relativity of truth to a world fails.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Anderson C.A. (1984). General intensional logic. In: Gabbay D., Guenthner F. (eds) Handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. II). Dordrecht, Kluwer, pp. 355–385

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach K. (1994). Conversational impliciture. Mind and Language 9: 124–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barwise J., Perry J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Cambridge, MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Avi G., Winter Y. (2007). A modular approach to intensionality. In: Puig-Waldmüller E. (ed) Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 11. Barcelona, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, pp. 76–90

    Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem J. (1991). Language in action. Amsterdam, North-Holland

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn P., de Rijke M., Venema Y. (2001). Modal logic. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R. (1947). Meaning and necessity. Chicago, University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia G., McConnell-Ginet S. (1990). Meaning and grammar: An introduction to semantics. Cambridge, MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Church A. (1951). A formulation of the logic of sense and denotation. In: Henle P., Kallen H.M., Langer S.K. (eds) Structure, method, and meaning: Essays in honor of H. M. Sheffer. New York, Liberal Arts Press, pp. 3–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Cresswell M.J. (1973). Logics and languages. London, Methuen

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1967). Truth and meaning. Synthese, 17, 304–323. Reprinted in Davidson (1984).

  • Davidson D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowty D.R., Wall R.E., Peters S. (1981). Introduction to Montague semantics. Dordrecht, Reidel

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan A. (2007). Epistemic modals, relativism, and assertion. Philosophical Studies 133: 1–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan A., Hawthorne J., Weatherson B. (2005). Epistemic modals in context. In: Preyer G., Peter G. (eds) Contextualism in philosophy. Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 131–168

    Google Scholar 

  • Elbourne P.D. (2005). Situations and individuals. Cambridge, MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Enç M. (1986). Towards a referential analysis of temporal expressions. Linguistics and Philosophy 9: 405–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enç M. (1987). Anchoring conditions for tense. Linguistic Inquiry 18: 633–657

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1985). Does tense logic rest upon a mistake? In Collected papers (pp. 342–362). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Frege, G. (1892). Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 100, 25–50. References are to the translation as “On Sense and Meaning” by M. Black, reprinted in Frege-84.

  • Frege, G. (1984). In B. McGuinness (Ed.), Collected papers on mathematics, logic, and philosophy. Oxford: Basil Blackwell

  • Gallin D. (1975). Intensional and higher-order modal logic. Amsterdam, North-Holland

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gamut, L. T. F. (1991). Logic, language, and meaning, Vol. 2: Intensional logic and grammar. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ‘Gamut’ is a pseudonym for van Benthem, Groenendijk, de Jongh, Stokhof, and Verkuyl.

  • Glanzberg M. (2007). Context, content, and relativism. Philosophical Studies 136: 1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldblatt R. (1993). Mathematics of modality. Stanford, CSLI Publications

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman G., Thomson J.J. (1996). Moral relativism and moral objectivity. Oxford, Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Heck R.G., May R. (2006). Frege’s contribution to philosophy of language. In: Lepore E., Smith B.C. (eds) Oxford handbook of philosophy of language. Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 3–39

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim I. (1991). Artikel und definitheit. In: von Stechow A., Wunderlich D. (eds) Semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research. Berlin, de Gruyter, pp. 487–535

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim I., Kratzer A. (1998). Semantics in generative grammar. Oxford, Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham J. (1988). Contexts, models, and meanings: A note on the data of semantics. In: Kempson R. (ed) Mental representations: The interface between language and reality. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp. 29–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press. First publication of a widely circulated manuscript dated 1977.

  • King J.C. (2003). Tense, modality, and semantic value. Philosophical Perspectives 17: 195–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King J.C., Stanley J. (2004). Semantics, pragmatics, and the role of semantic content. In: Szabó Z.G. (ed) Semantics vs pragmatics. Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 111–164

    Google Scholar 

  • Kölbel M. (2002). Truth without objectivity. London, Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kölbel M. (2003). Faultless disagreement. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 104: 53–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusumoto, K. (1999). Tense in embedded contexts. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

  • Larson R., Segal G. (1995). Knowledge of meaning. Cambridge, MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn P. (2005). Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy 28: 643–686

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, P. (forthcoming). Relative truth, speaker commitment, and control of implicit arguments. Proceedings of the North East Linguistics Society, 37.

  • Lepore E. (1983). What model-theoretic semantics cannot do. Synthese 54: 167–187

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis C.I. (1943). The modes of meaning. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 4: 236–250

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1970). General semantics. Synthese, 22, 18–67. Reprinted in Lewis-83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge, Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D. (1983). Philosophical papers (Vol. 1). Oxford, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford, Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane J. (2003). Future contingents and relative truth. Philosophical Quarterly 53: 321–336

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane J. (2005). Making sense of relative truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105: 321–339

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1973). The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In J. Hintikka, J. Moravcsik, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Approaches to natural language (pp. 221–242). Dordrecht: Reidel. Reprinted in Montague-74.

  • Montague, R. (1974). In R. Thomason (Ed.), Formal philosophy. New Haven, Yale University Press

  • Parsons C. (1982). Intensional logic in extensional language. Journal of Symbolic Logic 47: 289–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Partee B.H., Hendriks H.L.W. (1997). Montague grammar. In: van Benthem J., ter Meulen A. (eds) Handbook of logic and language. Amsterdam, Elsevier, pp. 5–91

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Percus O. (2001). Constraints on some other variables in syntax. Natural Language Semantics 8: 173–229

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pohlers W. (1989). Proof theory. Berlin, Springer-Verlag

    Google Scholar 

  • Richard M. (1981). Temporalism and eternalism. Philosophical Studies 39: 1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richard M. (1982). Tense, propositions, and meanings. Philosophical Studies 41: 337–351

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soames S. (1987). Direct reference, propositional attitudes, and semantic content. Philosophical Topics 15: 47–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. C. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole (Ed.), Pragmatics, Vol. 9 of Syntax and semantics (pp. 315–322). New York: Academic Press. Reprinted in Stalnaker (1999).

  • Stalnaker R.C. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge, MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker R.C. (1999). Context and content. Oxford, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmermann T.E. (1989). Intensional logic and two-sorted type theory. Journal of Symbolic Logic 54: 65–77

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Glanzberg.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Glanzberg, M. Semantics and truth relative to a world. Synthese 166, 281–307 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-007-9285-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-007-9285-3

Keywords

Navigation