Skip to main content
Log in

Nonsense Made Intelligible

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

My topic is the relation between nonsense and (un-)intelligibility, and the contrast between nonsense and falsehood which played a pivotal role in the rise of analytic philosophy (sct. 1). I shall pursue three lines of inquiry. First I shall briefly consider the positive case, namely linguistic understanding (sct. 2). Secondly, I shall consider the negative case—different breakdowns of understanding and connected forms of failure to make sense (sct. 3–4). Third, I shall criticize three important misconceptions of nonsense and unintelligibility: the austere conception of nonsense propounded by the New Wittgensteinians (scts. 5–6); the “no nonsense position” which roundly denies that there are cases of nonsense—Chomsky’s semantic anomalies or Ryle’s category mistakes–that are grammatically well-formed, without even having the potential for being used to make a truth-apt statement (scts. 7–8); the individualistic conception of language and of semantic mistakes championed by Davidson (scts. 9–10). All three positions, I shall argue, ignore or deny combinatorial nonsense, the fact that perfectly meaningful sentence-components can be combined in a way that may be grammatical, yet without resulting in a sentence that is itself “meaningful”, i.e. endowed with linguistic sense. At a more strategic level, the first and the third position deny or ignore that natural languages are communal historical practices that go beyond idiolects and the employments of expressions in specific contexts and that are guided by semantic rules—standards for the meaningful use of words.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Chomsky (1957, p. 15) treats this “semantic anomaly” as grammatical yet nonseniscal. By contrast, Chomsky (1965) contests the idea that such sentences are syntactically well-formed.

  2. For the distinction between first- and second-order powers see Kenny (1989, p. 20) and Hacker (2006, pp. 105–106).

  3. See Rundle (2001, pp. 109–110), Baker and Hacker (2005, pp. 381–382). Even this variant of my account differs from theirs, however, by conceding the episodic nature of token understanding and by employing the dichotomies between first- and second-order powers and between one-way and two-way powers.

  4. The distinction between a power, its exercise and the opportunity conditions for that exercise hails from Kenny, e.g. (1989, ch. 5).

  5. Several items on this list hail from Waismann (1965, p. 347). Others combine Wittgensteinian ideas with more recent distinctions (drawn in Künne 1983, pp. 196–202).

  6. By dint of its venerable pedigree, persistence and pervasiveness, this confusion can lay claim to the title “the mother of all philosophical errors”.

  7. A threat of circularity looms here, if familiarity with words presupposes the capacity to employ them in sentences. In fact, however, children are become familiar with certain words through training involving simply speech acts like labelling or one-word sentences. This provides the foundation for the ability to employ these words in more complex speech acts.

  8. Another kernel of truth is that in the case of ambiguous words, context is needed to determine which of the different meanings is at issue. But first, even such words have their different meanings outside of a sentential context, e.g. in a list of homonyms. And secondly, disambiguation does not always require the context of a complete sentence. To exclude the meaning harbour, for instance, “a bottle of port” will do just fine.

  9. Several of the combinatorial principles invoked are closely related to Evans’ “generality constraint”. Ironically, Evans himself specifically excluded category mistakes from the scope of that constraint (1982, p. 101n).

  10. Magidor denies that simile can explain metaphors to begin with. She appeals to Davidson’s objection that the theory cannot do justice to the fact that metaphors are difficult to figure out and defy paraphrase in literal terms. But analogies and comparisons can be complex, rich and unserveyable. These kinds of comparisons defy straightforward paraphrase no less than ambitious metaphors do. For a convincing defence of the simile account against other objections see Schroeder 2004.

  11. Glock 2010 provides a more sustained critique of Davidson’s position.

  12. In a manuscript of 2002, p. 3, they claim that “we have no trouble understanding what he meant to convey”. However, they do not repeat either this wonderful example nor their assessment in the published version (2007).

References

  • Baker, G. P., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2005). Wittgenstein: Understanding and meaning, part I: Essays. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bronzo, S. (2011). Context, compositionality, and nonsense in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. In R. Read & M. Lavery (Eds.), Beyond the Tractatus Wars (pp. 84–111). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2004). The generality constraint and categorical restrictions. Philosophical Quarterly, 54, 210–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic structures. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conant, J. (2001). Two Conceptions of Die Überwinding der Metaphysik. In T. McCarthy & S.C. Stidd (Eds.), Wittgenstein in America (pp. 13–61). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Conant, J. (2002). The method of the Tractatus. In E. Reck (Ed.), From Frege to Wittgenstein (pp. 374–470). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Creary, A., & Read, R. (Eds.). (2000). The New Wittgenstein. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dain, E. (2008). Wittgenstein, contextualism and nonsense: A reply to Hans-Johann Glock. Journal of Philosophical Research, 33, 111–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1986). A nice derangement of epitaphs. In E. LePore (Ed.), Truth and interpretation (pp. 433–446). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1990). The structure and content of truth. Journal of Philosophy, 87, 279–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1994). The social aspect of language. In B. McGuinness & G. Oliveri (Eds.), The philosophy of Michael Dummett (pp. 1–16). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1999). The centrality of truth. In J. Peregrin (Ed.), Truth and its nature (if any) (pp. 105–115). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2001). Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, C. (1991). The realistic spirit. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, C. (2000). Ethics, imagination and the method of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. In A. Creary & R. Read (Eds.), The new Wittgenstein (pp. 149–173). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1981). Frege: Philosophy of language. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1986). A nice derangement of epitaphs: Some comments on Davidson and Hacking. In E. LePore (Ed.), Truth and interpretation: Perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson (pp. 459–476). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1991). Frege and other philosophers. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H. J. (1996). A Wittgenstein dictionary. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H. J. (2003). Quine and Davidson on thought, language and reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H. J. (2004). All kinds of nonsense. In E. Ammereller & E. Fischer (Eds.), Wittgenstein at work (pp. 221–245). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H. J. (2008). Necessity and language: In defence of conventionalism. Philosophical Investigations, 31, 24–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H. J. (2010). Does language require conventions? In P. Frascolla, D. Marconi, & A. Voltolini (Eds.), Wittgenstein: Mind, meaning and metaphilosophy (pp. 85–112). London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H. J., & Preston, J. (1995). Externalism and first person authority. The Monist, 78, 515–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haack, R. J. (1971). No need for nonsense. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 49, 71–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (1997). Davidson on first-person authority. Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 285–304.

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Wittgenstein, Carnap and the New American Wittgensteinians. The Philosophical Quarterly, 53, 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (2006). Human nature: The categorical framework. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, A. J. P. (1989). The metaphysics of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Künne, W. (1983). Abstrakte Gegenstände. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, E., & Ludwig, K. (2002). The reality of language, unpublished manuscript.

  • Lepore, E., & Ludwig, K. (2007). The Reality of Language: on the Davidson/Dummett exchange. In R. E. Auxier & L. E. Hahn (Eds.), The philosophy of Michael Dummett (pp. 185–214). LaSalle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magidor, O. (2010). Category mistakes are meaningful. Linguistics and Philosophy, 32, 553–581.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1980). From a logical point of view. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Routley, R. (1969). The need for nonsense. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 44, 172–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rundle, B. (2001). Meaning and understanding. In H. J. Glock (Ed.), Wittgenstein: A critical reader (pp. 94–118). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. repr. London: Penguin.

  • Ryle, G. (1970). Autobiographical. In O. P. Wood & G. Pitcher (Eds.), Ryle (pp. 1–15). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1971). Collected papers 2. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, S. (2004). Why Juliet is the Sun. In M. Siebel & M. Textor (Eds.), Semantik und Ontologie (pp. 63–101). Frankfurt: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waismann, L. (1965). The principles of linguistic philosophy. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1967). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1993). Philosophical occasions. In J. Klagge, & A. Nordmann (Eds.), Indianapolis: Hackett.

Download references

Acknowledgments

For comments on previous versions, I am indebted to Alex Burri, Peter Hacker, as well as to audiences at Regensburg and Erfurt. I am particularly grateful to Kai Büttner and David Dolby for alerting me to complications concerning the passive nature of understanding and the connection between the privation view of nonsense and nonsense monism.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hans-Johann Glock.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Glock, HJ. Nonsense Made Intelligible. Erkenn 80 (Suppl 1), 111–136 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9662-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9662-5

Keywords

Navigation