Skip to main content
Log in

Getting Out in Front of the Owl of Minerva Problem

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Our meta-argumentative vocabulary supplies the conceptual tools used to reflectively analyse, regulate, and evaluate our argumentative performances. Yet, this vocabulary is susceptible to misunderstanding and abuse in ways that make possible new discursive mistakes and pathologies. Thus, our efforts to self-regulate our reason-transacting practices by articulating their norms makes possible new ways to violate and flout those very norms. Scott Aikin identifies the structural possibility of this vicious feedback loop as the Owl of Minerva Problem. In the spirit of a shared concern for the flourishing or our rational, argumentative practices, this paper approaches the Owl of Minerva Problem from a vantage point that, by comparison with Aikin’s, affords perspectives that are more pessimistic in some aspects and more optimistic in others. Pessimistically, the problem at the root of the weaponization of our meta-argumentative vocabulary is motivational, not structural. Its motivational nature explains its resistance to the normal repertoire of reparative (meta-)argumentative maneuvers, as well as revealing a profound and deeply entrenched misunderstanding of the connection between our reasons-transacting practices and the goods achievable within them. Optimistically, in the absence of this motivational problem, the misunderstandings and errors made possible by our meta-argumentative vocabularies are amenable to remedy by familiar techniques of discursive instruction and repair. More optimistically, even though our meta-argumentative vocabularies are generated only retrospectively, they can be used prospectively, thereby making possible an aspirational motivation resulting in a virtuous cycle of increasingly autonomous normative self-regulation. Properly harnessed, the Owl of Minerva releases the Lark of Arete.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. That said, I agree with the spirit of, and find some cause for hope in, those constructive suggestions for deep dialectical repair suggested by Aikin (2018, 2019) and Aikin and Talisse (2019, especially chapters 14, 15).

  2. For a further discussion of these matters, and of adversariality in argumentation generally, see (Godden 2021).

  3. Stevens here follows Susan Moller Okin (1989: 193) who introduces the notion of exit options in the context of relationships generally. Those who can best endure dissent or strife in a relationship, or the degradation or dissolution of the relationship, can leverage that power in shaping the relationship.

  4. Importantly, it should be noted, as one reviewer astutely observed, that additional instruction and rule clarification cannot foreclose on the possibilities of misinterpretation, misunderstanding, misapplication, or incompetence. Rather, these possibilities remain perennial. Any efforts at remedial correction can themselves be misunderstood. As such the Owl of Minerva problem is recursive in nature—for any instance of the problem, x, a derivative instance of it, x, can recur at the level of instructional remediation of x. How is this possibility to be addressed?

    The view advanced here builds on previous work of the author (Godden 2019), where a competence view of our reason-giving practices is presented. On this view, what any form of instruction depends upon for its success is some prior conceptual competency or pre-conceptual ability. That is, what must be presupposed, at some level, is a relatively primary and pre-existing conceptually-inflected agential competence or, at a minimum, a stable pattern of behavior in the agent that reliably discriminates among relevant phenomena. It is upon these that any conceptually-inflected competency we might hope to inculcate must be grafted and subsequently honed. As Larry Wright has put the point, albeit in a slightly different context:

    For justification, if it is to be of any value at all, comes to an and. And the best place for it to end is in a competent judgment. (Wright 2001: 100; cf. 1995: 568; Campolo 2018; Wittgenstein PI: §217; OC: §110).

    Our abilities in any rule-governed—which is to say conceptually articulated—activity, including reasoning, depend, at some level, on our competency to make reliable, unmediated judgments.

    On such a view, effective remedies to misunderstanding or incompetence must reach down to those existing competencies or abilities and, building on those, inculcate the more sophisticated and articulated competencies necessary to master the skill or practice under instruction. In the event that those pre-existing, if latent, competencies or abilities are absent and unattainable, it could be the case that mastery of the technique under instruction will not be possible. In the context of this paper, the absence of such relatively basic, or primary, competencies or abilities might result in our coming to deem the subject untrainable, and thereby generally incompetent in a way that prompts us to subsequently classify, and treat them, as non-agential in the relevant area of practice. When rational competency (Godden 2019) is at issue, we might be brought to the point where we cease to recognize such subjects as having rational agency.

  5. Compare Adam Leite’s (2004: 222f.) discussion of what he calls the spectatorial conception of the activity of justification.

References

  • Aikin, S. 2008. Holding one’s own. Argumentation 22: 571–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aikin, S. 2018. Deep disagreement and the problem of the criterion. Topoi. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9568-y

  • Aikin, S. 2019. Deep disagreement, the dark enlightenment, and the rhetoric of the red pill. Journal of Applied Philosophy 36 (3): 420–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aikin, S. 2020. The Owl of Minerva problem. Southwest Philosophical Review 36 (1): 13–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aikin, S. and Talisse, R. 2017a. Democracy, deliberation, and the Owl of Minerva problem: The malaise of argumentation via technological mediation. The Critique (January/February, 2–71; 15 January, 2017). http://www.thecritique.com/articles/democracy-and-the-owl-of-minerva/

  • Aikin, S. and Talisse, R. 2017b. The Owl of Minerva problem. 3 Quarks Daily: Science, Arts, Philosophy, Politics, Literature (27 February, 2017). https://www.3quarksdaily.com/3quarksdaily/2017/02/the-owl-of-minerva-problem.html

  • Aikin, S and Talisse, R. 2018. The Owl of Minerva and the fallacy fallacy. 3 Quarks Daily: Science, Arts, Philosophy, Politics, Literature (26 March, 2018). https://www.3quarksdaily.com/3quarksdaily/2018/03/the-owl-of-minerva-and-the-fallacy-fallacy.html

  • Aikin, S., and R. Talisse. 2019. Why we argue (and how we should): A guide to political disagreement in an age of unreason, 2nd ed. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariely, D. 2008. Predictably irrational: The hidden forces that shape our decisions. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. 1994. Making it explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callard, A. 2018. Aspiration: The agency of becoming. New York: Oxford UP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Campolo, C. 2019. On staying in character: Virtue and the possibility of deep disagreement. Topoi 38 (4): 719–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godden, D. 2014. Teaching rational entitlement and responsibility: A Socratic exercise. Informal Logic 34 (1): 124–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godden, D. (2019). On the rational resolvability of deep disagreement through meta-argumentation: A resource audit. Topoi, 38, 725–750. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-019-09682-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godden, D. 2021 (forthcoming). The compliment of rational opposition: Disagreement, adversariality, and disputation. Topoi.

  • Hacking, I. 1999. The social construction of what? Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, G.H. [1940] 2012. A mathematician’s apology. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.

  • Inglis, M., and A. Aberdein. 2015. Beauty is not simplicity: An analysis of mathematicians’ proof appraisals. Philosophia Mathematica 23 (1): 87–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, S. 2019. Reason-giving and the natural normativity of argumentation. Topoi 38 (4): 631–643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krabbe, E.C.W. 2003. Metadialogues. In Anyone Who Has a View, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, J.A. Blair, C. Willard, and A.F. SnoeckHenkemans, 83–90. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Leite, A. 2004. On justifying and being justified. Philosophical Issues, Epistemology 14: 219–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okin, S. 1989. Justice, gender and the family. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. [1956] 1997. Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge. MA: Harvard UP.

  • Siegel, H. 1988. Educating reason: Rationality, critical thinking, and education. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. 1997. Rationality redeemed: Further dialogues on an educational ideal. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevens, K. 2019. The roles we make others take: Thoughts on the ethics of arguing. Topoi 38 (4): 693–709.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1953. [PI] Philosophical investigations, 3rd ed. G.E.M. Anscombe (trans.). New York: Macmillan.

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1969. [OC] On certainty. G.E.M. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright (eds.). D. Paul and G.E.M. Anscombe (trans.). New York: Harper & Row.

  • Wright, L. 1995. Argument and deliberation: A plea for understanding. Journal of Philosophy 92: 565–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. 2001. Justification, discovery, reason and argument. Argumentation 15: 97–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Association for Philosophy of Education session of the American Philosophical Association, Central Division, on February 28, 2020, in Chicago, Illinois, under the title “It’s always darkest before the dawn: The Lark of Arete and praiseworthiness in public discourse.” I am grateful to my colleague Matt Ferkany for organizing that session and inviting me to participate. The advertised topic of that session was “Argument and Critical Thinking in Democracy,” though it was really an author-meets-critics panel discussion in which Scott Aikin presented “The Owl of Minerva problem and public argument,” summarizing some of his recent work, whereupon John Casey, Matt Ferkany, and I separately delivered prepared commentaries to which Scott then replied. Participating in that panel gave me the occasion and impetus to give this topic the serious reflection and consideration it deserves, and my thinking on these matters has been clarified and corrected significantly through many conversations over the years with my co-panelists. Thanks are also due to the participants of that session, particularly Danielle Lee Clevenger, as well as the anonymous referees of this paper for their constructive criticisms.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Godden.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Godden, D. Getting Out in Front of the Owl of Minerva Problem. Argumentation 36, 35–60 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-021-09554-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-021-09554-2

Keywords

Navigation