Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Law and Science: The Autonomy and Limits of Culpability as a Cornerstone to the Ascription of Liability (or the Subject of Criminal Law: Three Maxims, a Problem and a Glimpse into the Future)

  • Published:
International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue internationale de Sémiotique juridique Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In recent years, the advancements made in the field of neuroscience have been echoed in criminal law, reigniting the discussion on culpability from the viewpoint of if it actually exists, considering the echoes of determinism on the re-found non-existence of free will. This discussion has triggered, once again, the issue of the boundaries and inter-relations between (criminal) law and science, namely on whether normative or legal concepts and categories should acknowledge scientific breakthroughs. Bringing forth the theme of the limits of the law, this discussion is able to provide insight, with reference to a specific problem, as to whether there are plausible legal answers in the context of the ascription of liability if the subject of law ceases to be a responsible—and thus free—person. Taking into consideration evolution both of science and criminal law dogmatic, we aim to argue that in the particular case of culpability, the desired autonomy of law has its limitations, and that without such limitations the ascription of liability would not have a correct answer. For this argument we will firstly approach the meaning of culpability as a milestone of subjective responsibility in criminal law, so that we can then analyse some arguments made regarding the impact of neuroscience on the maintenance of a concept of culpability with the meaning given above, so that lastly we can proceed to the rebuttal of the overarching impact of (neuro) science on the law and advocate the autonomy of culpability within the necessary limits imposed by the needs of a plausible legal answer.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This was fairly different in the Middle Ages; in fact, there are reports of criminal trials of animals, which were, too, convicted for their “crimes”. See [10: 566 ff.].

  2. A criminal act represents the connection between human conduct and the violation of a criminally protected legal interest. The expression “human conduct” encompasses the need for volition, but such conduct can be active (action) or passive (omission).

  3. Differently, Cesare Lombroso, in his L’Uomo Delinquente (1876), believed there to be a “natural offender”, based on the physical traits of each person.

  4. This is particularly relevant in the consideration of other problems, such as the mistake of fact and the vis absoluta as to the act as an action liberae.

  5. In this regard, particularly relevant [12: 216]. This leads to the fact that negligent conduct – actio libera in causa – is not considered to be as reproachable as intentional conduct – actio libera in se, and is, then, deemed as an “exceptional” source of responsibility in criminal law, only being foreseen in offenses regarding some legal interests (life, for example).

  6. However, considering criminal offence provisions as text, it can also be said that “A text is not simply a communicational apparatus. It is a device which questions the previous signifying systems, often renews them, and sometimes destroys them” [4: 25].

  7. Under Searle, “Intentionality is that property of many mental states and events by which they are directed at or about or of objects and states of affairs in the world” [30: 1].

  8. See United States v. Semrau (2010).

  9. We refer to the primary function of legal rules; there are, however, legal definitions, a.s.o., which do not carry said functions.

References

  1. Bennett, Elisabeth. 2016. Neuroscience and criminal law, Fordham Law Review 85.

  2. Denno, Deborah W. 2019. Neuroscience and the personalization of criminal law, The University of Chicago Law Review 89.

  3. Denno, Deborah W. 2016. The place for neuroscience in Criminal Law, in: Dennis Patterson/Michael S. Pardo (Ed.), Philosophical Foundations of Law and Neuroscience, Oxford: OUP.

  4. Eco, Umberto. 1984. Semiotics and the Philosophy of Language. Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

  5. Farah, Marta J. et al. 2014. Functional MRI-based lie detection: scientific and societal challenges, Neuroscience 15.

  6. Fletcher, George. 2007. The Grammar of Criminal Law. N.Y.: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Frisch, Wolfgang. 2012. Sobre el futuro del Derecho Penal de la culpabilidad, in: Cancio Meliá/Feijoo Sánchez, Derecho Penal de la Culpabilidad y Neurociencias, Civitas.

  8. Godinho, Inês Fernandes. 2017. Wissenschaftliche Erkenntnistheorie und strafrechtliche Methodologie: Beziehungen und Grenzen zwischen moderner Hirnforschung und strafrechtlicher “(Willens)freiheit”, Rechtsphilosophie, 3/2017.

  9. Godinho, Inês Fernandes. 2017a. The criminal offence – definitions and internal structure – Portugal, in: Sieber/Jarvers/Silverman (eds.), National Criminal Law in a Comparative Legal Context, Vol. 3.2.: Defining criminal conduct.

  10. Gless, Sabine/Weigend, Thomas. 2014. Intelligente Agenten und das Strafrecht, ZStW 126.

  11. Hirsch, Hans Joachim. 2010. Zur gegenwärtigen deutschen Diskussion über Willensfreiheit und Strafrecht, ZIS 2/2010.

  12. Hruschka, Joachim. 2003. La imputación ordinaria y extraordinaria en Pufendorf (transl, 12. Revista de Derecho Penal y Criminología: Nuria Pastor Muñoz).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Hruschka, Joachim. 1994. Reglas de comportamiento y reglas de imputación, Anuario de Derecho Penal y Ciencias Penales.

  14. Hyman, John. 2015. Action, knowledge and will. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. Jackson, Bernard S. Jackson. 2017. A Journey into Legal Semiotics. Actes Semiotiques n.º 120.

  16. Kaiafa-Gbandi, Maria. 2011. The Importance of Core Principles of Substantive Criminal Law for a European Criminal Policy Respecting Fundamental Rights and the Rule of Law, European Criminal Law Review 1.

  17. Kenny, Anthony. 1978. Freewill and responsibility. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Lloyd, Harold Anthony, How To Do Things With Signs: Semiotics in Legal Theory, Practice, and Education (January 8, 2020). University of Richmond Law Review, Forthcoming, Wake Forest Univ. Legal Studies Paper , Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3516238 or https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3516238

  19. Morse, Stephen. 2015. Criminal Law and common sense: an essay in the perils and promise of neuroscience, Marquette Law Review 99.

  20. Nisco, Attilio. 2012. Il confronto tra neuroscienze e diritto penale sulla libertà di volere, Diritto penale e processo 4/2012.

  21. Oliveira, Rui (Coord.). 2019. Cérebro. Mais vasto que o céu, Lisboa: Fundação Calouste Gulbenkian.

  22. Patterson, Dennis. 2016. Criminal law, neuroscience and voluntary acts, Journal of Law and the Biosciences.

  23. Pauen, Michael, and Gerhard Roth. 2008. Freiheit, Schuld und Verantwortung, Grundzüge einer naturalistischen Theorie der Willensfreiheit. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Pietrzykowski, Tomasz. 2018. Personhood beyond humanism. Animals chimeras, autonomous agents and the law. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Prinz Wolfgang. 2004. Der Mensch ist nicht frei. Ein Gespräch, In: Christian Geyer (Hg.) Hirnforschung und Willensfreiheit, Frankfurt: Suhrkam.

  26. Pufendorf, Samuel. 1726. Of the Law of Nature and Nations (Transl. Basil Kennett), 4th, Book I.

  27. Raz, Joseph. 2011. From normativity to responsibility. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  28. Robinson, Paul. 1990. Rules of Conduct and Principles of Adjudication, The University of Chicago Law Review 57.

  29. Roth, Gerhard. 2004. Wir sind determiniert. Die Hirnforschung befreit von Illusionen, Christian Geyer (Hg), Hirnforschung und Willensfreiheit. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Searle, John R. 1999. Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind (Repr.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Singer, Wolf. 2006. Vom Gehirn zum Bewusstsein. Frankfuhrt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Sousa, Ronald Bon de. 2013. The Myth of Responsibility, in: Maria Fernanda Palma, Augusto Silva Dias, Paulo de Sousa Mendes (Coord.), Filosofia, Ciência, Arte e Direito Penal, Coimbra: Almedina.

  33. Sousa, Susana Aires de. 2017. Neurociências e processo penal: verdade ex machina, In: Estudos em homenagem ao Senhor Prof. Doutor Manuel da Costa Andrade, Vol.II, Boletim da Faculdade de Direito da Universidade de Coimbra.

  34. Williams, Glanville. 1961. Criminal law: The general part. London: Stevens.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Willmott, Chris. 2016. Biological determinism, free will and moral responsibility. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Inês Fernandes Godinho.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Godinho, I.F. Law and Science: The Autonomy and Limits of Culpability as a Cornerstone to the Ascription of Liability (or the Subject of Criminal Law: Three Maxims, a Problem and a Glimpse into the Future). Int J Semiot Law 35, 297–308 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-020-09804-8

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-020-09804-8

Keywords

Navigation