Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

On Blaming and Punishing Psychopaths

  • OriginalPaper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Current legal practice holds that a diagnosis of psychopathy does not remove criminal responsibility. In contrast, many philosophers and legal experts are increasingly persuaded by evidence from experimental psychology and neuroscience indicating moral and cognitive deficits in psychopaths and have argued that they should be excused from moral responsibility. However, having opposite views concerning psychopaths’ moral responsibility, on the one hand, and criminal responsibility, on the other, seems unfortunate given the assumption that the law should, at least to some extent, react to the same desert-based considerations as do ascriptions of moral responsibility. In response, Stephen Morse has argued that the law should indeed be reformed so as to excuse those with severe psychopathy from blame, but that psychopaths that have committed criminal offences should still be subject to some legal repercussions such as civil commitment. We argue that consequentialist and norm-expressivist considerations analogous to those that support punishing psychopaths or at least retaining some legal liability, might also be drawn on in favour of holding psychopaths morally accountable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. However, for an interesting argument that the capacity for self-regulation is a key part of moral agency and one on which psychopaths are likely to fall short, see Kennett (2010). While we do touch on the issue of control in the context of psychopaths’ prudential deficits, we do not make it the focus of our discussion.

  2. Dolan and Fullam (2010) also conducted a study with youths with conduct disorders where performance in the moral-conventional task only partially corresponded to what would be expected from Blair’s studies.

  3. In some of the examples used, the harm occurs for some perceived future benefit and in others it is a reaction to a preceding transgression. This latter point is also made by Rosas (2012) in a criticism of Kelly et al.’s (2007) experimental setup. He also raises a further issue, which is that many of their examples are mixed domain situations where an authority’s rule differs from the moral rule.

  4. An additional and related problem for the law is how to deal with psychopaths who may not have committed crimes yet but are likely to do so.

  5. These justifications for punishment may either represent considerations that replace the notion of desert altogether or they may be conceived of as additional justifications for punishment that are constrained by the just deserts (Feinberg 1970; Fine and Kennett 2004; Pardo and Patterson 2013).

  6. The insanity defence is the primary vehicle for excusing individuals of responsibility who, due to their mental condition or disorder, have insufficient moral understanding or impaired rationality at the time their crimes were committed. If an individual is acquitted after a successful plea of insanity, the court typically automatically commits her to psychiatric treatment and surveillance. Psychopathy is currently not amongst those psychiatric disorders that are considered to be a necessary (though not sufficient) part of such a defence by the American Model Penal Code and most analogous codes in other countries. However, the evidence of psychopaths’ impaired moral cognition discussed in the last section may be seen to count in favour of changing this.

  7. Another rather common but unpersuasive proposal about subsuming psychopaths under the insanity defence is that they cannot be as successfully rehabilitated or treated, as offenders with mental disorders where the insanity defence tends to be evoked, e.g., psychosis and schizophrenia (Reznek 1997; Lee 2007). There are several problems with this proposal. First, it is not clear whether therapy and interventions are as futile as they are commonly thought to be. More importantly, the insanity defence is perceived as legitimate in other cases where there is no chance of rehabilitation, such as disabilities and dementia. In general, the possibility of and susceptibility to treatment do not constitute the grounds of defence.

  8. The concern about upholding public confidence in legal institutions arguably also arises in a consequentialist analysis about the justice system’s role in giving individuals a sense of security and also in doing something that actually deters individuals with the threat of punishment or indeed involuntary commitment.

  9. Where these limits should lie is beyond the scope of this article and is of course strongly dependent on the crime and the length of the sentence normally handed out for that type of crime.

  10. As we have argued, the objection from pointlessness can also be given an expressivist reading. We further discuss the expressivist rationale below.

  11. On some accounts of moral responsibility it may be that the possibility of intervention is itself evidence for desert. We leave it to others to explore the plausibility of this line of argument.

  12. In fact, one of the authors believes that the impact of the social responses and environment on the development of some psychopathic traits provides some grounds for arguing that there may also be a fairness dimension of our responsibility attributions. That is, the argument for holding psychopaths accountable is not only that we might we affect the psychopath’s social and moral behaviour over time with some hope for desirable results for the individual with psychopathy and for society at large, but also out of fairness continue to morally engage with individuals thereby acknowledging that their traits may be partly a failing on the part of the moral community as a whole.

  13. It is of course entirely possible that these findings only hold for a subgroup of youthful psychopaths or for so-called “secondary” psychopaths (for this distinction, see Mealy 1995).

  14. We would like to thank Jeanette Kennett for alerting us to this important possibility.

  15. While it has to be admitted that this is a difficult feat to accomplish, Pickard (2011) recommends a similar course of action in the context of the interaction between health care providers and individuals with personality disorders. She stresses the importance of holding service users responsible for their behaviour while not rejecting them as individuals. It should however be pointed out that Pickard distinguishes between holding responsible and blaming in a way we do not. This is because she takes blame to be emotionally charged and to have a characteristic “sting” attached to it (cf. Pickard 2013).

  16. We thank our anonymous referee for pointing out that this conclusion only holds if we can be sure that blaming and holding responsible do not have negative repercussions. There is some evidence that blame in understood as an emotionally charged condemnation of the person is counterproductive (cf. Pickard 2011). However, in this section we have cited evidence which at least shows some beneficial effects of holding psychopaths responsible in the sense of pointing out that behaviour was morally wrong and imposing negative repercussions for such behaviour (e.g., Shaw 2003; Caldwell et al. 2007; Salekin et al. 2010; McDonald et al. 2011). As mentioned, there is a growing body of experimental work that shows the belief that one can change is also an important precondition to attempting such change (Mueller and Dweck 1998; Baumeister et al. 2009; Vohs and Schooler 2008; Charland 2011). Holding people responsible is one way of expressing one’s confidence that this can be done.

References

  • Eyal Aharoni, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Kent Kiehl, “Can Psychopathic Offenders Detect Moral Wrongs? A New Look at the Moral/Conventional Distinction”, Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 121(2) (2012): 484–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lisa G. Aspinwall, Teneille R. Brown, James Tabery, “The Double-Edged Sword: Does Biomechanism Increase or Decrease Judges’ Sentencing of Psychopaths?”, Science 337(6096) (2012): 846–849.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul Babiak, Richard D. Hare, Snakes in Suits: When Psychopaths go to Work (New York: Harper Collins, 2007).

    Google Scholar 

  • Roy F. Baumeister, E.J. Masicampo, C. Nathan DeWall, “Prosocial Benefits of Feeling Free: Disbelief in Free Will Increases Agression and Decreases Helpfulness”, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 35 (2009): 260–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James Blair, “A cognitive developmental approach to morality: investigating the psychopath”, Cognition 57(1) (1995): 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James Blair, “Affect and the moral-conventional distinction”, Journal of Moral Education 26(2) (1997): 187–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michael F. Caldwell, David J. McCormick, Deborah Umstead, Gregory J. van Rybroek, “Evidence of Treatment Progress and Therapeutic Outcomes Among Adolescents with Psychopathic Features”, Criminal Justice and Behavior 34(5) (2007): 573–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Louis Charland, “Decision Making Capacity and Responsibility in Addiction”, in J. Poland and G. Graham (eds.), Addiction and Responsibility (Cambridge MA and London: MIT Press, 2011): 139–158.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jeremy Coid, Min Yang, Simone Ullrich, Amanda Roberts, Paul Moran, Paul Bebbington, Traolach Brugha, Rachel Jenkins, Michael Farell, Glyn Lewis, Nicola Singleton, Robert Hare, “Psychopathy Among Prisoners in England and Wales”, International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 32(3) (2009): 134–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mairead C. Dolan, Rachael S. Fullam, “Moral/conventional transgression distinction and psychopathy in conduct disordered adolescent offenders”, Personality and Individual Difference 49(8) (2010): 995–1000.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • John F. Edens, John Petrila, Jacqueline K. Buffington-Vollum, “Psychopathy and the Death Penalty: Can the Psychopathy Checklist-Revised Identify Offenders Who Represent ‘a Continuing Threat to Society’?”, Journal of Psychiatry & Law 29 (2001): 433–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joel Feinberg, Doing & Deserving: Essays in the Theory of Responsibility (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  • Cordelia Fine, Jeannette Kennett, “Mental Impairment, Moral Understanding and Criminal Responsibility: Psychopathy and the Purposes of Punishment”, International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 27, (2004): 425–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adam R. Fox, Trevor H. Kvaran, Reid Griffith Fontaine, “Psychopathy and Culpability: How Responsible is the Psychopath for Criminal Wrongdoing?”, Law & Social Inquiry 38(1) (2013): 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul J. Frick, Eva R. Kimonis, Dannielle M. Dandreaux, J.M. Farell, “The 4-year Stability of Psychopathic Traits in Non‐Referred Youth”, Behavioral Sciences & the Law 21(6) (2003): 713–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jean-Pierre Guay, John Ruscio, Raymond A. Knight, Richard D. Hare, “A Taxometric Analysis of the Latent Structure of Psychopathy: Evidence for Dimensionality”, Journal of Abnormal Psychology 116(4) (2007): 701–716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richard D. Hare, The Hare Psychopathy Checklist—Revised (PCL-R) (Toronto: Multi Health Systems, 1991).

    Google Scholar 

  • Richard D. Hare, “Psychopathy as a Risk Factor for Violence”, Psychiatric Quarterly 70(3) (1999): 181–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephen D. Hart, “Psychopathy, Culpability, and Commitment”, in R.F. Schopp et al. (eds.), Mental Disorder and Criminal Law (New York: Springer, 2009): 159–178.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • James F. Hemphill, Richard D. Hare, Stephen Wong, “Psychopathy and Recidivism: A Review”, Legal and Criminological Psychology 3(1) (1998): 139–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniel Kelly, Stephen Stich, Kevin J. Haley, Serena J. Eng, Daniel M.T. Fessler, “Harm, Affect, and the Moral/Conventional Distinction”, Mind & Language 22(2) (2007): 117–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeanette Kennett, “Reasons, Emotion and Moral Judgment in the Psychopath”, in: L. Malatesti and J. McMillan (eds.), Responsibility and Psychopathy: Interfacing Law, Psychiatry and Philosophy (International Perspectives in Philosophy and Psychiatry series) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010): 243–259.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grazyna Kochanska, Nazan Aksan, “Children’s conscience and self‐regulation” Journal of Personality 74(6) (2006): 1587–1618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christina Lee, “Judicial Response to Psychopathic Criminals: Utilitarianism over Retribution”, Law & Psychology Review 31, (2007): 125–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ken Levy, “Dangerous Psychopaths, Criminally Responsible but Not Morally Responsible, Subject to Criminal Punishment and to Preventive Detention”, San Diego Law Review 48 (2011): 1301–1395.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neil Levy, Neuroethics—Challenges for the 21st century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007a).

    Google Scholar 

  • Neil Levy, “The Responsibility of the Psychopath Revisited”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 14(2) (2007b): 129–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neil Levy, “Psychopaths and Blame: The Argument from Content”, Philosophical Psychology 27(3) (2014): 351–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul Litton, “Responsibility status of the psychopath: On moral reasoning and rational self-governance”, Rutger’s Law Journal 39(349) (2008): 350–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renee McDonald, Mary Catherine Dodson, David Rosenfield, Ernest N. Jouriles, “Effects of a Parenting Intervention on Features of Psychopathy in Children”, Journal of Abnormal Child Psychology 39(7) (2011): 1013–1023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris McIlwain, “Living Strangely in Time: Emotions, Masks and Morals in Psychopathically-inclined People”, European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 6(1) (2010): 75–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linda Mealey, “The Sociobiology of Sociopathy: an Integrated Evolutionary Model”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18(03) (1995): 523–541.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephen J. Morse, “Psychopathy and Criminal Responsibility”, Neuroethics 1(3) (2008): 205–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephen J. Morse, “Psychopathy and the Law: The United States Experience”, in L. Malatesti and J. McMillan (eds.), Responsibility and Psychopathy: Interfacing Law, Psychiatry and Philosophy (International Perspectives in Philosophy and Psychiatry series) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010): 41–62.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stephen J. Morse, “Mental Disorder and Criminal Law”, Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 101(3) (2011a): 885–968.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephen J. Morse, “Protecting Liberty and Autonomy: Desert/Disease Jurisprudence”, San Diego Law Review 48(4) (2011b): 1077–1125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Claudia M. Mueller, Carol S. Dweck, “Praise for Intelligence can Undermine Children’s Motivation and Performance”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 75(1) (1998): 33–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniel C. Murrie, David K. Marcus, Kevin S. Douglas, Zina Lee, Randall T. Salekin, Gina Vincent, “Youth with Psychopathy Features are Not a Discrete Class: a Taxometric Analysis”, Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry 48(7) (2007): 714–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dustin A. Pardini, Rolf Loeber, “Interpersonal and Affective Features of Psychopathy in Children and Adolescents: Advancing a Developmental Perspective Introduction to Special Section”, Journal of Clinical Child and Adolescent Psychology 36(3) (2007): 269–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michael Pardo, Dennis Patterson, “Neuroscientific Challenges to retributivism”, in T. Nadelhoffer (ed.), The Future of Punishment (Oxford University Press, 2013): 133–154.

  • Hannah Pickard, “Responsibility without Blame: Empathy and Effective Treatment of Personality Disorder”, Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 18(3) (2011): 209–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hannah Pickard, “Irrational Blame”, Analysis 73(4) (2013): 613–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuel H. Pillsbury, “Meaning of Deserved Punishment: An Essay on Choice, Character, and Responsibility, The Indiana Law Journal 67(3) (1992): 719–752.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawrie Reznek, Evil or Ill? Justifying the Insanity Defence (London and New York: Routledge, 1997).

    Google Scholar 

  • Alejandro Rosas, “Mistakes To Avoid In Attacking The Moral/Conventional Distinction”, Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 7(1) (2012): 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Randall T. Salekin, Courtney Worley, Ross D. Grimes, “Treatment of Psychopathy: A Review and Brief Introduction to the Mental Model Approach for Psychopathy”, Behavioral Sciences & the Law 28(2) (2010): 235–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robert F. Schopp, Andrew J. Slain, “Psychopathy, Criminal responsibility, and Civil Commitment as a Sexual Predator”, Behavioral Sciences & The Law 18(2–3) (2000): 247–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniel S. Shaw, “Innovative Approaches and Methods to the Study of Children’s Conduct Problems”, Social Development 12(3) (2003): 309–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David W. Shoemaker, “Psychopathy, Responsibility, and the Moral/Conventional Distinction”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy 49(s1) (2011): 99–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephen Stich, Daniel M.T. Fessler, Daniel Kelly, “On the Morality of Harm: A Response to Sousa, Holbrook and Piazza”, Cognition 113(1) (2009): 93–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simone Ullrich, David P. Farrington, Jeremy W. Coid, “Dimensions of DSM-IV Personality Disorders and Life-Success”, Journal of Personality Disorders 21(6) (2007): 657–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kathleen D. Vohs, Jonathan W. Schooler, “The Value of Believing in Free Will Encouraging a Belief in Determinism Increases Cheating”, Psychological Science 19(1) (2008): 49–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephen C.P. Wong, Robert D. Hare, Guidelines for a Psychopathy Treatment Program (Toronto, ON, Canada, Multi-Health Systems, 2005).

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Stephen Morse and all the other participants at the workshop “Law and Neuroscience—The Work of Stephen Morse” for inspiration and insightful criticism of our paper. Many thanks also to Helen Beebee and the AHRC Science and Culture Awards for the initial opportunity to explore the topic. For helpful comments on the draft, we would like to thank Jan-Hendrik Heinrichs, Emily Williamson and the anonymous reviewers at Criminal Law and Philosophy.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marion Godman.

Additional information

Authors are listed in alphabetical order and contributed equally to this work.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Godman, M., Jefferson, A. On Blaming and Punishing Psychopaths. Criminal Law, Philosophy 11, 127–142 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-014-9340-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-014-9340-3

Keywords

Navigation